Skip to main content

Relevance in the Law

  • Chapter
  • First Online:

Part of the book series: Logic, Epistemology, and the Unity of Science ((LEUS,volume 20))

Abstracts

If the law embodies a culture of implicity, logic’s orientation displays an enthusiasm for the explicit. Logicians put a premium on precision and exactitude, and they reserve a special place for definitions, both biconditional and implicit. It has a considerable bearing on the two-solitudes phenomenon that, for over a century, mainstream logic has been part of mathematics. As the name suggests, mathematical logic serves the interests of mathematics, and its methods are themselves imbued with richly mathematical content. Certainly it would take only the most monomaniacal of mathematical logicians to propose that the logic of legal reasoning is a Boolean lattice or that the secrets of legal relevance are best revealed in a possible worlds semantics for relevant logic. But logic has come a long way in the past 40 years, spurred by developments in computer science, AI, logic programming, dynamic and deontic logics and logics of practical reasoning in which there have been repeated attempts to reconnect with human reasoning in real-life situations. Any number of successes (or partial successes) have already been claimed by theorists working in what collectively has been called the New Logic. It is here that the two-solitudes phenomenon makes least sense, and it is here that prospects of rapprochement are at their best. In companion articles, we have recently explored the logical structure of probability in legal reasoning, as well as the abductive character of the criminal proof standard; In each case, we have attempted to bring to bear upon these legal issues resources from the New Logic. In the present essay we try our hand at relevance.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   149.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD   199.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD   199.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    (1997), 9 C. R. (5th) 1 (S. C. C.).

  2. 2.

    R. v. Starr, [2000] 2 (S. C. C.) 144 at para. 242: “… it will be of great assistance for a jury if the trial judge situates the reasonable doubt standard approximately between [the] two standards.”

  3. 3.

    To forestall confusion, what logicians recognize as “implicit” definitions, legal scholars would recognize as explicit definitions. A case in point is the implicit definition of the definite article afforded by Russell’s theory of descriptions ([Russell, 1905]). The theory defines ‘the’ by mapping sentences containing ‘the’ to equivalent sentences not containing ‘the’. Definitions implicit in this sense, Russell also calls “contextual”.

  4. 4.

    Whether it be Frege’s logicism (Frege, 1879]), which was an attempt to reduce mathematics to pure logic, or Brouwer’s intuitionism ([Brouwer, 1975]), which was an attempt to refine logic’s capacity to elucidate the character of constructivist reasoning in mathematics.

  5. 5.

    For example, the use of mathematical induction in the proofs of many of the most important metatheorems.

  6. 6.

    For example, in a variation of the system known as First-Degree Entailment ([Routley and Routley, 1973, 1985], [Priest, 1987]).

  7. 7.

    Prefiguring the probalistic concept is the view that relevance is a causal relation ([Stephen, 1876]). While rejected by legal theorists (Ilbert, 1960, p. 13), a causal conception of relevance flourishes in the present-day theory of Agenda Relevance (Gabbay and Woods, 2003).

  8. 8.

    On this reading, probabilistic relevance has an unmistakable Wigmorean flavour. According to Wigmore, an “identiary fact” is relevant if it can be used to prove or counter a case’s factum probandum (Wigmore, 1983, 1104–1195).

  9. 9.

    See here (James, 1941): “Why exclude any data which if admitted would change the apparent probabilities and hence serve, even to a slight degree, to aid the search for truth? Justice Holmes suggested one answer, it is ‘a concession to the shortness of life’ – and perhaps to the shortness of purse of harassed litigants. If any and all evidence may be admissible which … would operate to any extent to alter the apparent probability of some material proposition, the field of judicial inquiry in most cases would be unlimited. Trials would come to an end only by the exhaustion of lawyers’ ingenuity or client’s money, and the trial judge or jury might be overwhelmed and bewildered by the multiplicity of collaterial issues”.

  10. 10.

