Skip to main content
Log in

An everyday account of witnessing

  • Original article
  • Published:
AI & SOCIETY Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This paper presents a discussion of an everyday ontology of witnessing drawing on the writings of Martin Heidegger, cognitive science and presence research. We begin by defining witnessing: to witness we must be present; and that which is witnessed must be available. Witnessing is distinguished from perceiving in that it implies and requires a record (a representation) of what has been perceived. Presence and availability are (relatively) uncontroversial but finding a place for representation, which is a classically dualistic concept, in an ontological account potentially presents difficulties. We address this problem by recognising that being available, ready-to-hand and proximal can also serve to represent the very thing being witnessed.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. A quick word of explanation on Dasein before we continue. The German word Dasein (lit. being-there) is traditionally left un-translated and is taken to stand for ‘human being’ and is usually printed in a different font–like this. Being undefined, Dasein is recognized as being contingent or seen as a ‘placeholder’ for ‘who’ and ‘what’ we are.

  2. To describe present-at-hand as unavailable is a simplification but one which I do not believe misleads. Dreyfus (1991), for example, in his commentary on Heidegger’s Being and Time, distinguishes between available and unavailable as being aspects of readiness-to-hand and uses the term occurrentness to describe being present-at-hand (occurrentness also having two states or modes). While these are important distinctions I do not think that they are germane to the current discussion here.

  3. The everyday use of the term intentionality meaning intending, intentions or motivations such as the intention to drink a cup of tea should be distinguished from the concept’s philosophical sense.

  4. Heidegger’s ontology requires us to regard all things in the world as beings–e.g. chair-beings, book-beings, macbook-pro-beings, pencil-beings, cup-of-coffee-beings. While this is, to most people, unfamiliar it does remove the fundamental Cartesian assumption of subject and object. Instead, we encounter other beings but this is not to suggest that these beings have intelligence or sentience but that an everyday ontological examination of chairs would be into their chair-ness for me. The everydayness of a chair is its availability for sitting on, or standing on, or for barricading a door with and so on.

  5. Lewin (1936) referred to affordances as Aufforderungscharakter or invitation character.

References

  • Baños RM, Botella C, Alcañiz M, Liaño V (2004) Immersion and emotion: their impact on the sense of presence. Cyberpsychol Behav 7(6):734–741

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bartlett FC (1932) Remembering. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Biocca F (1997) The cyborg’s dilemma: progressive embodiment in virtual environments. J Comput Mediat Commun 3(2)

  • Braun KA, Ellis R, Loftus EF (2002) Make my memory: how advertising can change our memories of the past. Psychol Mark 19(1):1–23

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brentano F (1995) Psychology from an Empirical Standpoint (trans: Rancurello AC, Terrell DB, McAlister LL). Routledge, London

  • Brogni A, Slater M, Steed A (2003) More breaks less presence. In: Proceedings of 6th annual international workshop on presence

  • Burt CDB, Kemp S, Conway M (2001) What happens if you retest autobiographical memory 10 years on? Mem Cogn 29(1):127–136

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chemero A (2009) Radical embodied cognitive science. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark A (1997a) The dynamical challenge. Cogn Sci 21(4):461–481

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clark A (1997b) Being there: putting brain, body and world together again. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark A, Grush R (1999) Towards a cognitive robotics. Adapt Behav 7(1):5–16

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cohen G (1989) Memory in the real world. Lawrence Erlbaum Associates, East Sussex

    Google Scholar 

  • Cole M (1996) Cultural psychology. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Conway MA (2001) Sensory-perceptual episodic memory and its context: autobiographical memory. Philos Trans R Soc Lond B 356:1375–1384

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Conway MA (2003) Commentary: cognitive-affective mechanisms and processes in autobiographical memory. Memory 11(2):217–224

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • de Souza CS (1993) The semiotic engineering of user interface languages. Int J Man Mach Stud 39:753–773

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • de Souza CS, Prates RO, Carey T (2000) Missing and declining affordances: are these appropriate concepts? J Brazilian Comput Soc 7(1):26–34

    Google Scholar 

  • Dreyfus H (1991) Being-in-the-world: a commentary on Heidegger’s being and time division I. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Dreyfus H (1996) The current relevance of Merleau-Ponty’s phenomenology of embodiment. Electron J Anal Philos. http://ejap.louisiana.edu/EJAP/1996.spring/dreyfus.1996.spring.html (last retrieved 11.01.2011)

  • Dreyfus H (2002) Intelligence without representation–Merleau-Ponty’s critique of mental representation: the relevance of phenomenology to scientific explanation. Phenomenol Cogn Sci 1(4):367–383

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dreyfus HL, Wrathall MA (2005) Introduction. In: Dreyfus HL, Wrathall MA (eds) A companion to Heidegger. Blackwell, Malden

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Fencott C (1999) Presence and the content of virtual environments. In: Proceedings of 2nd international workshop on presence. Essex, UK

  • Freeman WJ (1999) Societies of brain. Laurence Elbaum Associates, Hillsdale

    Google Scholar 

  • Freeman J, Lessiter J, Keogh E, Bond FW, Chapman K (2004) Relaxation island: virtual, and really relaxing. In: Proceedings of 7th international workshop on presence, pp 67–72

