Skip to main content
Log in

Electoral competition under costly policy implementation

  • Original Paper
  • Published:
Social Choice and Welfare Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This paper analyzes a unidimensional electoral competition model between two policy-motivated candidates, assuming that the elected candidate has to incur an idiosyncratic policy implementation cost. Think of this as the election of chairman in an academic department, a parent-teacher association, or a condominium association board, where the election winner perceives office holding as a cost, and not benefit. We prove that in such a game, a pure strategy Nash equilibrium is guaranteed to exist even when the policy implementation costs are heterogeneous, as long as they are not very large. We also provide the equilibrium characterization, comparative statics, and welfare analysis in the case of Euclidean preferences. In particular, we show that equilibrium strategies are divergent and in general not symmetric around the expected bliss point of the median voter. A higher policy implementation cost makes a candidate propose a more extreme policy, and lowers his electoral chances. Naturally, the voter’s welfare decreases when the candidates’ implementation costs increase.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. This policy implementation cost is somewhat similar to the private cost of providing a public good in the literature on voluntary provision of public goods (Bergstrom et al. 1986; Bliss and Nalebuff 1984; Andreoni 1988; Cornes and Sandler 1996). The novelty of this paper is that the public good (the policy in our setting) is assumed to be differentiated.

  2. Note that uniform distribution is excluded.

  3. Modeling electoral uncertainty with a prior distribution \(F\left( \cdot \right) \) is common in the political competition literature (see Martimort and Semenov 2008; Saporiti 2008).

  4. Assumption 1 is a differential version of strict log-concavity.

  5. While it is common in the electoral competition literature, the assumption of concavity is not universal and is realistic only in certain issues (such as in economic policies, for example). Kamada and Kojima (2014) analyze the implications of convex utility functions and show that equilibrium strategies diverge if and only if the voters’ utility function is sufficiently convex.

  6. As for the asymmetric case, Drouvelis et al. (2014) provide existence results when the median voter’s bliss point is uniformly distributed on a segment of the policy space.

  7. As far as the mixed equilibria are concerned, one can adjust the arguments of Saporiti (2008) because they do not depend on whether the value of holding office is positive or negative, and show that a mixed strategy equilibrium is guaranteed to exist for any parameterization of our model, considering, however, a bounded strategy space. Indeed, when a player’s strategy space is unbounded, the game need not admit an equilibrium in either the pure or mixed strategies even when the discontinuities in the payoff functions are “well behaved” (in that the conditions of known equilibrium existence theorems are satisfied; see, for example, Dasgupta and Maskin 1986; Reny 1999).

  8. Formally, these equilibria exist for \(\alpha _{1}<-\frac{\max \left[ C_{1},C_{2}\right] }{2}<\frac{\max \left[ C_{1},C_{2}\right] }{2}<\alpha _{2}\).

References

  • Andreoni J (1988) Privately provided public goods in a large economy: the limits of altruism. J Pub Econ 35:57–73

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ball R (1999) Discontinuity and nonexistence of equilibrium in the probabilistic spatial voting model. Soc Choice Welfare 16:533–555

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bergstrom TC, Blume LE, Varian HR (1986) On the private provision of public goods. J Publ Econ 29:25–49

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bernhardt D, Duggan J, Squintani F (2009) The case for responsible parties. Am Polit Sci Rev 103:570–587

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bilodeau M, Slivinski A (1996) Toilet cleaning and department chairing: volunteering a public service. J Publ Econ 59:299–308

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bliss C, Nalebuff B (1984) Dragon-slaying and ballroom dancing: the private supply of a public good. J Publ Econ 25:1–12

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Calvert RL (1985) Robustness of the multidimensional voting model: candidate motivations, uncertainty, and convergence. Am J Polit Sci 29:69–95

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cornes R, Sandler T (1996) The theory of externalities, public goods and club goods. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Dasgupta P, Maskin E (1986) The existence of equilibrium in discontinuous economic games, I: theory. Rev Econ Stud 53:1–26

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Debreu G (1952) A social equilibrium existence theorem. Proc Natl Acad Sci USA 38:886–893

  • Downs A (1957) An economic theory of democracy. Harper and Row, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Drouvelis M, Saporiti A, Vriend NJ (2014) Political motivations and electoral competition: equilibrium analysis and experimental evidence. Games Econ Behav 83:86–115

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Duggan J, Fey M (2005) Electoral competition with policy-motivated candidates. Games Econ Behav 51:490–522

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hinich M (1977) Equilibrium in spatial voting: the median voter result is an artifact. J Econ Theory 16:208–219

