Skip to main content
Log in

Cut-Elimination for Quantified Conditional Logic

  • Published:
Journal of Philosophical Logic Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

A semantic embedding of quantified conditional logic in classical higher-order logic is utilized for reducing cut-elimination in the former logic to existing results for the latter logic. The presented embedding approach is adaptable to a wide range of other logics, for many of which cut-elimination is still open. However, special attention has to be payed to cut-simulation, which may render cut-elimination as a pointless criterion.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2
Fig. 3

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. It is a recommended exercise to verify that η-equality, and hence β η-equality, is implied by the rules of \(\mathcal {G}_{\mathfrak {fb}}\).

  2. Obviously, any universally quantified predicate variable (occurring negatively in the above approach) is a possible source for cut-simulation. The challenge thus is to avoid those predicate variables as far as possible. An axiomatic approach based on cut-strong axioms, as proposed by several authors including e.g. [45, 46], is therefore hardly a suitable option for the automation of HOL.

  3. Note the predicate argument A of f in the term for \(\Rightarrow _{\tau \rightarrow \tau \rightarrow \tau }\) and the second-order quantifier ∀P τ in the term for π(ττ)→τ . FOL encodings of both constructs, if feasible, will be less natural.

  4. Sets are identified with their characteristic functions.

  5. In fact, it may be safely assumed that there are no other typed constant symbols given, except for the symbols f iττ , e i w iuo , k u n τ , and the logical connectives.

  6. In H M we have merely fixed D i = S, D u = D and D τ = Q, and the interpretations of k u n τ , f iττ and e i w iuo . These choices are not in conflict with any of the requirements regarding frames and interpretations. The existence of a valuation function V for an HOL interpretation crucially depends on how sparse the function spaces have been chosen in frame {D α } αT . Andrews [3] discusses criteria that are sufficient to ensure the existence of a valuation function; they require that certain λ-abstractions have denotations in frame {D α } αT . Since it is explicitly required that every term denotes and since Q has been appropriately constrained in QCL models (and hence D io in H M) these requirements are met.

  7. Experiments with these and other reasoners for THF are supported online via Sutcliffe’s SystemOnTPTP infrastructure [62]; cf. www.tptp.org/cgi-bin/SystemOnTPTP.

References

  1. Andrews, P. (2014). Church’s type theory. In Zalta, E.N. (Ed.) The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Spring 2014 edn.: Stanford University.

  2. Andrews, P.B. (1971). Resolution in type theory. Journal of Symbolic Logic, 36(3), 414–432.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  3. Andrews, P.B. (1972). General models and extensionality. Journal of Symbolic Logic, 37(2), 395–397.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  4. Andrews, P.B. (1972). General models, descriptions, and choice in type theory. Journal of Symbolic Logic, 37(2), 385–394.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  5. Backes, J., & Brown, C.E. (2011). Analytic tableaux for higher-order logic with choice. Journal of Automated Reasoning, 47(4), 451–479.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  6. Benzmüller, C. (1999). Equality and extensionality in automated higher-order theorem proving. Ph.D. thesis, Saarland University.

    Google Scholar 

  7. Benzmüller, C. (1999). Extensional higher-order paramodulation and RUE-resolution. In Ganzinger, H. (Ed.) Automated Deduction - CADE-16, 16th International Conference on Automated Deduction, Trento, Italy, July 7-10, 1999, Proceedings, no. 1632 in LNCS, pp. 399–413. : Springer. doi:10.1007/3-540-48660-7_39

  8. Benzmüller, C. (2009). Automating access control logic in simple type theory with LEO-II. In Gritzalis, D., & López, J. (Eds.) Emerging Challenges for Security, Privacy and Trust, 24th IFIP TC 11 International Information Security Conference, SEC 2009, Pafos, Cyprus, May 18-20, 2009. Proceedings, IFIP, vol. 297, pp. 387–398. doi:10.1007/978-3-642-01244-0_34: Springer.

  9. Benzmüller, C. (2011). Combining and automating classical and non-classical logics in classical higher-order logic. Annals of Mathematics and Artificial Intelligence (Special issue Computational logics in Multi-agent Systems (CLIMA XI)), 62(1-2), 103–128. doi:10.1007/s10472-011-9249-7.