    See also the Australian Law Reform Commission Report 26, Volume 1, Evidence (1985), section 11, Relevance (ALRC, 1985): “It may be concluded that two people, or groups, may have different, but equally rational, views of the relevance of a piece of evidence, depending on their prior experience and conceptions. In a jury case, the experience of jurors may be quite different from that of the trial judge, and consequently their assessment of ‘relevance’ and probative force may vary from his. Therefore, so long as a juror’s assessment of the probabilities in the case might be rationally affected by the proferred evidence, then it is relevant. The trial judge may be doubtful about the probative force of the evidence and yet should admit it because the jury may rationally assess probative force differently from the way he does. That does not mean the jury is acting irrationally or emotionally, but only that they are utilizing their own experience to supply and evaluate appropriate hypotheses of proof.”

  11. 11.

    In the legal literature, the having-a-bearing notion of relevance is developed in, e.g., Wills (1938).

  12. 12.

    It is interesting that notwithstanding his earlier work on topical relevance, Walton’s discussion of relevance in the law in Walton, (2002) overlooks the factor of materiality. (It is mentioned in passing on p. 20 as one of Wigmore’s conditions on relevance.)

  13. 13.

    The tightness of the tie of relevant to materiality is resisted by some writers. According to (Eggleston, 1970, p. 59), “[t]o attempt to confine the evidence to transactions or facts in issue and the surrounding details of those transactions and facts is to exclude some evidence of strong probative value. Unless the definition of ‘surrounding details’ is widened in such a way as to include any facts having logical probative value, then the expression becomes meaningless.”

  14. 14.

    A new edition, under the title Evidence in Trials at Common Law is edited by Peter Tiller, whose substantial footnotes are a valuable commentary on the work (Wigmore, 1983). Critics of Wigmore include (Twining, 1985). See also Tillers’ commentary in Wigmore, (1983).

  15. 15.

    The notorious claim of Sextus Empiricus that all valid arguments are question-begging arises from confusing question-begging with circularity.

  16. 16.

    If we tell you that we greatly disagree with him, we are not confronting you, since we are not expressing this agreement with you, and we are not confronting him because we are not even addressing him.

  17. 17.

    A recent example of how the excessive dialecticization of concepts can lead us astray is Douglas Walton’s demonstration of the difference between probability and plausibility. It is part of the dialectical character of probability that “if you claim that a proposition is probably true, then there is a burden of proof attached …” (Walton, 2002, p. 110). On the other hand, “if you only [sic] claim that a proposition is plausibly true, there is no burden of proof attached.” (p. 110). Since “the dialectical requirements for the reasonable acceptance of the two kinds of speech acts are quite difference” (110), then the two concepts are not the same. We think that we are not alone in seeing two difficulties with this account. First, whether or not one create a burden of proof for oneself in uttering “P’ depends on whether in so doing one asserts something challengable. (“I feel depressed” and “My name is Johan van den Boten” make assertions, but typically they are not challengeable.) Walton thinks that it is intrinsic to utterances of “Probably P” that a challengeable assertion is made, and that intrinsic to utterances of “Plausibly P” that no such assertion is made. Nowhere in the empirical record of actual speech is any such suggestion upheld. But, secondly, even if Walton were right about this, it would have done nothing to demonstrate that when “possibly” occurs in these contexts, it is, as Walton also avers, statistical probability that is at work. (See below).

  18. 18.

    The same is also true of a slender minority of lawyers. Alluding to FRE 401’s characterization of probabilistic relevance, (Dejnoska, 2004) has it that “FRE 401 … leaves probability undefined. And if FRE 401 is uninterpreted, it is useless ... The whole question is what probability is in the first place. The fundamental task of probability is to answer that question. Aristotle, Venn, Keynes, Ramsey, Mises, and Reichenbach all agree that probability is the obscure and basic notion needing explanation. But FRE 401 goes in the opposite direction and defines relevance in terms of probability”.

  19. 19.

    Keynes’ approach to probability is discernible in Lempert (1977) discussion of logical relevance.

  20. 20.

    By these lights, it is a considerable virtue of (Walton, 2002) to emphasize the dominance of plausibilities over aleatory probabilities in legal proceedings. See Chapters 4 and 6.

  21. 21.

    See also Learned Hand: “[Evidence’s] relevancy really did not, and indeed could not, demand that it be conclusive; most convictions result from the accumulation of bits of proof which taken singly would not be enough in the mind of a fair-minded person. All that is necessary, and all that is possible, is that each bit may have enough rational connection with the issue to be considered a factor contributing to an answer.” (US v Pugliese 153 F 2d 497, 500 (1945))

  22. 22.