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hirsch AV, Shotts KW (2015) Competitive policy development. Am Econ Rev 105:1646–1664

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hotelling H (1929) Stability in competition. Econ J 39:41–57

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kamada Y, Kojima F (2014) Voter preferences, polarization, and electoral policies. Am Econ J Microecon 6:203–236

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Martimort D, Semenov A (2008) Ideological uncertainty and lobbying competition. J Publ Econ 92:456–481

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Messner M, Polborn MK (2004) Paying politicians. J Publ Econ 88:2423–2445

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Reny PJ (1999) On the existence of pure and mixed strategy nash equilibria in discontinuous games. Econometrica 67:1029–1056

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Roemer JE (1994) A theory of policy differentiation in single issue electoral politics. Soc Choice Welfare 11:355–380

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Roemer JE (1997) Political-economic equilibrium when parties represent constituents. Soc Choice Welfare 14:479–502

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Roemer JE (2001) Political competition. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Saporiti A (2008) Existence and uniqueness of nash equilibrium in electoral competition games: the hybrid case. J Publ Econ Theory 10(5):827–857

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wittman D (1977) Candidates with policy preferences: a dynamic model. J Econ Theory 14:180–189

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wittman D (1983) Candidate motivation: a synthesis of alternative theories. Am Polit Sci Rev 77:142–157

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wittman D (1990) Spatial strategies when candidates have policy preferences. In: Enelow J, Hinich M (eds) Advances in the spatial theory of voting. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Galina Zudenkova.

Additional information

The authors are grateful to Luis Corchón, Eckhard Janeba, Ignacio Ortuño Ortín, two anonymous referees, the associate editor, and seminar and conference participants at several institutions for their useful comments and suggestions. Zudenkova acknowledges financial support from the Karin–Islinger–Stiftung Foundation and Spanish Ministry of Science and Innovations (Project ECO2011-25203). The usual disclaimer applies.

Appendices

Appendix

Proof of Proposition 1

To prove the equilibrium existence, we define a restricted game. We define a positive number \(d=\max \{-k_{1},k_{2}\}\) and assume that candidate 1 is allowed to announce a policy in \([\alpha _{1},-d]\) and that candidate 2 is allowed to announce a policy in \([d,\alpha _{2}]\). The value \(k_{i}\ \)is given by \(v(\left| k_{i}-\alpha _{i}\right| )-C_{i}=v(\left| -k_{i}-\alpha _{i}\right| )\). It pins down the location beyond which candidate i would unambiguously decrease his payoff when approaching further his symmetrically located competitor. Assumption 2 guarantees that, for sufficiently small policy implementation costs: (a) a unique \(k_{i}\) exists for each i; (b) it is more moderate than i’s ideal policy; and (c) it monotonically converges to zero when \(C_{i}\) goes to zero.

Our aim is first to show that the restricted game admits a pure strategy equilibrium and then to argue that this equilibrium is also an equilibrium of the unrestricted version of the game, i.e., when both candidates are free to propose any policy in \( \mathbb {R} \). Obviously, the restricted game exists only when the implementation costs are sufficiently small. Formally, only when \(d<\min \{-\alpha _{1},\alpha _{2}\}\).

  • Step 1  In the restricted game, we have that

    $$\begin{aligned} \frac{\partial \Pi _{1}\left( x_{1},x_{2}\right) }{\partial x_{1}}= & {} v^{\prime }(x_{1}-\alpha _{1})F\left( \frac{x_{1}+x_{2}}{2}\right) \nonumber \\&+\frac{ 1}{2}(-C_{1}+v(x_{1}-\alpha _{1})-v(x_{2}-\alpha _{1}))f\left( \frac{ x_{1}+x_{2}}{2}\right) . \end{aligned}$$

    We observe that \(\frac{\partial \Pi _{1}\left( x_{1},x_{2}\right) }{\partial x_{1}}\mid _{x_{1}=\hat{x}_{1}}=0\) if and only if

    $$\begin{aligned} \frac{v^{\prime }(x_{1}-\alpha _{1})}{\frac{1}{2}(C_{1}-v(x_{1}-\alpha _{1})+v(x_{2}-\alpha _{1}))}=\frac{f\left( \frac{x_{1}+x_{2}}{2}\right) }{ F\left( \frac{x_{1}+x_{2}}{2}\right) } \end{aligned}$$
    (A.1)

    for some \(x_{1}=\hat{x}_{1}\). Derivating the left-hand side of (A.1) with respect to \(x_{1}\) yields

