Skip to main content
Log in

What might philosophy of science look like if chemists built it?

  • Original Paper
  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Had more philosophers of science come from chemistry, their thinking would have been different. I begin by looking at a typical chemical paper, in which making something is the leitmotif, and conjecture/refutation is pretty much irrelevant. What in fact might have been, might be, different? The realism of chemists is reinforced by their remarkable ability to transform matter; they buy into reductionism where it serves them, but make no real use of it. Incommensurability is taken without a blink, and actually serves. The preeminence of synthesis in chemistry could have led philosophers of science to take more seriously questions of aesthetics within science, and to find a place in aesthetics for utility. The necessary motion twixt macroscopic and microscopic views of matter in modern chemistry leads to the coexistence of symbolic and iconic representations. And in another way to the deliberate, creative violation of categories.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

References

  • Ammons A.R. (1990). The really short poems of A.R. Ammons. New York, Norton, p. 16

    Google Scholar 

  • Bader R.F.W. (1990). Atoms in molecules: A quantum theory. Oxford, Oxford Univ. Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Bensaude-Vincent B. (2005). Chemistry in the French tradition of philosophy of science: Duhem, Meyerson, Metzger and Bachelard. Studies in the History and Philosophy of Science, 36, 627–648

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bensaude-Vincent B. (2000). Lessons in the history of science. Configurations, 8(2):203–214

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bensaude-Vincent B. (2005). Faut-il Avoir Peur de la Chimie. Seuil, Paris

    Google Scholar 

  • Berson J.A. (2003). Chemical discovery and the Logicians’ program. Weinheim, Wiley-VCH

    Google Scholar 

  • Earley J.E. (1981). Self-organization and agency in chemistry and in process philosophy. Process Studies, 11, 242–258

    Google Scholar 

  • Earley J.E. (1998). Modes of chemical becoming. Hyle, 4, 105–115

    Google Scholar 

  • Feyerabend P. (1975). Against method. London, Verso

    Google Scholar 

  • Galison P. (1997). Image and logic: A material culture of microphysics. Chicago, University of Chicago Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Goethe J.W.v. (1971). Elective affinities. Tr. R. J. Hollingdale (p. 53). Hammondsworth, Penguin

    Google Scholar 

  • Godfrey-Smith P. (2003). Theory and reality. Chicago, The University of Chicago Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Golinski J. (2003). Chemistry. In: Poter R. (eds) The Cambridge history of science, Vol. 4. Eighteenth-century science. Cambridge, Cambridge Universaity Press, pp. 377–396

    Google Scholar 

  • Grosholz E.R., Hoffmann R. (2000). How symbolic and iconic languages bridge the two worlds of the chemist: A case study from contemporary bioorganic chemistry. In: Bhushan N., Rosenfeld S. (eds) Of minds and molecules: New philosophical perspectives on chemistry. Oxford, Oxford University Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Hacking I. (1983). Representing and intervening. Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, (p. 262)

    Google Scholar 

  • Hoffmann R. (1995). The same and not the same. New York, Columbia University Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Hoffmann R. (1988). Nearly circular reasoning. American Scientist, 76, 182

    Google Scholar 

  • Hoffmann R. (2003). Why buy that theory?. American Scientist, 91, 9–11

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hoffmann R. (1990). Molecular beauty. The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 48(3):191–204

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hoffmann R., Laszlo P. (1991). Representation in chemistry. Angewandte Chemie, International Edition in English, 30, 1–16

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Komatsu K., Murata M., Murata Y. (2005) . Science, 307, 238–240

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Laszlo P. (1993). La Parole des Choses. Paris, Hermann

    Google Scholar 

  • Schummer, J. (2004). Why do chemists perform experiments? In D. Sobczynska, P. Zeidler, & E. (Eds.), Chemistry in the philosophical melting pot (pp. 395–410). Peter Lang (Frankfurt/M.).

  • Schummer J. (1997a). Scientometric studies on chemistry I: The exponential growth of chemical substances, 1800–1995. Scientometrics, 39, 107–123

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schummer J. (1997b). Scientometric studies on chemistry II: Aims and methods of producing new chemical substances. Scientometrics, 39, 125–140

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stein R.L. (2004). Towards a process philosophy of chemistry. Hyle, 10, 5–22

    Google Scholar 

  • Ziman J. (1978). Reliable knowledge. Cambridge, Cambridge University Press

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Roald Hoffmann.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Hoffmann, R. What might philosophy of science look like if chemists built it?. Synthese 155, 321–336 (2007). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-006-9118-9

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-006-9118-9

Keywords

Navigation