Skip to main content
Log in

Future development of scientific structures closer to experiments: Response to F.A. Muller

  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

First of all, I agree with much of what F.A. Muller (Synthese, this issue, 2009) says in his article ‘Reflections on the revolution in Stanford’. And where I differ, the difference is on the decision of what direction of further development represents the best choice for the philosophy of science. I list my remarks as a sequence of topics.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

References

  • Cavalieri, B. (1635). Geometria indivisibilibus continuorum nova quadam ratione promote. Bologna: Clemente Ferroni (2nd ed. 1653).

  • Chuaqui, R., & Suppes, P. (1990). An equational deductive system for the differential and integral calculus. In P. Martin-Löf & G. Mints (Eds.), Lecture Notes in Computer Science, Proceedings of COLOG-88 International Conference on Computer Logic (pp. 25–49). Berlin: Springer-Verlag.

  • Chuaqui R., Suppes P. (1995) Free-variable axiomatic foundations of infinitesimal analysis: A fragment with finitary consistency proof. The Journal of Symbolic Logic 60: 122–159

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fechner, G. T. (1860/1966). Elemente der Psychophysik. Leipzig: Druck und Verlag von Breitkopfs Härtel. Transl. H. E. Adler (1966). Elements of Psychophysics (Vol. 1). New York: Holt, Rinehart & Winston.

  • Falmagne J. C. (1976) Random conjoint measurement and loudness summation. Psychological Review 83: 65–79

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Falmagne J. C. (1978) A representation theorem for finite random scale systems. Journal of Mathematical Psychology 18: 52–72

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hoyrup J. (2002) Lengths, widths, surfaces: A portrait of old Babylonian algebra and its kin. Springer, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Huntington E. V. (1934) Independent postulates for the “informal” part of Principia Mathematica. Bulletin of the American Mathematical Society 40: 127–136

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Muller, F. A. (2009). Reflections on the revolution in Stanford. Synthese (this issue).

  • Ornstein D., Weiss B. (1991) Statistical properties of chaotic systems. Bulletin of the American Mathematical Society (New Series) 24: 11–116

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rubin H., Suppes P. (1954) Transformations of systems of relativistic particle mechanics. Pacific Journal of Mathematics 4: 563–601

    Google Scholar 

  • Sommer R., Suppes P. (1996) Finite models of elementary recursive nonstandard analysis. Notas de la Sociedad Matematica de Chile 15: 73–95

    Google Scholar 

  • Sommer R., Suppes P. (1997) Dispensing with the continuum. The Journal of Mathematical Psychology 41: 3–10

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Suppes P. (1959) Axioms for relativistic kinematics with or without parity. In: Henkin L. et al (eds) The axiomatic method with special reference to geometry and physics. North-Holland Publishing Co., Amsterdam, pp 291–307

    Google Scholar 

  • Suppes P. (1962) Models of data. In: Nagel E., Suppes P., Tarski A. (eds) Logic, methodology, and philosophy of science: Proceedings of the 1960 International Congress. Stanford University Press, Stanford, pp 252–261

    Google Scholar 

  • Suppes P. (1970) A probabilistic theory of causality. North-Holland Publishing Co, Amsterdam

    Google Scholar 

  • Suppes P. (1993) The transcendental character of determinism. In: French P. A., Uehling T. E., Wettstein H. K. (eds) Midwest Studies in Philosophy, Vol. XVIII. University of Notre Dame Press, Notre Dame, pp 242–257

    Google Scholar 

  • Suppes P. (1995) Principles that transcend experience: Kant’s antinomies revisited. Transzendentale Prinzipien: Eine Neubetrachtung der Kantschen Antinomien. Metaphysik 11: 43–54

    Google Scholar 

  • Suppes P. (1999) The noninvariance of deterministic causal models. Synthese 121: 181–198

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Suppes P. (2002) Representation and invariance of scientific structures. CSLI Publications, Stanford

    Google Scholar 

  • Suppes P. (2006) Transitive indistinguishability and approximate measurement with standard finite ratio-scale representations. Journal of Mathematical Psychology 50: 329–336

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Suppes P., Chuaqui R. (1993) A finitarily consistent free-variable positive fragment of infinitesimal analysis. Proceedings of the IX Latin American Symposium on Mathematical Logic. Notas de Logica Matematica 38: 1–59

    Google Scholar 

  • Suppes P., de Barros J. A. (1996) Photons, billiards and chaos. In: Weingartner P., Schurz G. (eds) Law and Prediction in the Light of Chaos Research. Lecture Notes in Physics. Springer-Verlag, Berlin, pp 189–201

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Thurstone L. L. (1927a) A law of comparative judgment. Psychological Review 34: 273–286

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thurstone L. L. (1927b) Psychophysical analysis. American Journal of Psychology 38: 368–389

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wiener N. (1921) A new theory of measurement: A study in the logic of mathematics. Proceedings of the London Mathematical Society 19: 181–205

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Patrick Suppes.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Suppes, P. Future development of scientific structures closer to experiments: Response to F.A. Muller. Synthese 183, 115–126 (2011). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-009-9670-1

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-009-9670-1

Keywords

Navigation