Skip to main content
Log in

At least not false, at most possible: between truth and assertibility of superlative quantifiers

  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Generalized Quantifier Theory defines superlative quantifiers at most n and at least n as truth-conditionally equivalent to comparative quantifiers fewer than n+1 and more than n \(-\)1. It has been demonstrated, however, that this standard theory cannot account for various linguistic differences between these two types of quantifiers. In this paper I discuss how the distinction between assertibility and truth-conditions can be applied to explain this phenomenon. I draw a parallel between the assertibility of disjunctions and superlative quantifiers, and argue that those assertibility conditions are essentially modal. I use epistemic logic to formalize the assertibility conditions and revisit some of the linguistic puzzles related to superlative quantification.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. For our purposes only formulas with quantification under the scope of model operators are needed, and the philosophical questions (though interesting) that arise from allowing modalities under the scope of quantifiers are not relevant for this paper.

  2. Since in the current paper the analysis is limited to sentences of form at most n/at least n A are B, here and in all definitions below, \(\phi \) is a formula \((A(x) \wedge B(x))\), where \(A\),\(B\) are unary FO predicates.

  3. $$\begin{aligned}&\exists ^{=n}x\phi (x) \overset{dfn}{\iff } \exists x_1...\exists x_n [ \bigwedge _{i=1}^{n}\phi (x_i)\wedge \bigwedge _{1\le i<j\le n}(x_i\ne x_j) \wedge \forall y (\bigwedge _{i=1}^{n} y\ne x_i \rightarrow \lnot \phi (y))]\end{aligned}$$
    (VI)
    $$\begin{aligned}&\exists ^{>n}x\phi (x) \overset{dfn}{\iff } \exists x_1...\exists x_{n+1} \left[ \bigwedge _{i=1}^{n+1}\phi (x_i)\wedge \bigwedge _{1\le i<j\le n+1}(x_i\ne x_j)\right] \end{aligned}$$
    (VII)
    $$\begin{aligned}&\exists ^{<n}x\phi (x) \overset{dfn}{\iff } \forall x_1...\forall x_{n} \left[ \bigwedge _{1\le i<j\le n}(x_i\ne x_j)\rightarrow \bigvee _{i=1}^{n}\lnot \phi (x_i)\right] \end{aligned}$$
    (VIII)
  4. Note that \(\Diamond _S \exists ^{<n}x\phi (x)\) is not equivalent to \(\bigwedge _{i=o}^{n-1} \Diamond _S \exists ^{=i}x\phi (x)\), where \(\exists ^{=0}x\phi (x)\) means that \(\lnot \exists x\phi (x)\).

  5. Such a requirement would enforce the following formulation of the belief condition: \(\bigwedge _{i=n}^{N} \Diamond _S \exists ^{=i}x\phi (x)\), where \(N\) is the cardinality of the quantifier’s domain.

  6. “Smallest” is used here from the point of view of economy principles governing verification procedure, i.e. the “first” one that results in falsification failure.

References

  • Barwise, J. (1987). Noun phrases, generalized quantifiers, and anaphora. In P. Gärdenfors (Ed.), Generalized quantifiers. Linguistic and logical approaches (pp. 1–30). Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barwise, J., & Cooper, R. (1981). Generalized quantifiers and natural language. Linguistics and Philosophy, 4(2), 159–219.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Belnap, N. D. J. (1973). Restricted quantification and conditional assertion. In H. Leblanc (Ed.), Truth, syntax and modality. Amsterdam: North-Holland.

    Google Scholar 

  • Borg, E. (2007). Minimalism versus contextualism in semantics. In G. Preyer & G. Peter (Eds.), Context-sensitivity and semantic minimalism: New essays on semantics and pragmatics (pp. 339–359). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Borg, E. (2012). Pursuing meaning. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Brandom, R. (1976). Truth and assertibility. The Journal of Philosophy, 73(6), 137–149.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Büring, D. (2007). The least “at least” can do. In C. B. Chang & H. J. Haynie (Eds.), Proceedings of the 26th West Coast Conference on Formal Linguistics (pp. 114–120). Somerville, MA: Cascadilla Proceedings Project.

  • Cappelen, H., & Lepore, E. (2005). A tall tale: In defense of semantic minimalism and speech act pluralism. In G. Preyer & G. Peter (Eds.), Contextualism in philosophy: Knowledge, meaning, and truth (pp. 197–219). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chierchia, G. (2004). Scalar implicatures, polarity phenomena, and the syntax/pragmatics interface. In A. Belletti (Ed.), Structures and beyond (pp. 39–103). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chierchia, G., Fox, D., & Spector, B. (2012). The grammatical view of scalar implicatures and the relationship between semantics and pragmatics. In P. Portner, C. Maienborn, & K. von Heusinger (Eds.), An international handbook of natural language meaning. The Hague: Mouton de Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, A., & Krifka, M. (2011). Superlative quantifiers as modifers of meta-speech acts. The Baltic International Yearbook of Cognition, Logic and Communication, 6, 1–46.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, A., & Krifka, M. (2014). Superlative quantifiers and meta-speech acts. Linguistics & Philosophy, 37, 41–90.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Coppock, E., & Brochhagen, T. (2013a). Diagnosing truth, interactive sincerity, and depictive sincerity. Proceedings of SALT, 23, 358–375.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Coppock, E., & Brochhagen, T. (2013b). Raising and resolving issues with scalar modifiers. Semantics & Pragmatic, 6, 1–57.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cummins, C., & Katsos, N. (2010). Comparative and superlative quantifiers: Pragmatic effects of comparison type. Journal of Semantics, 27, 271–305.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Douven, I. (2011). Indicative conditionals. In L. Horsten & R. Pettigrew (Eds.), A Companion to Philosophical Logic (pp. 83–405). London: Continuum Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Douven, I., & Verbrugge, S. (2010). The Adams family. Cognition, 117, 302–318.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dummett, M. A. E. (1975). What is a theory of meaning. In S. Guttenplan (Ed.), Mind and Language, CUP, reprinted in Dummett, The Seas of Language, OUP, 1993.

