Skip to main content

Variables vs. Parameters in the Interpretation of Natural Language

  • Conference paper
  • First Online:
  • 577 Accesses

Part of the book series: Lecture Notes in Computer Science ((LNAI,volume 12331))

Abstract

This paper compares two systems of functional type logic that have been applied to the analysis of meaning composition in natural language: Montague’s Intensional Logic IL and its extensional substratum Ty2 of two-sorted type theory. The two systems differ in their treatment of reference and quantification over indices (like possible worlds or times): whereas the denotations of IL-formulae (inter alia) depend on indices as parameters, their Ty2-counterparts contain explicit free and bound variables for them. Building on earlier results, it is argued that, appearances to the contrary, the two systems are largely equivalent; that any differences in expressivity are irrelevant to said applications; and that the equivalence also extends to variations of the systems that make use of multiple indices (as in mixed systems of modal and temporal interpretation) or additional dimensions (as in standard accounts of context dependence).

The first two sections are based on [32] and cover the material the second author presented at his invited LENLS lecture; the results in the third section had also been hinted at in that presentation, but were only obtained by a joint effort of both authors well after the LENLS conference. We would like to thank the LENLS audience for an interesting discussion following the presentation and the editors for providing an opportunity to publish our work.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   39.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD   54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    With the variability of the underlying Logical Space of possibilities, the intensions are generalizations of Kripke’s [17] possible worlds, as propagated in [19].

  2. 2.

    The \(\lambda \)-operator indicates functional abstraction: \([\lambda x. \dots \ x \ \dots ]\) is that function f that assigns \(\dots \ u \ \dots \) to any u in its domain D (which is left implicit); given the set-theoretic account of functions we thus have:

    $$ [\lambda x. \dots \ x \ \dots ] \ = \ \{(u,v) \vert u \in D \ \& \ v = \dots \ u \dots \}.$$
  3. 3.

    Following [20], the sets \(\textit{Con}_{(s,b)}\) are usually referred to as \(\textit{Con}_b\), which we feel is confusing (given their interpretation) and moreover leads to complications when it comes to comparing IL and Ty2.

  4. 4.

    See [20, p. 387] and [9, p. 15] for other, less transparent ways of defining conjunction.

  5. 5.

    It ought to be mentioned that there is every reason to believe that Montague had been aware of Theorem (6), given the very design of IL.

  6. 6.

    In fact, it is almost that fragment, except for a little twist concerning constants occurring without index argument; cf. [30, p. 75].

  7. 7.

    Tautologies are among the obvious exceptions.

  8. 8.

    Hint: (7-a) and (8-a) boil down to a cardinality condition on \(D_s\); and the \(^*\)-counterpart of (8-b) is:

    • \((\lambda F^{((s,t),t)}. \ (\lambda \upsilon ^s_0. \ ( \lambda p^{(s,t)}. \ (p(\upsilon ^s_0) \ = F)))) \ (\lambda p. p(\upsilon ^s_0)).\)

  9. 9.

    The classic elimination algorithm from [4, p. 189] cannot be applied directly because it outputs terms of types outside \(\textit{IT}^+\). Thanks are due to Oleg Kiselyov for bringing up the question during the discussion following the LENLS presentation.

  10. 10.

    The syntactic variable t indicates the surface position from which the underlying noun plush toys has been moved and corresponds to the \(\lambda \)-bound Ty2-variable P in (13-b). See [10, p. 199f.] for an early formulation (and a different motivation) of such an analysis.

  11. 11.

    \(\chi '\), too, would have to be subjected to a meaning postulate in order to make sure it denotes a choice function \(\chi \), i.e. that \(w\in \chi (p)\) whenever \(p \ne \emptyset \).

  12. 12.

    The exact nature of the representation relation between contexts and indices varies across different versions of two-dimensional semantics and need not concern us here.

  13. 13.

    Cf. [15, p. 510], where the ban is presented as a descriptive observation on English and related languages. The more natural interpretation, following [18], takes it to be a defining criterion for context-dependence: unlike indices, contexts comprise those denotation-determining factors that cannot be shifted.

  14. 14.

    Here we slightly simplify matters: contexts are usually taken to contain more components than indices (cf. [14]); alternatively, they may be taken to be fully specified (utterance) situations (cf. [18]). In any case, these complications are orthogonal to our concerns.

  15. 15.

    The reasoning runs parallel to the proof Corollary (50b) in [16, Sec. 2.6]; see the next sub-section for this connection.

  16. 16.

    The (contextual) truth conditions of (23) are captured by equating index time \(t_0\) and context time \(t^*\) in (24), which still need to be kept apart to account for embedded occurrences of (23).

  17. 17.

    Apart from that a further result was proved to the effect that denotational equivalence holds across all types at diagonal points; obviously, this result is also covered by (27).

  18. 18.

    The ‘Y’ stands for ‘Yanovich’ on whose account [29] of backwards-looking operators (25) and (26) are based.

