Skip to main content
Log in

Let Us Investigate! Dynamic Conjecture-Making as the Formal Logic of Abduction

  • Published:
Journal of Philosophical Logic Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

We present a dynamic approach to Peirce’s original construal of abductive logic as a logic of conjecture making, and provide a new decidable, contraction-free and cut-free proof system for the dynamic logic of abductive inferences with neighborhood semantics. Our formulation of the dynamic logic of abduction follows the philosophical and scientific track that led Peirce to his late, post-1903 characterization of abductive conclusions as investigands, namely invitations to investigate propositions conjectured at the level of pre-beliefs.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. On dynamic epistemic logic (DEL), see e.g. [1,2,3, 5,6,7].

  2. See [8, 12, 14, 19,20,21,22, 32] for good reasons why abduction is not, and perhaps should not have been conflated with, IBE.

  3. Reference R is to the Peirce Papers deposited at the Harvard University Houghton Library, as cataloged by Richard Robin [25], by the manuscript number, page number (if available) and year (if available).

  4. All reasoning has, according to Peirce, a diagrammatic form in thought. Ideally, one ought to use the graphical logic of Peirce’s existential graphs in order to represent the logical forms of propositions and the inferential relationships between them, even in the case of non-deductive logic and reasoning. We do not discuss the topic of graphical logic and its relations to abduction in the present paper. Let us note, however, that Peirce himself presented at least one logical diagram which he apparently meant to represent abductive rather than deductive reasoning (Syllabus, R 478s, 1903, a draft page).

  5. July 16, 1905, R L 493. This letter has escaped earlier notice because it was not included in the 1966 microfilm edition (R) and not published in the collection of letters between Peirce and Welby, Semiotics and Significs (SS, 1977).

  6. This formulation of KD45 differs from the standard one in [11, p. 39]. The difference is that we use the axiom \((N_{B_{a}})\) instead of the rule of necessitation, the latter being that from φ that has been already derived infer Baφ. One can easily prove that the resulting system is equivalent to KD45.

  7. There are some counterexamples to these properties debated among philosophers over the years, but for our purposes of contrasting them with the principles of conjecture-making such complications are not crucial.

  8. Semantically, this corresponds to the property of density in possible-worlds semantics.

  9. Peirce’s recommendation was to take the scientific attitude toward “buried secrets”: that we should resist making the fallacy of pre-empting what the future science might bring before us, even when we would right now be faced with meager or no evidence whatsoever concerning the status of such secrets, or even no prospects of ever gaining one.

  10. To further clarify: we assume bivalence and that propositions are non-vague in the meta-theory. We could entertain tautologies being assumed, in the somewhat unwarranted sense in which from holding them something unwelcome might follow, such as an intuitionist mathematician arguing against a classical mathematician. In such examples we conjecture the hypothetical conditional, namely we conjecture that, supposing that the LEM holds in infinite domains, then non-constructive proofs would have to be allowed in such domains (and thus something unwelcome might have to be accepted, such as existence proofs without producing the objects that the indirect proof talks about, etc.). In these kinds of arguments, we assume a tautology, or a logical or necessary truth, but what we conjecture is the entire conditional formula. We thank the reviewer for suggesting possible counterexamples to our argument that conjecturing tautologies (or dually, logical or necessary falsities) is meaningless and illicit in the context of scientific reasoning. A conjecture is not the same thing as an assumption or supposition. A conjecture is a conclusion of an abductive argument. The conclusion of an abductive argument can well present itself in the form of a hypothetical conditional, such as “If LEM, then something unwelcome may occur for a classical mathematician”. But then it is this entire conditional form that will be the investigand of abductive reasoning, subject to further inquiry in order to extract its various consequences and hence its real meaning in the future proceedings of the investigation.

  11. Beliefs, as a wealth of research has confirmed, tend to be strongly irrational and biased types of attitudes, but this based on different, empirical and psychological kinds of observations.

  12. Textual evidence for setting up such a hierarchy in this manner is abundant in Peirce’s writings: “An increase of information by induction, hypothesis [abduction], or analogy, is a presumption” ([24] CP 2.430). “Animated by that [great and cheerful] hope [for true guesses], we are to proceed to the construction of a hypothesis” (EP 2:107). “The entire fabric of science has to be built up out of surmises at truth” ([24] CP 7.87). “Retroduction … depends on our hope, sooner or later, to guess at the conditions under which a given kind of phenomena will present itself” (L 477).

References

  1. Baltag, A., Moss, L.S., Solecki, S. (1998). The logic of public announcements, common knowledge, and private suspicions. In Gilboa, I. (Ed.) Proceedings of TARK, (Vol. 98 pp. 43–56).

  2. Baltag, A., Coecke, B., Sadrzadeh, M. (2005). Algebra and sequent calculus for epistemic actions. Electronic Notes in Theoretical Computer Science, 126, 27–52.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  3. Baltag, A., & Smets, A. (2008). A qualitative theory of dynamic interactive belief revision. In Proceedings of 7th LOFT, Texts in Logic and Games 3 (pp. 13–60). Amsterdam: Amsterdam University Press.

  4. Bellucci, F., & Pietarinen, A.-V. (2016). The iconic moment: towards a Peircean theory of scientific imagination and abductive reasoning. In Pombo, O., Nepomuceno, A., Redmond, J. (Eds.) Epistemology, Knowledge, and the Impact of Interaction (pp. 463–481). Dordrecht: Springer.

  5. van Benthem, J. (1996). Exploring logical dynamics. Stanford: CSLI Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  6. van Benthem, J. (2011). Logical dynamics of information and interaction. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  7. van Benthem, J., & Smets, S. (2015). Dynamic logics of belief change. In van Ditmarsch, H., Halpern, J., van der Hoek, W., & Kooi, B. (Eds.) Handbook of Epistemic Logic (pp. 299–368). London: College Publications.

  8. Campos, D. (2011). On the distinction between Peirce’s abduction and Lipton’s Inference to the best explanation. Synthese, 180, 419–442.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  9. Chellas, B. (1980). Modal logic: an introduction. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  10. Dewey, J. (1910). How we think. Boston: D. C. Heath & Co.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  11. van Ditmarsch, H., van der Hoek, W., Kooi, B. (2007). Dynamic epistemic logic. Dordrecht : Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  12. Gabbay, D.M., & Woods, J. (2005). The reach of abduction. Insight and trial. Amsterdam : Elsevier.

    Google Scholar 

  13. Goble, L. (1974). Gentzen systems for modal logics. Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic, 15, 455–461.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  14. Hintikka, J. (2007). Socratic Epistemology. Explorations of knowledge-seeking by questioning. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  15. Hintikka, J. (1962). Knowledge and belief: an introduction to the logic of the two notions. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  16. Indrzejczak, A. (2005). Sequent calculi for monotonic modal logics. Bulletin of the Section of Logic, 34(3), 151–164.

    Google Scholar 

  17. Lavendhomme, R., & Lucas, T. (2000). Sequent calculi and decision procedures for weak modal systems. Studia Logica, 65, 121–145.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  18. Ma, M., & Pietarinen, A.-V. (2015). A dynamic approach to Peirce’s interrogative construal of abductive logic. IFCoLog Journal of Logic and Applications, 3, 73–104.

    Google Scholar 

  19. Magnani, L. (2009). Abductive cognition: the epistemological and Eco-cognitive dimensions of hypothetical reasoning. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  20. Mcauliffe, W.H.B. (2015). How did abduction get confused with inference to the best explanation?. Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society, 51, 300–319.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  21. Paavola, S. (2004). Abduction as a logic and methodology of discoveries: the importance of strategies. Foundations of Science, 9(3), 267–283.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  22. Paavola, S. (2006). Hansonian and Harmanian abduction as models of discovery. International Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 20, 93–108.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  23. Park, W. (2017). Abduction in context: the conjectural dynamics of scientific reasoning. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  24. Peirce, C.S. (1958). The collected papers of Charles S. Peirce, 8 vols. In Hartshorne, C., Weiss, P., Burks, A.W. (Eds.) Cited as CP followed by volume and paragraph number (pp. 1931–1966). Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

  25. Peirce, C.S. Manuscripts and Letters in the Houghton Library of Harvard University, as identified by Richard Robin, Annotated catalogue of the papers of Charles S. Peirce, University of Massachusetts Press, Amherst, 1967, and in The Peirce Papers: A supplementary catalogue, Transactions of the C. S. Peirce Society. 7:37–57, 1971. Cited as R or R L, followed by manuscript number and, when available, page number.

  26. Pietarinen, A.-V. (2015). The science to save us from philosophy of science. Axiomathes, 25, 149–166. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10516-014-9261-8.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  27. Pietarinen, A.-V., & Sandu, G. (2004). IF logic, game-theoretical semantics, and philosophy of science. In Rahman, S., Gabbay, D., van Bendegem, J.P., Symons, J. (Eds.) Logic, Epistemology and the Unity of Science (pp. 105–138). Dordrecht: Kluwer.

  28. Pietarinen, A.-V., & Bellucci, F. (2014). New light on Peirce’s conceptions of retroduction, deduction, and scientific reasoning. International Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 28(4), 1–21. https://doi.org/10.1080/02698595.2014.979667.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  29. Troelstra, A.S., & Schiwchtenberg, H. (2000). Basic proof theory. The second edition. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  30. Wansing, H. (2002). Sequent systems for modal logics. In Gabbay, D.M., & Guenthner, F. (Eds.) Handbook of Philosophical Logic, (Vol. 8 pp. 61–145). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  31. West, D., & Anderson, M. (2016). Habit: before and beyond consciousness. Studies in Applied Philosophy Epistemology and Rational Ethics (SAPERE 31). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  32. Woods, J. (2011). Recent developments in abductive logic. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, Part A, 42(1), 240–244.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Minghui Ma.

Additional information

This first author is supported by Chinese National Funding of Social Sciences (grant no. 16CZX049). The second author is supported by the Academy of Finland (project 1270335, Diagrammatic Mind (DiaMind): Logical and Cognitive Aspects of Iconicity, 2013–2017) and the Estonian Research Council (project PUT 1305, (Abduction in the Age of Fundamental Uncertainty, 2016–2018), Principle Investigator A.-V. Pietarinen).

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Ma, M., Pietarinen, AV. Let Us Investigate! Dynamic Conjecture-Making as the Formal Logic of Abduction. J Philos Logic 47, 913–945 (2018). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10992-017-9454-x

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10992-017-9454-x

Keywords

Navigation