    $$\begin{aligned}&\frac{\partial }{\partial x_{1}}\left( \dfrac{v^{\prime }(x_{1}-\alpha _{1}) }{\frac{1}{2}(C_{1}-v(x_{1}-\alpha _{1})+v(x_{2}-\alpha _{1}))}\right) \\&\quad = \frac{v^{\prime }(x_{1}-\alpha _{1})^{2}+(C_{1}-v(x_{1}-\alpha _{1})+v(x_{2}-\alpha _{1}))v^{\prime \prime }(x_{1}-\alpha _{1})}{\frac{1}{2} (C_{1}-v(x_{1}-\alpha _{1})+v(x_{2}-\alpha _{1}))^{2}}, \end{aligned}$$

    which is strictly positive due to Assumption 2. Therefore, the left-hand side of (A.1) is strictly increasing in \(x_{1}\). The right-hand side of (A.1) is strictly decreasing in \(x_{1}\) (due to Assumption 1). Therefore, for any fixed \(x_{2}\in [d,\alpha _{2}]\), there is at most one critical value \(\hat{x}_{1}\in [\alpha _{1},-d]\) such that \(\Pi _{1}\left( x_{1},x_{2}\right) \) is strictly increasing (decreasing) for any \(x_{1}<\hat{x}_{1}\) (\(x_{1}>\hat{x}_{1}\)). In other words, \(\Pi _{1}\left( x_{1},x_{2}\right) \) is strictly quasi-concave in \(x_{1}\) in the restricted game for any \(x_{2}\in [d,\alpha _{2}]\). By analogy and given the symmetry of the candidates’ utility functions, \(\Pi _{2}\left( x_{1},x_{2}\right) \) is strictly quasi-concave in \(x_{2}\) in the restricted game for any \(x_{1}\in [\alpha _{1},-d]\). Therefore, by Debreu (1952) it follows that this restricted game admits a Nash equilibrium in pure strategies, \((x_{1}^{*},x_{2}^{*})\). Next, we argue that when \(d\rightarrow 0\), none of the equilibrium strategies of the restricted game, \(x_{1}^{*}\) and \(x_{2}^{*}\), converges to zero.

  • Step 2  Assume that \(d\rightarrow 0\) and that the candidates play a Nash equilibrium of the restricted game, \((x_{1}^{*},x_{2}^{*})\). If \((x_{1}^{*},x_{2}^{*})\rightarrow \left( 0,0\right) \), then candidate 1 can deviate to \(x_{1}=\alpha _{1}\) and get a strictly larger payoff. This is so because: (i) candidate 1’s payoff that relates to the policy is larger in profile \(\left( \alpha _{1},0\right) \) than in profile (0, 0),

    $$\begin{aligned} F\left( \frac{\alpha _{1}}{2}\right) v\left( 0\right) +\left[ 1-F\left( \frac{ \alpha _{1}}{2}\right) \right] v\left( -\alpha _{1}\right) >v\left( -\alpha _{1}\right) , \end{aligned}$$

    as \(v\left( 0\right) >v\left( -\alpha _{1}\right) \) and \(F\left( \frac{ \alpha _{1}}{2}\right) \in (0,1)\) due to \(F\left( \cdot \right) \) having full support; and (ii) candidate 1’s payoff that relates to the disutility of being in office is larger in profile \(\left( \alpha _{1},0\right) \) than in (0, 0),

    $$\begin{aligned} -F\left( \frac{\alpha _{1}}{2}\right) C_{1}>-\frac{1}{2}C_{1}, \end{aligned}$$

    due to \(F\left( \cdot \right) \) having full support and being symmetric around zero. Thus,

    $$\begin{aligned} \Pi _{1}\left( \alpha _{1},0\right)= & {} F\left( \frac{\alpha _{1}}{2}\right) v\left( 0\right) +\left[ 1-F\left( \frac{\alpha _{1}}{2}\right) \right] v\left( -\alpha _{1}\right) -F\left( \frac{\alpha _{1}}{2}\right) C_{1}>v\left( -\alpha _{1}\right) -\frac{1}{2}C_{1}\\= & {} \Pi _{1}\left( 0,0\right) . \end{aligned}$$

