Skip to main content
Log in

Moore’s Paradox is not just another pragmatic paradox

  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

One version of Moore’s Paradox is the challenge to account for the absurdity of beliefs purportedly expressed by someone who asserts sentences of the form ‘p & I do not believe that p’ (‘Moorean sentences’). The absurdity of these beliefs is philosophically puzzling, given that Moorean sentences (i) are contingent and often true; and (ii) express contents that are unproblematic when presented in the third-person. In this paper I critically examine the most popular proposed solution to these two puzzles, according to which Moorean beliefs are absurd because Moorean sentences are instances of pragmatic paradox; that is to say, the propositions they express are necessarily false-when-believed. My conclusion is that while a Moorean belief is a pragmatic paradox, it is not just another pragmatic paradox, because this diagnosis does not explain all the puzzling features of Moorean beliefs. In particularly, while this analysis is plausible in relation to the puzzle posed by characteristic (i) of Moorean sentences, I argue that it fails to account for (ii). I do so in the course of an attempt to formulate the definition of a pragmatic paradox in more precise formal terms, in order to see whether the definition is satisfied by Moorean sentences, but not by their third-person transpositions. For only an account which can do so could address (ii) adequately. After rejecting a number of attempted formalizations, I arrive at a definition which delivers the right results. The problem with this definition, however, is that it has to be couched in first-person terms, making an essential use of ‘I’. Thus the problem of accounting for first-/third-person asymmetry recurs at a higher order, which shows that the Pragmatic Paradox Resolution fails to identify the source of such asymmetry highlighted by Moore’s Paradox.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

References

  • Baldwin T. (1990) G. E Moore. Routledge, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Braun D. (2002) Cognitive significance, attitude ascriptions, and ways of believing propositions. Philosophical Studies 108: 65–81. doi:10.1023/A:1015760114297

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Castañeda H.N. (1966) He*, a study in the logic of self-consciousness. Ratio 8: 130–157

    Google Scholar 

  • Castañeda H.N. (1968) On the logic of attributions of self-knowledge to others. The Journal of Philosophy 65: 439–456. doi:10.2307/2024296

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clark R. (1994) Pragmatic paradox and rationality. Canadian Journal of Philosophy 24: 229–242

    Google Scholar 

  • Cohen L.J. (1950) Mr. O’Connor’s “pragmatic paradoxes”. Mind 59: 85–87. doi:10.1093/mind/LIX.233.85

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Collins J. (2003) Expressions, sentences, propositions. Erkenntnis 59: 233–262

    Google Scholar 

  • De Almeida C. (2001) What Moore’s Paradox is about. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 62: 33–58

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Deutscher M. (1967) Bonney on saying and disbelieving. Analysis 27: 184–186. doi:10.2307/3326986

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Green M.S. (2007). Moorean absurdity and showing what’s within. In: Green M.S., Williams J.N. (eds). Moore’s Paradox: New essays on belief, rationality, and the first person. Clarendon Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Green M.S., Williams J.N. (2007) Introduction. In: Green M.S., Williams J.N. (eds) Moore’s Paradox: New essays on belief, rationality, and the first person. Clarendon Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Heal J. (1994) Moore’s Paradox: A Wittgensteinian approach. Mind 103: 5–24. doi:10.1093/mind/103.409.5

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jacquette D. (2000) Identity, intensionality, and Moore’s Paradox. Synthese 123: 279–292. doi:10.1023/A:1005234102606

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jones O.R. (1991) Moore’s Paradox, assertion and knowledge. Analysis 51: 182–186. doi:10.2307/3328752

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kaplan D. (1978) Dthat. In: Cole P. (eds) Syntax and semantics, Vol. 9: Pragmatics. Academic Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Kaplan D. (1979) On the logic of demonstratives. Journal of Philosophical Logic 8: 91–98

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Martinich A.P. (1980) Conversational maxims and some philosophical problems. The Philosophical Quarterly 30: 215–228. doi:10.2307/2219243

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • The Merriam-Webster’s Collegiate Dictionary. (1983). 9th ed. Springfield, MA: Merriam-Webster.

  • Moore G.E. (1993) Moore’s Paradox. In: Baldwin T. (eds) Selected writings. Routledge, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, T. (1971). The absurd. Journal of Philosophy, 68, 716–727 (Reprinted in Mortal questions, by T.Nagel, 1979, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press).

  • O’Connor D.J. (1948) Pragmatic paradoxes. Mind 57: 358–359. doi:10.1093/mind/LVII.227.358

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Perry, J. (1979). The problem of the essential indexical. Noûs, 13, 3–21 (Reprinted in The problem of the essential indexical and other essays, by J. Perry, 2000 (Expanded Edition). Stanford: CSLI Publications).

  • Perry, J. (1998). Myself and I. In M. Stamm (Ed.), Philosophie in Synthetisher Absicht (pp. 83–103). Stuttgart: Klett-Cotta (Reprinted in The problem of the essential indexical and other essays, by J. Perry, 2000 (Expanded Edition). Stanford: CSLI Publications).

  • Priest, G. (2004). Dialetheism. In N. Z. Edward (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Summer 2004 Edition). Retrieved September 15, 2007 from http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2004/entries/dialetheism/.

  • Sainsbury R.M. (1995) Paradoxes (2nd eds). Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Shoemaker S. (1996) Moore’s Paradox and self-knowledge. In: Shoemaker S. (eds) The first-person perspectives and other essays. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Sorensen R.A. (1988) Blindspots. Clarendon Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Van Fraassen B. (1995) Belief and the problem of Ulysses and the Sirens. Philosophical Studies 77: 7–37. doi:10.1007/BF00996309

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Welbourne M. (1992) More on Moore. Analysis 52: 237–241. doi:10.2307/3328342

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Williams J.N. (1979) Moore’s Paradox: One or two?. Analysis 39: 141–142. doi:10.2307/3327254

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Williams J.N. (1994) Moorean absurdity and the intentional ‘structure’ of assertion. Analysis 54: 160–166. doi:10.2307/3328665

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Williams J.N. (1996) Moorean absurdities and the nature of assertion. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 74: 135–149. doi:10.1080/00048409612347111

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Williams J.N. (1998) Wittgensteinian accounts of Moorean absurdity. Philosophical Studies 92: 283–306. doi:10.1023/A:1004260008644

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Williams J.N. (2006) Wittgenstein, Moorean absurdity and its disappearance from speech. Synthese 149: 225–254. doi:10.1007/s11229-004-6252-0

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Williamson T. (2000) Knowledge and its limits. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein L. (1967) Philosophical investigations (3rd ed., Original Publication 1953). Blackwell, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Timothy Chan.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Chan, T. Moore’s Paradox is not just another pragmatic paradox. Synthese 173, 211–229 (2010). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-008-9403-x

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-008-9403-x

Keywords

Navigation