    Google Scholar 

  10. Benzmüller, C. (2013). Automating quantified conditional logics in HOL. In Rossi, F. (Ed.) 23rd International Joint Conference on Artificial Intelligence (IJCAI-13), pp. 746-753, Beijing, China.

  11. Benzmüller, C. (2013). Cut-free calculi for challenge logics in a lazy way. In Clint van Alten Petr Cintula, C.N. (Ed.) Proceedings of the International Workshop on Algebraic Logic in Computer Science.

  12. Benzmüller, C. (2013). A top-down approach to combining logics. In Proc. of the 5th International Conference on Agents and Artificial Intelligence (ICAART), pp. 346–351. SciTePress Digital Library, Barcelona, Spain. doi:10.5220/0004324803460351.

  13. Benzmüller, C. (2015). Higher-order automated theorem provers. In Delahaye, D., & Woltzenlogel Paleo, B. (Eds.) All about Proofs, Proofs for All, Mathematical Logic and Foundations, pp. 171-214, College Publications.

  14. Benzmüller, C., Brown, C., & Kohlhase, M. (2004). Higher-order semantics and extensionality. Journal of Symbolic Logic, 69(4), 1027–1088. doi:10.2178/jsl/1102022211.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  15. Benzmüller, C., Brown, C., & Kohlhase, M. (2008). Cut elimination with xi-functionality. In Benzmüller, C., Brown, c., Siekmann, J., & Statman, R. (Eds.) Reasoning in Simple Type Theory — Festschrift in Honor of Peter B. Andrews on His 70th Birthday, Studies in Logic, Mathematical Logic and Foundations, pp. 84–100. College Publications.

  16. Benzmüller, C., Brown, C., & Kohlhase, M. (2009). Cut-simulation and impredicativity. Logical Methods in Computer Science, 5 (1:6), 1–21. doi:10.2168/LMCS-5(1:6)2009.

    Google Scholar 

  17. Benzmüller, C., Gabbay, D., Genovese, V., & Rispoli, D. (2012). Embedding and automating conditional logics in classical higher-order logic. Annals of Mathematics and Artificial Intelligence, 66(1-4), 257–271. doi:10.1007/s10472-012-9320-z.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  18. Benzmüller, C., & Genovese, V. Quantified conditional logics are fragments of HOL. In The International Conference on Non-classical Modal and Predicate Logics (NCMPL). Guangzhou (Canton), China (2011). The conference had no published proceedings; the paper is available as. arXiv:1204.5920v1.

  19. Benzmüller, C., & Paulson, L. (2008). Exploring properties of normal multimodal logics in simple type theory with LEO-II. In Benzmüller, C., Brown, C., Siekmann, J., & Statman, R. (Eds.) Reasoning in Simple Type Theory — Festschrift in Honor of Peter B. Andrews on His 70th Birthday, Studies in Logic, Mathematical Logic and Foundations, pp. 386–406. College Publications.

  20. Benzmüller, C., & Miller, D. (2014). Automation of Higher-Order Logic. Chapter. In Gabbay, D.M., Siekmann, J.H., & Woods, J. (Eds.) Handbook of the History of Logic, Volume 9 — Computational Logic, North Holland, Elsevier, pp. 215–254.

  21. Benzmüller, C., & Paulson, L. (2010). Multimodal and intuitionistic logics in simple type theory. The Logic Journal of the IGPL, 18(6), 881–892. doi:10.1093/jigpal/jzp080.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  22. Benzmüller, C., & Paulson, L. (2013). Quantified multimodal logics in simple type theory. Logica Universalis (Special Issue on Multimodal Logics), 7(1), 7–20. doi:10.1007/s11787-012-0052-y.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  23. Benzmüller, C., Paulson, L.C., Sultana, N., & Theiß, F. (2015). The higher-order prover LEO-II. Journal of Automated Reasoning, 55(4), 389–404. doi:10.1007/s10817-015-9348-y.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  24. Benzmüller, C., & Sultana, N. (2013). LEO-II Version 1.5. In Blanchette , J.C., & Urban, J. (Eds.) PxTP 2013, EPiC Series, vol. 14, pp. 2–10. EasyChair.