    Similarly, if \((x_{1}^{*},x_{2}^{*})\rightarrow \left( 0,b\right) \) with \(b>0\) as \(d\rightarrow 0\) then candidate 1 can deviate to some non-degenerate (i.e., not converging to zero) \(k<0\) and get a strictly larger payoff. This is so because Assumption 1 implies that, for any \(\alpha _{1}<0\), \(\Pi _{1}\left( x_{1},b\right) \) is strictly decreasing with \(x_{1}\in [k,0]\) for some non-degenerate \(k<0\). By analogy and given the symmetry of the candidates’ utility functions, if \((x_{1}^{*},x_{2}^{*})\rightarrow \left( b,0\right) \) with \(b<0\) as \(d\rightarrow 0 \) then candidate 2 can deviate to some non-degenerate \(k>0\) and get a strictly larger payoff. Therefore, there exists \(\bar{d}>0\) such that whenever \(d<\bar{d}\), any Nash equilibrium of the restricted game \( (x_{1}^{*},x_{2}^{*})\) is such that \((x_{1}^{*},x_{2}^{*})\in [\alpha _{1},-d)\times (d,\alpha _{2}]\) (i.e., none of the equilibrium strategies of the restricted game converges to zero). Next, we argue that if \((x_{1}^{*},x_{2}^{*})\) is an equilibrium of the restricted game, then a best response of candidate 1 in the unrestricted game to candidate 2 playing \(x_{2}^{*}\) cannot be strictly to the left of his ideal policy \(\alpha _{1}\). Similarly, the set of best responses of candidate 2 in the unrestricted game when candidate 1 plays \(x_{1}^{*}\) does not contain policies strictly to the right of \(\alpha _{2}\).

  • Step 3  (By contradiction) Assume that \(x_{1}<\alpha _{1}\). Then

    $$\begin{aligned} \frac{\partial \Pi _{1}\left( x_{1},x_{2}^{*}\right) }{\partial x_{1}}= & {} -v^{\prime }(-x_{1}+\alpha _{1})F\left( \frac{x_{1}+x_{2}^{*}}{2} \right) \\&+\,\frac{1}{2}(-C_{1}+v(-x_{1}+\alpha _{1})-v(x_{2}^{*}-\alpha _{1}))f\left( \frac{x_{1}+x_{2}^{*}}{2}\right) . \end{aligned}$$

    We observe that \(\frac{\partial \Pi _{1}\left( x_{1},x_{2}^{*}\right) }{ \partial x_{1}}\mid _{x_{1}=\hat{x}_{1}}=0\) if and only if

    $$\begin{aligned} \frac{v^{\prime }(-x_{1}+\alpha _{1})}{\frac{1}{2}(-C_{1}+v(-x_{1}+\alpha _{1})-v(x_{2}^{*}-\alpha _{1}))}=\frac{f\left( \frac{x_{1}+x_{2}^{*} }{2}\right) }{F\left( \frac{x_{1}+x_{2}^{*}}{2}\right) } \end{aligned}$$

    for some \(x_{1}=\hat{x}_{1}\). The left-hand side is strictly increasing in \( x_{1}\) (by a similar reasoning to that in step 1) while the right-hand side is strictly decreasing in \(x_{1}\) (due to Assumption 1). Therefore, there exists at most one \(\hat{x}_{1}<\alpha _{1}\) for which \(\frac{\partial \Pi _{1}\left( x_{1},x_{2}\right) }{\partial x_{1}}\mid _{x_{1}=\hat{x} _{1}}=0\). Given that

    $$\begin{aligned} \lim _{x_{1}\rightarrow \alpha _{1}^{-}}\frac{\partial \Pi _{1}\left( x_{1},x_{2}^{*}\right) }{\partial x_{1}}>0, \end{aligned}$$

    \(\Pi _{1}\left( x_{1},x_{2}^{*}\right) \) is strictly increasing (decreasing) for any \(x_{1}>\hat{x}_{1}\) (\(x_{1}<\hat{x}_{1}\)), and so \(\hat{ x}_{1}\) should be a local minimum, which contradicts that \(\hat{x}_{1}\) is a best response to \(x_{2}^{*}\). By analogy and given the symmetry of the candidates’ utility functions, one can show that there exists at most one \( \hat{x}_{2}>\alpha _{2}\) for which \(\frac{\partial \Pi _{2}\left( x_{1}^{*},x_{2}\right) }{\partial x_{2}}\mid _{x_{2}=\hat{x}_{2}}=0\), and it should be a local minimum, which contradicts that \(\hat{x}_{2}\) is a best response to \(x_{1}^{*}\). To conclude our equilibrium existence arguments, we will show that there exists \(d^{\prime }\) such that, whenever \(d<d^{\prime }\), a Nash equilibrium of the restricted game \((x_{1}^{*},x_{2}^{*})\) is a Nash equilibrium of the unrestricted game too. In what follows, we define \( x_{i}(x_{-i},C_{i}) \) as the policy that makes candidate i indifferent between winning and losing such that \(v(\left| x_{i}(x_{-i},C_{i})-\alpha _{i}\right| )-C_{i}=v(\left| x_{-i}-\alpha _{i}\right| )\).

  • Step 4  Assume that in the unrestricted game the candidates play a Nash equilibrium of the restricted game, \((x_{1}^{*},x_{2}^{*})\), and that \(d\rightarrow 0\). Candidate 1 has no incentives to deviate: a) to any \(x_{1}\in [\alpha _{1},-d]\), \(x_{1}\ne x_{1}^{*}\), because \((x_{1}^{*},x_{2}^{*})\) is a Nash equilibrium of the restricted game; b) to any \(x_{1}\in (-d,x_{1}(x_{2}^{*},C_{1})]\) because \(\frac{\partial \Pi _{1}\left( x_{1},x_{2}^{*}\right) }{\partial x_{1}}<0\) in this set (see arguments in Step 1); c) to any \( x_{1}>x_{1}(x_{2}^{*},C_{1})\) because by definition of \( x_{1}(x_{2}^{*},C_{1})\), \(\Pi _{1}\left( x_{1}(x_{2}^{*},C_{1}),x_{2}^{*}\right) >\Pi _{1}\left( x_{1},x_{2}^{*}\right) \) for any \(x_{1}>x_{1}(x_{2}^{*},C_{1})\); and d) to any \(x_{1}<\alpha _{1}\) as we established in step 3. Therefore, candidate 1 has no incentive to deviate from \(x_{1}^{*}\). By analogy and given the symmetry of the candidates’ utility functions, candidate 2 has no incentive to deviate from \(x_{2}^{*}\). It follows that there exists \(d^{\prime }>0\) such that whenever \(d<d^{\prime }\), any Nash equilibrium of the restricted game \( (x_{1}^{*},x_{2}^{*})\) is an equilibrium of the unrestricted game too.\(\square \)

Proof of Proposition 2

To characterize an interior equilibrium \((x_{1}^{*},x_{2}^{*})\), we notice that it must be such that: a) \(\frac{\partial \Pi _{1}\left( x_{1},x_{2}^{*}\right) }{\partial x_{1}}\mid _{x_{1}=x_{1}^{*}}=0\) and \(\frac{\partial \Pi _{2}\left( x_{1}^{*},x_{2}\right) }{\partial x_{2}}\mid _{x_{2}=x_{2}^{*}}=0\); and b) \(\alpha _{1}<x_{1}^{*}<x_{2}^{*}<\alpha _{2}\). The first-order conditions are given by

$$\begin{aligned}&\frac{\partial \Pi _{1}\left( x_{1},x_{2}^{*}\right) }{\partial x_{1}}\, \mid \,{}_{x_{1}=x_{1}^{*}}=-F\left( \frac{x_{1}^{*}+x_{2}^{*}}{2} \right) +\frac{1}{2}(x_{2}^{*}-x_{1}^{*}-C_{1})f\left( \frac{ x_{1}^{*}+x_{2}^{*}}{2}\right) =0, \\&\frac{\partial \Pi _{2}\left( x_{1}^{*},x_{2}\right) }{\partial x_{2}} \,\mid \,{}_{x_{2}=x_{2}^{*}}=1-F\left( \frac{x_{1}^{*}+x_{2}^{*}}{2 }\right) -\frac{1}{2}(x_{2}^{*}-x_{1}^{*}-C_{2})f\left( \frac{ x_{1}^{*}+x_{2}^{*}}{2}\right) =0, \end{aligned}$$

which amount to

$$\begin{aligned} x_{2}^{*}-x_{1}^{*}= & {} 2\frac{F\left( \frac{x_{1}^{*}+x_{2}^{*}}{2}\right) }{f\left( \frac{x_{1}^{*}+x_{2}^{*}}{2} \right) }+C_{1}, \\ x_{2}^{*}-x_{1}^{*}= & {} 2\frac{1-F\left( \frac{x_{1}^{*}+x_{2}^{*}}{2}\right) }{f\left( \frac{x_{1}^{*}+x_{2}^{*}}{2} \right) }+C_{2}, \end{aligned}$$

respectively. Therefore,

$$\begin{aligned} 2\frac{F\left( \frac{x_{1}^{*}+x_{2}^{*}}{2}\right) }{f\left( \frac{x_{1}^{*}+x_{2}^{*}}{2}\right) }+C_{1}=2\frac{1-F\left( \frac{x_{1}^{*}+x_{2}^{*}}{2}\right) }{f\left( \frac{x_{1}^{*}+x_{2}^{*}}{2}\right) }+C_{2}. \end{aligned}$$
(B.1)

Assumption 1

implies that the left-hand side of (B.1) is strictly increasing in \(\frac{x_{1}^{*}+x_{2}^{*}}{2}\) whereas the right-hand side is strictly decreasing in \(\frac{x_{1}^{*}+x_{2}^{*}}{2}\). Furthermore, as \(\frac{x_{1}^{*}+x_{2}^{*}}{2} \) goes to \(+\infty \), the left-hand side of (B.1) converges to \( +\infty \) whereas the right-hand side converges to a positive bounded value. As \(\frac{x_{1}^{*}+x_{2}^{*}}{2}\) goes to \(-\infty \), the left-hand side of (B.1) converges to a positive bounded value whereas the right-hand side converges to \(+\infty \). Thus, there exists a unique value of \(\frac{x_{1}^{*}+x_{2}^{*}}{2}\) for which (B.1) holds. We denote this unique value by s. Substituting s in the first-order conditions yields a unique interior equilibrium (5.1 ). Condition \(\alpha _{1}<x_{1}^{*}<x_{2}^{*}<\alpha _{2}\) amounts to

$$\begin{aligned} s-\frac{F\left( s\right) }{f\left( s\right) }-\frac{C_{1}}{2}>\alpha _{1} \quad \text { and }\quad s+\frac{1-F\left( s\right) }{f\left( s\right) }+\frac{C_{2} }{2}<\alpha _{2}. \ \ \end{aligned}$$

\(\square \)

Proof of Proposition 3

Note that (5.2) along with the symmetry of \(F\left( \cdot \right) \) around zero implies that: a) if \(C_{1}>C_{2}\) then \(s<0\), b) if \( C_{1}<C_{2}\) then \(s>0\) and c) if \(C_{1}=C_{2}\) then \(s=0\). Moreover,

$$\begin{aligned} \frac{\partial s}{\partial C_{1}}=-\frac{\frac{\partial }{\partial C_{1}} \left( 2\frac{F\left( s\right) }{f\left( s\right) }+C_{1}-2\frac{1-F\left( s\right) }{f\left( s\right) }-C_{2}\right) }{\frac{\partial }{\partial s} \left( 2\frac{F\left( s\right) }{f\left( s\right) }+C_{1}-2\frac{1-F\left( s\right) }{f\left( s\right) }-C_{2}\right) }=-\frac{1}{2\frac{\partial }{ \partial s}\left( \frac{F\left( s\right) }{f\left( s\right) }\right) -2 \frac{\partial }{\partial s}\left( \frac{1-F\left( s\right) }{f\left( s\right) }\right) }, \end{aligned}$$

which is always negative given Assumption 1. Similarly,

$$\begin{aligned} \frac{\partial s}{\partial C_{2}}=-\frac{\frac{\partial }{\partial C_{2}} \left( 2\frac{F\left( s\right) }{f\left( s\right) }+C_{1}-2\frac{1-F\left( s\right) }{f\left( s\right) }-C_{2}\right) }{\frac{\partial }{\partial s} \left( 2\frac{F\left( s\right) }{f\left( s\right) }+C_{1}-2\frac{1-F\left( s\right) }{f\left( s\right) }-C_{2}\right) }=\frac{1}{2\frac{\partial }{ \partial s}\left( \frac{F\left( s\right) }{f\left( s\right) }\right) -2 \frac{\partial }{\partial s}\left( \frac{1-F\left( s\right) }{f\left( s\right) }\right) }>0. \end{aligned}$$

Since \(f\left( \cdot \right) >0\), the equilibrium probability of candidate i being elected \(p_{i}\left( x_{1}^{*},x_{2}^{*}\right) \ \) decreases with his policy implementation cost \(C_{i}\) and increases with his competitor’s cost \(C_{-i}\).

Furthermore,

$$\begin{aligned} \frac{\partial x_{1}^{*}}{\partial C_{1}}= & {} \frac{\partial s}{\partial C_{1}}\cdot \frac{F\left( s\right) f^{\prime }\left( s\right) }{\left( f\left( s\right) \right) ^{2}}-\frac{1}{2}, \quad \frac{\partial x_{1}^{*}}{\partial C_{2}}=\frac{\partial s}{\partial C_{2}}\cdot \frac{F\left( s\right) f^{\prime }\left( s\right) }{\left( f\left( s\right) \right) ^{2}},\\ \frac{\partial x_{2}^{*}}{\partial C_{1}}= & {} -\frac{\partial s}{\partial C_{1}}\cdot \frac{\left( 1-F\left( s\right) \right) f^{\prime }\left( s\right) }{\left( f\left( s\right) \right) ^{2}}, \quad \frac{\partial x_{2}^{*}}{\partial C_{2}}=-\frac{\partial s}{\partial C_{2}}\cdot \frac{\left( 1-F\left( s\right) \right) f^{\prime }\left( s\right) }{\left( f\left( s\right) \right) ^{2}}+\frac{1}{2}. \end{aligned}$$

Given the above observations a)-c) and Assumption 1, the following holds.

  1. 1.

    If \(C_{1}>C_{2}\) then \(f^{\prime }\left( s\right) >0\) and therefore

    $$\begin{aligned} \frac{\partial x_{1}^{*}}{\partial C_{1}}<0, \quad \frac{\partial x_{1}^{*}}{\partial C_{2}}>0, \quad \frac{\partial x_{2}^{*}}{ \partial C_{1}}>0. \end{aligned}$$

    Moreover, for sufficiently small (and hence similar) costs \(C_{1}\) and \( C_{2} \), \(s\rightarrow 0\) and so \(\frac{\partial x_{2}^{*}}{\partial C_{2}}>0\).

  2. 2.

    If \(C_{1}<C_{2}\) then \(f^{\prime }\left( s\right) <0\) and therefore

    $$\begin{aligned} \frac{\partial x_{1}^{*}}{\partial C_{2}}<0, \quad \frac{\partial x_{2}^{*}}{\partial C_{1}}<0, \quad \frac{\partial x_{2}^{*}}{ \partial C_{2}}>0. \end{aligned}$$

    For sufficiently small (and hence similar) costs \(C_{1}\) and \(C_{2}\), \( s\rightarrow 0\) and so \(\frac{\partial x_{1}^{*}}{\partial C_{1}}<0\).

  3. 3.

    If \(C_{1}=C_{2}\equiv C\) then

    $$\begin{aligned} \frac{\partial x_{1}^{*}}{\partial C}<0, \quad \frac{\partial x_{2}^{*}}{\partial C}>0. \end{aligned}$$

    \(\square \)

Proof of Proposition 4

The median voter’s expected payoff \(Ev_{MV}\) is equal to

$$\begin{aligned} Ev_{MV}\equiv & {} \int _{-\infty }^{s}\left( -\left| x_{1}^{*}-\rho \right| \right) f\left( \rho \right) d\rho +\int _{s}^{+\infty }\left( -\left| x_{2}^{*}-\rho \right| \right) f\left( \rho \right) d\rho \\= & {} \int _{-\infty }^{x_{1}^{*}}\left( \rho -x_{1}^{*}\right) f\left( \rho \right) d\rho +\int _{x_{1}^{*}}^{s}\left( x_{1}^{*}-\rho \right) f\left( \rho \right) d\rho +\int _{s}^{x_{2}^{*}}\left( \rho -x_{2}^{*}\right) f\left( \rho \right) d\rho \\&+\int _{x_{2}^{*}}^{+\infty }\left( x_{2}^{*}-\rho \right) f\left( \rho \right) d\rho . \end{aligned}$$

In the case of \(C_{1}=C_{2}\equiv C\), differentiating \(Ev_{MV}\) with respect to C yields

$$\begin{aligned} \frac{\partial Ev_{MV}}{\partial C}=-\frac{1}{2}\left( 1-4F\left( -\frac{C }{2}-\frac{1}{2f\left( 0\right) }\right) \right) . \end{aligned}$$

Notice that it is negative if

$$\begin{aligned} C>-2F^{-1}\left( \frac{1}{4}\right) -\frac{1}{f\left( 0\right) }. \end{aligned}$$
(D.1)

We prove next that the right-hand side of (D.1) is negative. First, due to convexity of \(F\left( \cdot \right) \) for negative values,

$$\begin{aligned} \frac{\frac{1}{2}-F\left( -\frac{1}{2f\left( 0\right) }\right) }{0-\left( -\frac{1}{2f\left( 0\right) }\right) }>f\left( -\frac{1}{2f\left( 0\right) }\right) , \end{aligned}$$

which amounts to

$$\begin{aligned} \frac{1}{2}-F\left( -\frac{1}{2f\left( 0\right) }\right) >\frac{f\left( - \frac{1}{2f\left( 0\right) }\right) }{2f\left( 0\right) }. \end{aligned}$$
(D.2)