    For helpful advice and information, or other forms of support, we warmly thank Dale Jacquette, Ori Simchen, Andrew Jones, Steven Wexler, Andrew Irvine, S. Bradley Armstrong QC, C.L. Woods and K.A. Woods. Research for this essay was supported by the Engineering and Physical Sciences Research Council of the United Kingdom and the Faculty of Arts in the University of British Columbia. We are most grateful for this assistance.

Bibliography

  • Anderson AR and Belnap N Jr (1975). Entailment: The Logic of Relevance and Necessity, vol.1. Princeton NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Australian Law Reform Commission Report 26, volume 1, Evidence, 11. Relevance, 1985.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barth EM and Krabbe ECW (1982). From Axiom to Dialogue: A Philosophical Study of Logic and Argumentation. Berlin and New York: de Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bowles G (1990). Propositional relevance. Informal Logic XII, 65–77.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brouwer LEJ (1975). In Heyting A (ed) Collected Works 1. Philosophy and Foundations of Mathematics. Amsterdam: North-Holland.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cohen LJ (1977). The Probable and the Provable. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cross R and Wilkins N (1964). An Outline of the Law of Evidence. London: Butterworths.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dejnozka J (1996). Logical relevance, presented to Richard D. Friedman’s Advanced Evidence Seminar, University of Michigan School of Law, April 22, 1996; edited for the web May 8, 2004. Available online at http://www.members.tripod.com/~Jan_Dejnozka/

  • Demolombe R and Jones AJT (1999). Sentences of the kind ‘sentence P is about topic T’. In Ohlbach HJ and Reyle U (eds) Logic, Language and Reasoning. Dordrecht and Boston: Kluwer, pp. 115–133.

    Google Scholar 

  • Eggleston R (1970). The relationship between relevance and admissibility in the law of evidence. In Glass HH (ed) Seminars on Evidence. Sydney: Law Book Co.

    Google Scholar 

  • Federal Rules of Evidence, Ithaca, NY: Legal Information Institute, Cornell University, 1999. Updated version at http://www.law.cornell.edu/rules/fre/overview.html.

  • Feteris E (1999). Fundamentals of Legal Argumentation. Dordrecht and Boston: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frege G (1879). In van Heijenoort J (ed) Begriffsschrift, A Formula Language, Modeled Upon That of Arithmetic for Pure Thought. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gabbay DM and Woods J (2001a). Non-cooperation in dialogue logic. Synthese 127, 161–186.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gabbay DM and Woods J (2001b). More on non-cooperation in dialogue logic. Logic Journal of the IGPL 9, 321–339.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gabbay DM and Woods J (2001c). The new logic. Logic Journal of the IGPL 9, 157–190.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gabbay DM and Woods J (2003a). Agenda Relevance: A Study in Formal Pragmatics. Amsterdam: Elsevier/North-Holland.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gabbay DM and Woods J (2005). Logic and the law: Crossing the lines of discipline, Φ News 7, 4–45.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gabbay DM and Woods J (2006a). Probability in the law, to appear in 2006a.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gabbay DM and Woods J (2006b). The proof standard at the criminal bar: an abductive paradox, to appear in 2006b.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gabbay DM and Woods J (2006c). Should we legalize Bayes’ Theorem?, to appear in 2006c.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gigerenzer G and Selten R (2001) Rethinking rationality. In Gigerenzer G and Selten R (eds) The Adaptive Toolbox. Cambridge MA: MIT Press, pp. 1–12.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harman G (1986). Change in View: Principles of Reasoning. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hintikka J (1987). The fallacy of fallacies. Argumentation 1, 211–238, 1987.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hintikka J, Halonen I and Mutanen A (2002). Interrogative logic as a general theory of reasoning. In Gabbay DM, Johnson RH, Ohlbach HJ and Woods J (eds) Handbook of the Logic of Argument and Inference: The Turn Towards the Practical. Amsterdam: North Holland, pp. 295–337.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ilbert C (1960). Evidence. Encyclopedia Britannica, 11th ed., 10, 11–21.