  • Gaver WW (1991) Technological affordances. In: Proceedings of CHI ‘91. NY: ACM

  • Gaver WW (1992) The affordances of media space for collaboration.In: Proceedings of CSCW’92. NY: ACM Press, pp 17–24

  • Gibson JJ (1986) The ecological approach to visual perception. Houghton Mifflin, Boston

    Google Scholar 

  • Grèzes J, Decety J (2002) Does visual perception of object afford action? Evidence from a neuroimaging study. Neuropsychologia 40:212–222

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harman G (2002) Tool being: Heidegger and the metaphysics of objects. Open Court, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Hartson HR (2003) Cognitive, physical, sensory and functional affordances in interaction design. Behav Inf Technol 22(5):315–338

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger M (1927/1962) Being and time. (trans: Macquarrie J, Robinson E). Harper Collins, New York

  • Heidegger M (1985) History of the concept of time. Indiana University Press, Bloomington

    Google Scholar 

  • Held RM, Durlach NI (1992) Telepresence. Presence: Teleoperators Virtual Environ 1(1):109–112

    Google Scholar 

  • IJsselsteijn WA, de Ridder H, Freeman J, Avons SE (2000) Presence: concept, determinants and measurement. In: Proceedings of the SPIE, 3959. Human vision and electronic imaging V, San Jose, USA, 24–27 January 2000

  • Lessiter J, Freeman J, Keogh E, Davidoff J (2001) A cross-media presence questionnaire: the ITC-sense of presence inventory. Presence: Teleoperators Virtual Environ 10:282–298

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewin K (1936) Principles of topological psychology. McGraw-Hill, New York

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Loftus EF (1975) Leading questions and the eye-witness report. Cogn Psychol 7:560–572

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Loftus EF (1979) The malleability of human memory. Am Sci 67:312–320

    Google Scholar 

  • Loftus EF, Donders K, Hoffman HG, Schooler JW (1989) Creating new memories that are quickly accessed and confidently held. Mem Cogn 17:607–616

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lombard M, Ditton T (1997) At the heart of it all: the concept of presence. J Comput Mediat Commun 3(2)

  • Merleau-Ponty M (1945/1962) Phenomenology of perception. (trans: Smith C) Routledge Classics, London

  • Neisser U (1978) Memory: what are the important questions? In: Gruneberg MM, Morris P, Sykes R (eds) Practical aspects of memory. Academic Press, London, pp 3–24

    Google Scholar 

  • Norman DA (1988) The psychology of everyday things. Basic Books, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Norman DA (1999) Affordance, conventions and design. Interactions, May+June, pp 38–42

  • Nunez D, Blake EH (2006) Learning, experience and cognitive factors in the presence experiences of gamers: an exploratory relational study. Presence: Teleoperators Virtual Environ 15(4):373–380

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Revonsuo A (2006) Inner presence. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Riva G, Waterworth JA, Waterworth EH (2004) The layers of presence: a bio-cultural approach to understanding presence in natural and mediated environments. Cyberpsychol Behav 7(4):405–419

    Google Scholar 

  • Schloerb DW (1995) A quantitative measure of telepresence. Presence: Teleoperators Virtual Environ 4:64–80

    Google Scholar 

  • Schubert TW, Friedmann F, Regenbrecht HT (2001) The experience of presence: factor analytic insights. Presence: Teleoperators Virtual Environ 10(3):266–281

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Slater M (2003) A note on presence terminology. Presence connect 3(3). Available from: http://openpdf.info/ebook/a-note-on-presence-terminology-pdf.html (last retrieved 15.12.2010)

  • Stoffregen TA (2000) Affordances and events. Ecol Psychol 12:1–28

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Turner P (2005) Affordance as context. Interact Comput 17(6):787–800

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Turner P (2007) The intentional basis of presence. In: Proceedings of 10th international workshop on presence, pp 127–134

  • Turner P (2008a) Towards an account of intuitiveness. Behav Inf Technol 27(6):1–8

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Turner P (2008b) Being-with: a study of familiarity. Interact Comput 20:447–454

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Turvey MT (1992) Affordances and prospective control: an outline of the ontology. Ecol Psychol 4:173–187

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Warren WH (1984) Perceiving affordances: visual guidance of stair-climbing. J Exp Psychol Hum Percept Perform 10:683–703

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Waterworth JA, Waterworth EL (2001) Focus, sensus and locus: the three dimensions of virtual experience. Cyberpsychol Behav 4(2):203–213

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Witmer BG, Singer MJ (1998) Measuring presence in virtual environments: a presence questionnaire. Presence: Teleoperators Virtual Environ 7(3):225–240

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zahorik P, Jenison RL (1998) Presence as being-in-the-world. Presence: Teleoperators Virtual Environ 7:78–89

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

Sincere thanks to the reviewers of this paper and the editors of this special issue for their help in the preparation of this manuscript. Thanks also to Professor John Waterworth for his kind permission to reproduce Fig. 1.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Phil Turner.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Turner, P. An everyday account of witnessing. AI & Soc 27, 5–12 (2012). https://doi.org/10.1007/s00146-011-0323-9

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s00146-011-0323-9

Keywords

Navigation