  • Dummett, M. A. E. (1991). The logical basis of metaphysics. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Edgington, D. (1995). On conditionals. Mind, 104, 23539.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Frege, G. (1892). Über Sinn und Bedeutung. Zeitschrift für Philosophie und Philosophische Kritik, 100, 22–50.

    Google Scholar 

  • Geurts, B., & Nouwen, R. (2007). “At least” et al.: The semantics of scalar modifiers. Language, 83, 533–559.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Geurts, B., Katsos, N., Cummins, C., Moons, J., & Noordman, L. (2010). Scalar quantifiers: Logic, acquisition, and processing. Language and Cognitive Processes, 25, 130–148.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gierasimczuk, N. (2010). Knowing one’s limits. Logical analysis of inductive inference. DS-2010-11, ILLC, University of Amsterdam.

  • Groenendijk, J., & Roelofsen, F. (2009). Inquisitive semantics and pragmatics. In: J. Larrazabal & L. Zubeldia (Eds.), Meaning, content and argument: Proceedings of the ILCLI International Workshop on Semantics, Pragmatics and Rhetoric. San Sebastian: Universidad del Pais Vasco, Servicio Editorial, vol (SPR-09), pp 41–72.

  • Karttunen, L., & Peters, S. (1979). Conventional implicatures. In O. Choon-Kyu & D. Dineen (Eds.), Syntax and semantics, presuppositions (Vol. 11, pp. 1–56). New York: Academic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Koster-Moeller, J., Varvoutis, J., & Hackl, M. (2008). Verification procedures for modified numeral quantifiers. In N. Abner, J. Bishop (Eds.), Proceedings of the West Coast Conference on Formal Linguistics (Vol. 27, pp. 310–317). Somerville, MA: Cascadilla Proceedings Project.

  • Krifka, M. (1999). At least some determiners aren’t determiners. In K. Turner (Ed.), The semantics/pragmatics interface from different points of view (pp. 257–291). Amsterdam: Elsevier Science B.V.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levinson, S. C. (1983). Pragmatics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Musolino, J. (2004). The semantics and acquisition of number words: Intergrating linguistic and developmental perspectives. Cognition, 93(1), 1–41.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nilsen, O. (2007). At least-free choice and lowest utility. Talk given at the ESSLLI workshop on quantifier modification, Dublin. http://www.let.uu.nl/Rick.Nouwen/qm/nilsen.pdf.

  • Nouwen, R. (2010). Two kinds of modified numerals. Semantics and Pragmatics, 3, 1–41.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pagin, P. (2014). Assertion. In: E. N. Zalta (ed.) The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy, Spring 2014 edn. URL: http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2014/entries/assertion/

  • Peters, S., & Westerståhl, D. (2006). Quantifiers in langauge and logic. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W. V. O. (1952). Methods of logic. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Recanati, F. (2001). Unarticulated constituents. Linguistics & Philosophy, 25, 299–345.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Recanati, F. (2010). Truth-conditional pragmatics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Schroeder-Heister, P. (2014). Proof-theoretic semantics. In: E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy, Summer 2014 edn. URL: http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2014/entries/proof-theoretic-semantics/

  • Sperber, D., & Wilson, D. (1986). Relevance: Communication and cognition. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stalnaker, R. (1973). Presuppositions. The Journal of Philosophical Logic, 2, 447–457.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stenning, K., & van Lambalgen, M. (2008). Human reasoning and cognitive science. Cambridge: Massachusetts Institut of Technology.

    Google Scholar 

  • Suppes, P. (1982). Variable-free semantics with remark on procedural extensions. In Scholes Simon (Ed.), Language, mind and brain (pp. 21–34). Erlbaum: Hillsdale.

    Google Scholar 

  • Szymanik, J. (2009). Quantifiers in TIME and SPACE: Computational Complexity of Generalized Quantifiers in Natural Language. DS-2009-01, IILC, University of Amsterdam.

  • Tichý, P. (1969). Intension in terms of Turing machines. Studia Logica, 24(1), 7–21.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Van der Sandt, R., & Geurts, B. (2001). Too. In Proceedings of the 13th Amsterdam Colloquium. Amsterdam: University of Amsterdam.

  • Van Ditmarsch, H., van der Hoek, W., & Kooi, B. (2007). Dynamic epistemic logic. New York: Springer.

  • Zeevat, H. (2003). Particles: Presupposition triggers or context markers? In R. Blutner & H. Zeevat (Eds.), Optimality theory and pragmatics. New York: Palgrave-McMillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zimmermann, T. E. (2000). Free choice disjunction and epistemic possibility. Natural Language Semantics, 8, 255–290.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

For comments on the manuscript I would like to thank Henk Zeevat and Jarmo Kontinen. For linguistic corrections and remarks I am grateful to Kevin Reuter. This research was funded by the Foundation Stiftung Mercator.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Maria Spychalska.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Spychalska, M. At least not false, at most possible: between truth and assertibility of superlative quantifiers. Synthese 195, 571–602 (2018). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-014-0615-y

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-014-0615-y

Keywords

Navigation