    Google Scholar 

  • Johnson RH (2000). Manifest Rationality: A Pragmatic Theory of Argument. Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Keynes JM (1971). The Collected Writings of John Maynard Keynes. New York: St. Martin’s Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lempert R (1977). A Modern Approach to Evidence. Minneapolis Minn: West Publishing Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • MacKenzie J (1990). Four dialogue systems. Studia Logica XLIX, 567–583.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Murphy P (2000). Murphy on Evidence, 7th ed. London: Blackstone.

    Google Scholar 

  • Paciocco D and Stuesser L (2002). The Law of Evidence, 3rd ed. Toronto: Irwin Law.

    Google Scholar 

  • Priest G (1987). In Contradiction: A Study of the Transconsistent, Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic.

    Google Scholar 

  • Routley R and Routley V (1972). The semantics of first degree entailment. Noûs 6, 335–395.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Routley R and Routley V (1985). Negation and contradiction. Rifista Columbiana de Matemáticas 19, 201–231.

    Google Scholar 

  • Russell B (1905). On denoting. Mind 14, 479–493.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sperber D and Wilson D (1995). Relevance: Communication and Cognition, 2nd ed. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stanovich KA (1999). Who is Rational? Studies of Individual Differences in Reasoning. Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stephen J (1927). Digest of the Law of Evidence. St. Paul, MN: West Publishing Co. Originally published in 1876.

    Google Scholar 

  • Strong JW (1999). MacCormick on Evidence, 5th ed. St. Paul MN: West Group.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thayer JB (1927). A Preliminary Treatise on Evidence at the Common Law. Cambridge, MA: Legal Essays. Originally published in 1898.

    Google Scholar 

  • Twining W (1985). Theories of Evidence: Bentham and Wigmore. London: Weidenfeld and Nicolson.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Eemeren FH and Grootendorst R (1984). Speech Acts in Argumentative Discussions: A Theoretical Model for the Analysis of Discussions Directed Towards Solving Conflicts of Opinion. Dordrecht: Foris/Berlin.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Eemeren FH and Grootendoest R (1992a). Argumentation, Communication and Fallacies: A Pragma-Dialectical Perspective. Hillsdale, NJ and London: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Eemeren FH and Grootendorst R (1992b). Relevance reviewed; The case of argumentum ad hominem. Argumentation 6 (2), 141–159.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • van Eemeren FH and Grootendorst R (2004). A Systematic Theory of Argumentation: The Pragma-Dialectical Approach. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walton D (1982). Topical Relevance in Argumentation. Amsterdam: John Benjamins.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walton D (19945), A Pragmatic Theory of Fallacy. Tuscaloosa: University of Alabama Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walton D and Krabbe ECW (1995). Commitment in Dialogue, Basic Concepts of Interpersonal Reasoning. Albany, NY: State University of New York Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walton D (1996). Argument Structure: A Pragmatic Theory. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walton D (2002). Legal Argumentation and Evidence. University Park, PA: The Pennsylvania State University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walton D (2003). Relevance in Argumentation. Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wigmore JH (1940). Evidence in Trials at Common Law (Wigmore on Evidence). Boston: Little Brown.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wigmore JH (1983). A Kaleidoscope of Justice: Containing Authentic Accounts of Trial Scenes From All Times and Climes. Littleton, Colo: F.B. Rothman.

    Google Scholar 

  • W. Wills (1938). The Law of Evidence, 3rd ed. London: Stevens & Sons.

    Google Scholar 

  • Woods J (1994). Sunny prospects for relevance? In Johnson RH and Blair JA (eds) New Essays in Informal Logic, edited by. Windsor, ON: Informal Logic Press, pp. 93–104.

    Google Scholar 

  • Woods J (2004). The Death of Argument: Fallacies in Agent-Based Reasoning. Dordrecht and Boston: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Woods J and Hansen HV (1997). Hintikka on Aristotle’s fallacies. Synthese 113, 217–239.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Woods J and Hansen HV (2001). The subtleties of Aristotle’s non-cause. Logique et Analyse 176, 395–415.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Dov M. Gabbay .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2010 Springer Science+Business Media B.V.

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Gabbay, D.M., Woods, J. (2010). Relevance in the Law. In: Gabbay, D., Canivez, P., Rahman, S., Thiercelin, A. (eds) Approaches to Legal Rationality. Logic, Epistemology, and the Unity of Science, vol 20. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-90-481-9588-6_12

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics