Skip to main content
Log in

An interpretation of probability in the law of evidence based on pro-et-contra argumentation

  • Original Paper
  • Published:
Artificial Intelligence and Law Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The purpose of this paper is to improve on the logical and measure-theoretic foundations for the notion of probability in the law of evidence, which were given in my contributions Åqvist [ (1990) Logical analysis of epistemic modality: an explication of the Bolding–Ekelöf degrees of evidential strength. In: Klami HT (ed) Rätt och Sanning (Law and Truth. A symposium on legal proof-theory in Uppsala May 1989). Iustus Förlag, Uppsala, pp 43–54; (1992) Towards a logical theory of legal evidence: semantic analysis of the Bolding–Ekelöf degrees of evidential strength. In: Martino AA (ed) Expert systems in law. Elsevier Science Publishers BV, Amsterdam, North-Holland, pp 67–86]. The present approach agrees with the one adopted in those contributions in taking its main task to be that of providing a semantic analysis, or explication, of the so called Bolding–Ekelöf degrees of evidential strength (“proof-strength”) as applied to the establishment of matters of fact in law-courts. However, it differs from the one advocated in our earlier work on the subject in explicitly appealing to what is known as “Pro-et-Contra Argumentation”, after the famous Norwegian philosopher Arne Naess. It tries to bring out the logical form of that interesting kind of reasoning, at least in the context of the law of evidence. The formal techniques used here will be seen to be largely inspired by the important work done by Patrick Suppes, notably Suppes [(1957) Introduction to logic. van Nostrand, Princeton and (1972) Finite equal-interval measurement structures. Theoria 38:45–63].

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. We regret the plethora of misprints in Åqvist (1992), trusting, however, that the reader will be able to correct them successfully.

  2. A crucial distinction current among jurists and legal theorists is the one between factum probandum (“the [farthest] theme of proof”, “ultimate fact”, “fact immediately relevant to the issue”) and factum probans (“evidentiary fact”, “indicium”, “fact mediately relevant to the issue”)—see e.g. Ekelöf (1964, p. 48 f., esp. n.4), (1983, p. 10 f.). In the paper we make very little use of this admittedly highly important distinction, our interest being primarily focussed on the technical set-theoretical development of the Bolding–Ekelöf doctrine of “degrees of evidential strength”. A proper place for applying the factum probandum—factum probans distinction would then be in an empirical test of our present explication of this doctrine—a test that cannot be undertaken here.

  3. As was observed already in Åqvist (1992, § 5), the present clause of the Theorem as well as Definition 7.3 below profit from the fact that W is assumed to be finite throughout our discussion (see Definition 3.1 ff.), which means that we don’t have to worry about infinite sums and suchlike. But in this context we ought to keep in mind the following remark made in Suppes (1957, §12.4, p. 280):

    Since probability distributions appear to be so much simpler to define than finitely additive probability spaces, it might be thought that they should be the basic entities discussed in this section. Fields of sets could be dispensed with entirely, and the probability of any set would be obtained by summing over the probabilities of its individual elements. Unfortunately this simplicity disappears when infinite sets are considered, and many problems arise.

    Our reason for sticking to the assumption that W always be finite is not only the simplicity mentioned by Suppes, but also what I have elsewhere [Åqvist (2005, § 1)] called the fundamentally finitistic nature of legal reasoning, which is obviously at stake here.

  4. For the notion of a representation and uniqueness theorem required here, see Suppes (1972, §3).

  5. An anonymous referee pointed out that my present claim is not entirely convincing at least as far as the Second Principle of Preponderance is concerned. He/She observes that the fact that the principle is violated in some cases constructed according to my theory “seems to be unfortunate”. This pertinent observation is then taken to be an issue for future research and possible improvement, and I fully agree with it.

References

  • Åqvist L (1990) Logical analysis of epistemic modality: an explication of the Bolding–Ekelöf degrees of evidential strength. In: Klami HT (ed) Rätt och Sanning (Law and Truth. A symposium on legal proof-theory in Uppsala, May 1989). Iustus Förlag, Uppsala, pp 43–54

    Google Scholar 

  • Åqvist L (1992) Towards a logical theory of legal evidence: semantic analysis of the Bolding–Ekelöf degrees of evidential strength. In: Martino AA (ed) Expert systems in law. Elsevier Science Publishers BV, Amsterdam, North-Holland, pp 67–86

    Google Scholar 

  • Åqvist L (2005) Combinations of tense and deontic modality: on the rt approach to temporal logic with historical necessity and conditional obligation. J Appl Logic 3:421–460

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bolding PO (1951) Bevisbördan och den juridiska tekniken (Burden of proof and legal technique). Appelbergs, Uppsala

    Google Scholar 

  • Bolding PO (1960) Aspects of the burden of proof. Scandinavian studies in law, vol 4. Stockholm Institute for Sc Law, Stockholm, pp 9–28

  • Bolding PO (1988) Osannolikhet eller ovisshet? En fråga om behandling av alternativhypoteser vid bevisvärderingen (Improbability or uncertainty? a question about the treatment of alternative hypotheses in the evaluation of legal evidence). Svensk Juristtidning (The Swedish Law Rev) 73:606–609

    Google Scholar 

  • Bolding PO (1989) Går det att bevisa? (Can You Prove It?). Norstedts Förlag, Stockholm

    Google Scholar 

  • Ekelöf PO (1963) Rättegång (Judicial Procedure), vol 4, 1st edn. Norstedts Förlag, Stockholm

    Google Scholar 

  • Ekelöf PO (1964) Free evaluation of evidence. Scandinavian studies in law, vol 8. Institute for Sc Law, Stockholm, pp 45–66

  • Ekelöf PO (1983) My Thoughts on evidentiary value. In: Gärdenfors P, Hansson B, Sahlin N-E (eds) Evidentiary value: philosophical, judicial and psychological aspects of a theory (= Festschrift to S. Halldén. Library of Theoria No.15). Gleerups, Lund, pp 9–26

    Google Scholar 

  • Gorphe Fr (1947) L’appréciation des preuves en justice (The assessment of proofs in the law). Librairie du recueil Sirey, Paris

    Google Scholar 

  • Naess Arne (1971) En del elementaere logiske emner (Some elementary logical topics). Several Norwegian editions. Oslo: Universitetsforlaget. Swedish edition: Empirisk semantik (Empirical Semantics). Stockholm: Norstedts

  • Nilsson GB (1973) Om det fortfarande behovet av källkritik (On the continual need for source-criticism). Historisk Tidskrift (The Swedish Historical Rev) 93:173–211

    Google Scholar 

  • Shimony SE, Nissan E (2001) Kappa calculus and evidential strength: a note on Åqvist’s logical theory of legal evidence. Arti Intell Law 9:153–163, Kluwer Academic Publishers

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Suppes P (1957) Introduction to logic. van Nostrand, Princeton

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Suppes P (1972) Finite equal-interval measurement structures. Theoria 38:45–63

    Article  MATH  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Lennart Åqvist.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Åqvist, L. An interpretation of probability in the law of evidence based on pro-et-contra argumentation. Artif Intell Law 15, 391–410 (2007). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10506-007-9048-y

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10506-007-9048-y

Keywords

Navigation