Second, due to Assumption 1,

$$\begin{aligned} \frac{f\left( -\frac{1}{2f\left( 0\right) }\right) }{F\left( -\frac{1}{ 2f\left( 0\right) }\right) }\ge \frac{f\left( 0\right) }{F\left( 0\right) } \ \ \Rightarrow \ \ \frac{f\left( -\frac{1}{2f\left( 0\right) }\right) }{2f\left( 0\right) }\ge F\left( -\frac{1}{2f\left( 0\right) }\right) . \end{aligned}$$
(D.3)

Combining (D.2) and (D.3) yields

$$\begin{aligned} \frac{1}{2}-F\left( -\frac{1}{2f\left( 0\right) }\right) >F\left( -\frac{1 }{2f\left( 0\right) }\right) \ \ \Rightarrow \ \ -2F^{-1}\left( \frac{1}{4}\right) -\frac{1}{f\left( 0\right) }<0. \end{aligned}$$

Thus, the right-hand side of (D.1) is negative and so (D.1) holds for every \(C\ge 0\). This implies that \(\frac{\partial Ev_{MV}}{ \partial C}<0\). \(\square \)

Proof of Proposition 5

If \(C_{1}=C_{2}=C\) then \(s_{k}=0\) for every k because

$$\begin{aligned} 2\frac{F_{k}(s_{k})}{f_{k}(s_{k})}+C_{1}=2\frac{1-F_{k}(s_{k})}{ f_{k}(s_{k})}+C_{2} \end{aligned}$$

yields \(F_{k}(s_{k})=\frac{1}{2}\). Hence, \(\left( x_{1}^{*},x_{2}^{*}\right) \rightarrow \left( -\frac{C}{2},\frac{C}{2}\right) \).

If \(C_{1}\ne C_{2}\) then assume that there exists \(\varepsilon >0\) such that for every k there exists \(\hat{k}>k\) with \(s_{\hat{k}}\notin [-\varepsilon ,\varepsilon ]\). Then there exists a subsequence \((\widetilde{F} _{k}\left( \cdot \right) )_{k=1}^{\infty }\) such that: a) \(\widetilde{f} _{k}(0)\rightarrow +\infty \) and \(\widetilde{F}_{k}(\rho )\rightarrow \widetilde{f}_{k}(\rho )\rightarrow 0\) for every \(\rho <0\); and b)

$$\begin{aligned} 2\frac{\widetilde{F}_{k}(s_{k})}{\widetilde{f}_{k}(s_{k})}+C_{1}=2\frac{1- \widetilde{F}_{k}(s_{k})}{\widetilde{f}_{k}(s_{k})}+C_{2}, \end{aligned}$$

which amounts to

$$\begin{aligned} 4\widetilde{F}_{k}(s_{k})+\left( C_{1}-C_{2}\right) \widetilde{f} _{k}(s_{k})=2 \end{aligned}$$

with \(s_{k}\notin [-\varepsilon ,\varepsilon ]\) for every k. But if a) holds then

$$\begin{aligned} 4\widetilde{F}_{k}(s_{k})+\left( C_{1}-C_{2}\right) \widetilde{f} _{k}(s_{k})\rightarrow 0\ne 2 \end{aligned}$$

and so b) doesn’t hold. Therefore, there exists no \(\varepsilon >0\) such that for every k there exists \(\hat{k}>k\) with \(s_{\hat{k}}\notin [-\varepsilon ,\varepsilon ]\). Hence \(s_{k}\rightarrow 0\). Notice next that for \(C_{1}>C_{2}\),

$$\begin{aligned} 2\frac{F_{k}(s_{k})}{f_{k}(s_{k})}+C_{1}=2\frac{1-F_{k}(s_{k})}{ f_{k}(s_{k})}+C_{2} \end{aligned}$$

yields

$$\begin{aligned} 4\frac{F_{k}(s_{k})}{f_{k}(s_{k})}+(C_{1}-C_{2})=\frac{2}{f_{k}(s_{k})}. \end{aligned}$$

This implies that \(f_{k}(s_{k})\rightarrow \frac{2}{C_{1}-C_{2}}\) and hence \( (x_{1}^{*},x_{2}^{*})\rightarrow \left( -\frac{C_{1}}{2},\frac{C_{1} }{2}\right) \). Similarly, when \(C_{1}<C_{2}\) we have that \((x_{1}^{*},x_{2}^{*})\rightarrow \left( -\frac{C_{2}}{2},\frac{C_{2}}{2}\right) \) . \(\square \)

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Xefteris, D., Zudenkova, G. Electoral competition under costly policy implementation. Soc Choice Welf 50, 721–739 (2018). https://doi.org/10.1007/s00355-017-1103-3

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s00355-017-1103-3

Navigation