Skip to main content
Log in

The two faces of compatibility with justified beliefs

  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

When discussing knowledge, two relations are of interest: justified doxastic accessibility \(S\) (for all the agent is justified in believing in \(x\), she is in \(y\)) and justification equivalence \(E\) (the agent would have in \(y\) exactly the same justified beliefs that she has in \(x\)). Speaking of compatibility with the agent’s justified beliefs is potentially ambiguous: either of the two relations \(S\) or \(E\) can be meant. I discuss the possibility of identifying the relation of epistemic accessibility \(R\) (for all the agent knows in \(x\), she is in \(y\)) with the union of \(S\) and \(E\). Neither Gettier’s examples nor the ‘fake barn’ cases contradict this identification. However, the proposal leads to justification equivalent scenarios being symmetric with respect to knowledge: we cannot know a true proposition in a scenario if it is false in a justification equivalent scenario. This analysis may appear to render non-trivial knowledge impossible. This conclusion follows if the extra premise is granted that for all relevant true propositions there is a justification equivalent scenario in which the proposition is false. I provide a meaning-theoretic argument against this premise. I conclude by pointing out problems that would ensue from giving up the proposed connection between \(S\), \(E\) and \(R\) and allowing asymmetry of justification equivalent scenarios relative to knowledge.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Strictly speaking, Goldman allows that \(w\) and \(v\) produce a ‘sufficiently similar’ perceptual experience.

  2. See Hintikka (1969, pp.  151–183). For the term ‘perceptual alternative’, see Hintikka (1975, pp.  43–44).

  3. Stalnaker restricts attention to a strong notion of belief, characterized by the fact that believing in this sense entails believing that one knows (Stalnaker 2006, p.  179).

References

  • Davidson, D. (1974). Belief and the basis of meaning. Synthese, 27(3–4), 309–323.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dummett, M. (2006). Thought and reality. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gettier, E. (1963). Is justified true belief knowledge? Analysis, 23(6), 121–123.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goldman, A. (1976). Discrimination and perceptual knowledge. The Journal of Philosophy, 73(20), 771–791.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hintikka, J. (1962). Knowledge and belief. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hintikka, J. (1969). Models for modalities. Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hintikka, J. (1975). The intentions of intentionality and other new models for modalities. Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. (1981). Reason, truth, and history. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Stalnaker, R. (2006). On logics of knowledge and belief. Philosophical Studies, 128(1), 169–199.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Williamson, T. (2000). Knowledge and its limits. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Williamson, T. (2013a). Gettier cases in epistemic logic. Inquiry, 56(1), 1–14.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Williamson, T. (2013b). Response to Cohen, Comesaña, Goodman, Nagel, and Weatherson on Gettier cases in epistemic logic. Inquiry, 56(1), 77–96.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I wish to thank Giuseppina Ronzitti and the anonymous referees for comments and criticism that helped to improve the paper.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Tero Tulenheimo.

Appendix

Appendix

In this Appendix all formulas have ‘\(p\)’ as their sole propositional variable. Augmented models are triples \(\langle W, S, p \rangle \), where \(\langle W, S \rangle \) is a model and \(p \subseteq W\). It is understood that ‘\(p\)’ stands for \(p\). A formula \(\varphi \) is valid in \(\langle W, S \rangle \) (denoted \(\langle W, S \rangle \models \varphi \)) if for all augmented models \(M=\langle W, S, p \rangle \) and all \(w \in W\), the proposition expressed by \(\varphi \) in \(M\) is true at \(w\). (‘Valid in a model’ means what is usually termed ‘valid in a frame’. The terminology is deviant because I follow Williamson (2013a) in not incorporating a valuation in a model.) I write \({ Kp }\) for \(\{v:\) for all \(x\), if \(vR^*x\), then \(x \in p\}\). A model \(\langle W, S \rangle \) is justificatorily homogeneous if all sets \(S(w)\) with \(w \in W\) are justificatorily homogeneous. We recall from Sect. 5 that \(S(w)\) is justificatorily homogeneous if \(S(v)=S(w)\) for all \(v \in S(w)\).