  25. Benzmüller, C., & Woltzenlogel Paleo, B. (2014). Automating Gödel’s ontological proof of God’s existence with higher-order automated theorem provers. In Schaub, T., Friedrich, G., & O’Sullivan, B. (Eds.) ECAI 2014, Frontiers in Artificial Intelligence and Applications, vol. 263, pp. 93–98. IOS Press. doi:10.3233/978-1-61499-419-0-93.

  26. Brown, C.E. (2004). Set comprehension in church’s type theory. Ph.D. thesis, Department of Mathematical Sciences Carnegie Mellon University. See also Chad E. Brown (2007), Automated Reasoning in Higher-Order Logic, College Publications.

  27. Brown, C.E. (2005). Reasoning in extensional type theory with equality. In Nieuwenhuis, R. (Ed.) Proc. of CADE-20, LNCS, vol. 3632, pp. 23–37. Springer.

  28. Brown, C.E. (2012). Satallax: An automatic higher-order prover. In Gramlich, B., Miller, D., & Sattler, U. (Eds.) Automated Reasoning - 6th International Joint Conference, IJCAR 2012, Manchester, UK, June 26-29, 2012. Proceedings, LNCS, vol. 7364, pp. 111–117. Springer. doi:10.1007/978-3-642-31365-3_11.

  29. Brown, C.E., & Smolka, G. (2010). Analytic tableaux for simple type theory and its first-order fragment. Logical Methods in Computer Science, 6(2).

  30. Chellas, B. (1975). Basic conditional logic. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 4 (2), 133–153.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  31. Chellas, B. (1980). Modal logic: an introduction. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  32. Church, A. (1932). A set of postulates for the foundation of logic. Annals of Mathematics, 33(2), 346–366.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  33. Church, A. (1936). An unsolvable problem of elementary number theory. American Journal of Mathematics, 58(2), 354–363.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  34. Church, A. (1940). A formulation of the simple theory of types. Journal of Symbolic Logic, 5(2), 56–68.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  35. Chwistek, L. (1948). The limits of science: Outline of logic and of the methodology of the exact sciences. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  36. Delgrande, J. (1987). A first-order conditional logic for prototypical properties. Artificial Intelligence, 33(1), 105–130.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  37. Delgrande, J. (1998). On first-order conditional logics. Artificial Intelligence, 105(1–2), 105–137.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  38. Fitting, M. (2002). Interpolation for first order S5. Journal of Symbolic Logic, 67(2), 621–634.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  39. Frege, G. Begriffsschrift, eine der arithmetischen nachgebildete Formelsprache des reinen Denkens. Halle (1879). Translated in [43].

  40. Friedman, N., Halpern, J., & Koller, D. (2000). First-order conditional logic for default reasoning revisited. ACM Transactions on Computational Logic, 1(2), 175–207.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  41. Girard, J.Y. (1971). Une extension de l’interpretation de Gödel à l’analyse, et son application à l’élimination des coupures dans l’analyse et la théorie des types. In Fenstad, J.E. (Ed.) 2nd scandinavian logic symposium, pp. 63–92, North-Holland, Amsterdam.

  42. Gödel, K. (1931). Über formal unentscheidbare Sätze der Principia Mathematica und verwandter Systeme I. Monatshefte der Mathematischen Physik, 38, 173–198.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  43. van Heijenoort, J. (1967). From Frege to Gödel: A source Book in Mathematics, 1879–1931, 3rd printing, 1997 edn. Source books in the history of the sciences series. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA.

  44. Henkin, L. (1950). Completeness in the theory of types. Journal of Symbolic Logic, 15(2), 81–91.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  45. Huet, G.P. (1972). Constrained resolution: a complete method for higher order logic. Ph.D. thesis, Case Western Reserve University.

  46. Huet, G.P. (1973). A mechanization of type theory. In Proceedings of the 3rd International Joint Conference on Artificial Intelligence, pp. 139–146.

  47. Kohlhase, M. (1994). A mechanization of sorted higher-order logic based on the resolution principle. Ph.D. thesis, Saarland University.