References

  1. Bäuerle, R.: Pragmatisch-semantische Aspekte der NP-Interpretation. In: Faust, M., Harweg, R., Lehfeldt, W., Wienold, G. (eds.) Allgemeine Sprachwissenschaft, Sprachtypologie und Textlinguistik, pp. 121–131. Narr, Tübingen (1983)

    Google Scholar 

  2. Carnap, R.: Meaning and Necessity. University of Chicago Press, Chicago (1947)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  3. Church, A.: A formulation of the simple theory of types. J. Symb. Log. 5(2), 56–68 (1940)

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  4. Curry, H.B., Feys, R.: Combinatory Logic, vol. I. North-Holland Publishing Company, Amsterdam (1958)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  5. Davidson, D.: On saying that. Synthese 19, 130–146 (1968)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  6. Frege, G.: Function und Begriff. Pohle, Jena (1891)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  7. Frege, G.: Über Sinn und Bedeutung. Zeitschrift für Philosophie und philosophische Kritik NF 100(1), 25–50 (1892)

    Google Scholar 

  8. Friedman, J., Warren, D.S.: \(\lambda \)-normal forms in an intensional logic for English. Studia Logica XXXIX(2–3), 311–324 (1980)

    Google Scholar 

  9. Gallin, D.: Intensional and Higher-order Modal Logic. North-Holland Pub. Company, Amsterdam (1975)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  10. Groenendijk, J., Stokhof, M.: Semantic analysis of WH-complements. Linguist. Philos. 5(2), 175–233 (1982)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  11. Heim, I., Kratzer, A.: Semantics in Generative Grammar. Blackwell Publishers Ltd., Oxford (1998)

    Google Scholar 

  12. Henkin, L.: A theory of propositional types. Fundamenta Mathematicae 52(3), 323–334 (1963)

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  13. Kamp, H.: Formal properties of “now”. Theoria 37, 227–273 (1971)

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  14. Kaplan, D.: On the logic of demonstratives. J. Philos. Log. 8, 81–98 (1979)

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  15. Kaplan, D.: Demonstratives. An essay on the semantics, logic, metaphysics and epistemology of demonstratives and other indexicals. In: Almog, J., Perry, J., Wettstein, H. (eds.) Themes from Kaplan, pp. 481–563. Oxford University Press, Oxford (1989)

    Google Scholar 

  16. Köpping, J., Zimmermann, T.E.: Looking backwards in type logic. Inquiry (forthcoming)

    Google Scholar 

  17. Kripke, S.A.: Semantical considerations on modal logic. Acta Philosophica Fennica 16, 83–94 (1963)

    MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  18. Lewis, D.K.: Index, context, and content. In: Kanger, S., Öhman, S. (eds.) Philosophy and Grammar, pp. 79–100. Reidel, Dordrecht (1980)

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  19. Montague, R.: Pragmatics. In: Klibansky, R. (ed.) Contemporary Philosophy. Volume I: Logic and the Foundations of Mathematics, pp. 102–122. La Nuova Italia Editrice, Florence (1968)

    Google Scholar 

  20. Montague, R.: Universal Grammar. Theoria 36(3), 373–398 (1970)

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  21. Montague, R.: The proper treatment of quantification in ordinary English. In: Hintikka, J., Moravcsik, J., Suppes, P. (eds.) Approaches to Natural Language, pp. 221–242. Reidel, Dordrecht (1973)

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  22. Parsons, T.: Frege’s hierarchies of indirect senses and the paradox of analysis. In: French, P., Uehling, T., Wettstein, H. (eds.) Midwest Studies in Philosophy VI: The Foundations of Analytic Philosophy, pp. 37–57. University of Minnesota Press, Minneapolis (1981)

    Google Scholar 

  23. Percus, O.: Constraints on some other variables in syntax. Nat. Lang. Semant. 9(1), 173–229 (2000)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  24. Saarinen, E.: Backwards-looking operators in tense logic and in natural language. In: Hintikka, J., Niiniluoto, I., Saarinen, E. (eds.) Essays on Mathematical and Philosophical Logic, pp. 341–367. Reidel, Dordrecht (1979)

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  25. Scott, D.: Advice on modal logic. In: Lambert, K. (ed.) Philosophical Problems in Logic, pp. 143–173. Reidel, Dordrecht (1970)

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  26. Stalnaker, R.: A theory of conditionals. In: Rescher, N. (ed.) Studies in Logical Theory, pp. 41–55. Blackwell, Oxford (1968)

    Google Scholar 

  27. Stalnaker, R.: The problem of logical omniscience, I. Synthese 89, 425–440 (1991)

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  28. Stalnaker, R.: The problem of logical omniscience, II. In: Context and Content, pp. 255–273. Oxford University Press, Oxford (1999)

    Google Scholar 

  29. Yanovich, I.: Expressive power of “now” and “then” operators. J. Log. Lang. Inf. 24(1), 65–93 (2015)

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  30. Zimmermann, T.E.: Intensional logic and two-sorted type theory. J. Symb. Log. 54(1), 65–77 (1989)

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  31. Zimmermann, T.E.: Fregean compositionality. In: Ball, D., Rabern, B. (eds.) The Science of Meaning, pp. 276–305. Oxford University Press, Oxford (2018)

    Google Scholar 

  32. Zimmermann, T.E.: Representing intensionality: variables vs. parameters. In: Gutzmann, D., Matthewson, L., Meier, C., Rullmann, H., Zimmermann, T.E. (eds.) The Wiley Blackwell Companion to Semantics. Oxford, Wiley (forthcoming)

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Thomas Ede Zimmermann .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2020 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this paper

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this paper

Köpping, J., Zimmermann, T.E. (2020). Variables vs. Parameters in the Interpretation of Natural Language. In: Sakamoto, M., Okazaki, N., Mineshima, K., Satoh, K. (eds) New Frontiers in Artificial Intelligence. JSAI-isAI 2019. Lecture Notes in Computer Science(), vol 12331. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-58790-1_11

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-58790-1_11

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Cham

  • Print ISBN: 978-3-030-58789-5

  • Online ISBN: 978-3-030-58790-1

  • eBook Packages: Computer ScienceComputer Science (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics