Skip to main content
Log in

Belief ascription and the Ramsey test

  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In this paper, I analyse a finding by Riggs and colleagues that there is a close connection between people’s ability to reason with counterfactual conditionals and their capacity to attribute false beliefs to others. The result indicates that both processes may be governed by one cognitive mechanism, though false belief attribution seems to be slightly more cognitively demanding. Given that the common denominator for both processes is suggested to be a form of the Ramsey test, I investigate whether Stalnaker’s semantic theory of conditionals, which was inspired by the Ramsey test, may provide the basis for a psychologically plausible model of belief ascription. The analysis I propose will shed some new light on the developmental discrepancy between counterfactual reasoning and false belief ascription.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

References

  • Amsterlaw J., Wellman H. M. (2006) A microgenetic study of the development of false belief understanding. Journal of Cognition and Development 7(2): 139–172

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Apperly I. A. (2011) Mindreaders: The cognitive basis of ‘theory of mind’. Psychology Press, Routledge

    Google Scholar 

  • Apperly I. A., Riggs K. J., Simpson A., Chiavarino C., Samson D. (2006) Is belief reasoning automatic?. Psychological Science 17(10): 841–844

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baillargeon R., Scott R. M., He Z. (2010) False-belief understanding in infants. Trends in Cognitive Sciences 14(3): 10–18

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baron-Cohen S. (1995) Mindblindness: An essay on autism and theory of mind. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Baron-Cohen S., Leslie A. M., Frith U. (1985) Does the autistic child have a “theory of mind”?. Cognition 21: 37–46

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bennett J. (2003) A philosophical guide to conditionals. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bloom P., German T. P. (2000) Two reasons to abandon the false belief task as a test of theory of mind. Cognition 77: 25–31

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Byrne R. M. (2002) Mental models and counterfactual thoughts about what might have been. Trends in Cognitive Sciences 6(10): 426–431

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carruthers, P., Smith, P. K. (eds) (1996) Theories of theories of mind. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (2001). A coherence theory of truth and knowledge. In Subjective, intersubjective, objective (pp. 137–153). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Drayton S., Turley-Ames K. J., Guajardo N. R. (2011) Counterfactual thinking and false belief: The role of executive function. Journal of Experimental Child Psychology 108: 532–548

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Evans, J. S. B. T., & Over, D. E. (2004). If. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Frege, G. (1892/1948). Sense and reference. The Philosophical Review, 57(3), 209–230.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gärdenfors P. (1988) Knowledge in flux: Modelling dynamics of epistemic states. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • German T. P., Nichols S. (2003) Children’s counterfactual inferences about long and short causal chains. Developmental Science 6: 514–523

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grant C. M., Riggs K. J., Boucher J. (2004) Counterfactual and mental state reasoning in children with autism. Journal of Autism and Developmental Disorders 34(2): 177–188

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Guajardo N. R., Parker J., Turley-Ames K. (2009) Associations among false belief understanding, counterfactual reasoning, and executive function. British Journal of Developmental Psychology 27: 681–702

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Guajardo N. R., Turley-Ames K. (2004) Preschooler’s generation of different types of counterfactual statements and theory of mind understanding. Cognitive Development 19: 53–80

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kripke S. A. (1963) Semantical consideration on modal logic. Acta Philosophica Fennica 16: 83–94

    Google Scholar 

  • Leslie A. M. (1987) Pretense and representation: The origins of theory of mind. Psychological Review 94(4): 412–426

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis D. (1973) Causation. The Journal of Philosophy 70(17): 556–567

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis D. (1996) Elusive knowledge. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 74(4): 549–567

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nute D., Cross C. B. (2002) Conditional logic. In: Gabbay D. M., Guenthner F. (eds) Handbook of philosophical logic (Vol. 4, 2nd ed.). Springer, New York, pp 1–98

    Google Scholar 

  • Perner J. (1991) Understanding the representational mind. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Perner J., Rafetseder E. (2011) Counterfactual and other forms of conditional reasoning: Children lost in the nearest possible world. In: Hoerl C., McCormack T., Beck S. (eds) Understanding counterfactuals, understanding causation: Issues in philosophy and psychology. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Perner J., Sprung M., Steinkogler B. (2004) Counterfactual conditionals and false belief: A developmental dissociation. Cognitive Development 19: 179–201

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Peterson D. M., Riggs K. J. (1999) Adaptive modelling and mindreading. Mind & Language 14(1): L80–112

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Premack D., Woodruff G. (1978) Does the chimpanzee have a theory of mind?. The Behavioral and Brain Sciences 1: 512–526

    Google Scholar 

  • Rafetseder E., Cristi-Vargas R., Perner J. (2010) Counterfactual reasoning: Developing a sense of nearest possible world. Child Development 81(1): 76–389

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rafetseder E., Perner J. (2010) Is reasoning from counterfactual antecedents evidence for counterfactual reasoning?. Thinking & Reasoning 16(2): 131–155

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ramsey, F. P. (1929/1990). General propositions and causality. In D. H. Mellor (Ed.), Philosophical Papers. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press (pp. 145–163); original publication, 1929.

  • Recanati F. (2000) Oratio obliqua, oratio recta: An essay on metarepresentation. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Riggs K. J., Peterson D. M., Robinson E. J., Mitchell P. (1998) Are errors in false belief tasks symptomatic of a broader difficulty with counterfactuality?. Cognitive Development 13: 73–90

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stalnaker R. C. (1968) A theory of conditionals. In: Rescher N. (ed) Studies in logical theory. American Philosophical Quarterly Monograph Series, 2. Blackwell, Oxford, pp 98–112

    Google Scholar 

  • Stalnaker R. C. (1984) Inquiry. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Wimmer H., Perner J. (1983) Beliefs about beliefs representation and constraining function of wrong beliefs in young children’s understanding of deception. Cognition 13(1): 103–128

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Karolina Krzyżanowska.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Krzyżanowska, K. Belief ascription and the Ramsey test. Synthese 190, 21–36 (2013). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-012-0160-5

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-012-0160-5

Keywords

Navigation