    Google Scholar 

  48. McDowell, R., & Miller, D. (2002). Reasoning with higher-order abstract syntax in a logical framework. ACM Transactions on Computational Logic, 3(1), 80–136.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  49. Mints, G. (1999). Cut-elimination for simple type theory with an axiom of choice. Journal of Symbolic Logic, 64(2), 479–485.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  50. Muskens, R. (2007). Intensional models for the theory of types. Journal of Symbolic Logic, 72(1), 98–118.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  51. Nute, D. (1980). Topics in conditional logic. Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  52. Olivetti, N., Pozzato, G., & Schwind, C. (2007). A sequent calculus and a theorem prover for standard conditional logics. ACM Transactions on Computational Logic, 8(4).

  53. Paleo, B.W. (2014). An embedding of neighbourhood-based modal logics in hol. Unpublished draft; available at https://github.com/Paradoxika/ModalLogic.

  54. Pattinson, D., & Schröder, L. (2011). Generic modal cut elimination applied to conditional logics. Logical Methods in Computer Science, 7(1). doi:10.2168/LMCS-7(1:4)2011.

  55. Prawitz, D. (1968). Hauptsatz for higher order logic. Journal of Symbolic Logic, 33(3), 452–457.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  56. Ramsey, F.P. (1926). The foundations of mathematics. In Proceedings of the London Mathematical Society, 2, vol. 25, pp. 338–384.

  57. Rasga, J. (2007). Sufficient conditions for cut elimination with complexity analysis. Annals of Pure and Applied Logic, 149(1–3), 81–99. doi:10.1016/j.apal.2007.08.001.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  58. Russell, B. (1908). Mathematical logic as based on the theory of types. American Journal of Mathematics, 30(3), 222–262.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  59. Schütte, K. (1960). Semantical and syntactical properties of simple type theory. Journal of Symbolic Logic, 25(4), 305–326.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  60. Smullyan, R.M. (1963). A unifying principle for quantification theory. Proc Nat Acad Sciences, 49, 828–832.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  61. Stalnaker, R. (1968). A theory of conditionals. In Studies in Logical Theory , pp. 98–112. Blackwell.

  62. Sutcliffe, G. (2009). The TPTP Problem Library and Associated Infrastructure: The FOF and CNF Parts, v3.5.0. Journal of Automated Reasoning, 43(4), 337–362.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  63. Sutcliffe, G., & Benzmüller, C. (2010). Automated Reasoning in Higher-Order Logic using the TPTP THF Infrastructure. Journal of Formalized Reasoning, 73(1), 1–27.

    Google Scholar 

  64. Tait, W.W. (1966). A nonconstructive proof of Gentzen’s Hauptsatz for second order predicate logic. Bulletin of the American Mathematical Society, 72(6), 980–983.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  65. Takahashi, M. (1967). A proof of cut-elimination theorem in simple type theory. Journal of the Mathematical Society of Japan, 19, 399–410.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  66. Takeuti, G. (1954). On a generalized logic calculus. Japanese. Journal of Mathematics 23, 39–96 (1953). Errata: ibid, 24, 149–156.

    Google Scholar 

  67. Takeuti, G. (1960). An example on the fundamental conjecture of GLC. Journal of the Mathematical Society of Japan, 12, 238–242.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  68. Takeuti, G. (1975). Proof Theory, Studies in Logic and the Foundations of Mathematics, vol. 81. Elsevier.

  69. Wisniewski, M., & Steen, A. (2015). Embedding of First-Order Nominal Logic into Higher-Order Logic. In Beziau, J. Y. et al. Handbook of the 5th world congress and school on universal logic (UNILOG’15), Istanbul, Turkey (pp. 337–339).

Download references

Acknowledgments

I am grateful to several colleagues for fruitful discussions and contributions to earlier related work; this list of persons includes Chad Brown, Dov Gabbay, Valerio Genovese, Larry Paulson, Dale Miller, Nik Sultana, and Bruno Woltzenlogel Paleo. Moreover, I am grateful to Alexander Steen for proof reading this article.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Christoph Benzmüller.

Additional information

This work has been supported by the German National Research Foundation (DFG) under grant BE 2501/9-1,2.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Benzmüller, C. Cut-Elimination for Quantified Conditional Logic. J Philos Logic 46, 333–353 (2017). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10992-016-9403-0

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10992-016-9403-0

Keywords

Navigation