Fact 1

A model \(\langle W, S \rangle \) is justificatorily homogeneous \(\Leftrightarrow \) the relation \(S\) is transitive (whenever \(xSy\) and \(ySz\), then \(xSz\)) and Euclidean (whenever \(xSy\) and \(xSz\), then \(ySz\)) \(\Leftrightarrow \) \(\langle W, S \rangle \models { Jp } \rightarrow K{ Jp }\) and \(\langle W, S \rangle \models \lnot { Jp } \rightarrow K\lnot { Jp }\).

Proof

We prove two more specific claims:

  1. (a)

    \(S\) is transitive \(\Leftrightarrow \) \(S(y) \subseteq S(x)\) for all \(x \in W\) and \(y \in S(x)\) \(\Leftrightarrow \) \(\langle W, S \rangle \models { Jp } \rightarrow KJp \).

  2. (b)

    \(S\) is Euclidean \(\Leftrightarrow \) \(S(x) \subseteq S(y)\) for all \(x \in W\) and \(y \in S(x)\) \(\Leftrightarrow \) \(\langle W, S \rangle \models \lnot { Jp } \rightarrow K\lnot { Jp }\).

Now, \(S\) is transitive \(\Leftrightarrow \) for all \(x\), \(y\), \(z\), we have: if \(y \in S(x)\) and \(z \in S(y)\), then \(z \in S(x)\) \(\Leftrightarrow \) for all \(x\) and \(y\): if \(y \in S(x)\), then \(S(y) \subseteq S(x)\). Further, \(S\) is Euclidean \(\Leftrightarrow \) for all \(x\), \(y\), \(z\): if \(y \in S(x)\) and \(z \in S(x)\), then \(z \in S(y)\) \(\Leftrightarrow \) for all \(x\) and \(y\): if \(y \in S(x)\), then \(S(x) \subseteq S(y)\). Let us, then, consider the second equivalence of claim \((a)\). Let \(M\) be any augmented model in which \(S\) is transitive and let \(x\) be any scenario. Suppose \(S(x) \subseteq p\). Let \(y\) be any scenario with \(xR^*y\), whence \(xSy\) or \(xEy\). Using the first equivalence of \((a)\) and the definition of \(E\), we conclude that \(S(y) \subseteq S(x)\). It follows that \(S(y) \subseteq p\) and indeed \(x \in { KJp }\). Conversely, assume \(\langle W, S \rangle \models { Jp } \rightarrow { KJp }\). Suppose for contradiction there are \(x,y,z\) such that \(xSy\) and \(ySz\) but not: \(xSz\). Consider the augmented model \(\langle W,S,p \rangle \) where \(p=S(x)\). Then \(x \in { Jp }\). On the other hand, \(S(y) \not \subseteq p\) since \(z \notin S(x)\). As \(xR^*y\), it follows that \(x \notin { KJp }\). Finally, we consider the second equivalence of claim \((b)\). Let \(M\) be any augmented model in which \(S\) is Euclidean and let \(x\) be any scenario. Suppose \(S(x) \not \subseteq p\). Let \(y\) be any scenario with \(xR^*y\), whence \(xSy\) or \(xEy\). Using the first equivalence of \((b)\) and the definition of \(E\), we may infer that \(S(x) \subseteq S(y)\). It follows that \(S(y) \not \subseteq p\). Conversely, assume \(\langle W, S \rangle \models \lnot { Jp } \rightarrow K\lnot { Jp }\). Suppose for contradiction there are \(x,y,z\) such that \(xSy\) and \(xSz\) but not: \(ySz\). Consider the augmented model \(\langle W,S,p \rangle \) where \(p=W \setminus \{z\}\). Then \(x \in \lnot { Jp }\). Yet \(x \notin K\lnot { Jp }\), since \(xR^*y\) but \(S(y) \subseteq p\). The main claim follows immediately from the auxiliary claims \((a)\) and \((b)\). \(\square \)

Fact 2

There are models in which \(S\) is neither transitive nor Euclidean and which refute both introspection principles \({ Jp } \rightarrow K{ Jp }\) and \(\lnot { Jp } \rightarrow K\lnot { Jp }\).

Proof

We saw in Sect. 5 that there are models and scenarios \(x\), \(y\) such that \(S(x) \not \subseteq S(y)\) and \(S(y) \not \subseteq S(x)\). The claims follow by the proof of Fact 1. \(\square \)

Fact 3

\(R^*\) is transitive \(\Leftrightarrow \) all \(w \in W\) and \(v \in S(w)\) satisfy:

$$\begin{aligned} S(v) \cup E(v) \subseteq S(w)\, or\, S(v) = S(w). \end{aligned}$$

Proof

Assume first that \(S(v) \cup E(v) \subseteq S(w)\) or \(S(v) = S(w)\) for all \(w \in W\) and \(v \in S(w)\). Suppose \(xR^*y\) and \(yR^*z\). That is, [\(xEy\) and \(yEz\)] or [\(xSy\) and \(ySz\)] or [\(xEy\) and \(ySz\)] or [\(xSy\) and \(yEz\)]. In the first case we have trivially \(xEz\) and in the third case trivially \(xSz\), so in both cases \(xR^*z\). In the second case we have \(xSz\): namely, given our assumption, \(y \in S(x)\) entails in particular that \(S(y) \subseteq S(x)\), whence \(z \in S(y) \subseteq S(x)\). In the fourth case, consider the two subcases: either \(S(y) \cup E(y) \subseteq S(x)\) or \(S(y) = S(x)\) (at least one of them holds, since \(xSy\)). In the former subcase, we have \(xSz\) because \(z \in E(y) \subseteq S(x)\). In the latter subcase, we have \(xEz\) because \(S(x)=S(y)\) and \(S(y)=S(z)\). Thus, we have \(xR^*z\) also in the second and the fourth case.

Conversely, assume \(R^*\) is transitive. Suppose for contradiction that there are \(w \in W\) and \(v \in S(w)\) such that either \(S(w) \ne S(v) \not \subseteq S(w)\) or \(E(v) \not \subseteq S(w) \ne S(v)\). In the former case, there is \(u\) such that \(vSu\) but not: \(wSu\). Since \(wSv\), \(S\) is not transitive. This is impossible as \(S \subseteq R^*\) and \(R^*\) is transitive. Let us proceed to consider the latter case. Here we may assume that \(S(v) \subseteq S(w)\). Because \(E(v) \not \subseteq S(w)\), there is \(u\) such that \(vEu\) and \(u \notin S(w)\). Since \(S(v) \subseteq S(w)\), in particular \(u \notin S(v)\). Now, \(wSv\) and \(vEu\), whence \(wR^*v\) and \(vR^*u\), from which it follows by the transitivity of \(R^*\) that \(wR^*u\). So either \(wSu\) or \(wEu\). The latter option is blocked by the fact that \(S(w) \ne S(v) = S(u)\). The former option is likewise blocked: \(u \notin S(w)\). This is a contradiction. \(\square \)

Fact 4

There are models in which \(S\) is transitive but \(R^*\) is not.

Proof

Define a model \(\langle W,S \rangle \) by setting \(W=\{0,1,-1,2\}\) and \(S=\{(0,1),(1,2), (0,2),\) \((-1,2)\}\). We note that \(S\) is transitive and that \(E=\{(x,x) : x \in W\} \cup \{(1,-1), (-1,1)\}\). Now \(1 \in S(0)\), but \(\{-1,1\}=E(1) \not \subseteq S(0)=\{1,2\}\ne \{2\}=S(1)\). It follows by Fact 3 that \(R^*\) is not transitive. \(\square \)

Fact 5

Transitivity of \(R^*\) does not trivialize the analysis (4).

Proof

Consider the model \(\langle \mathbb {N},S \rangle \) with \(S=\{(x,y) \in \mathbb {N}^2 : x < y\}\), whence \(E=\{(x,x) : x \in \mathbb {N}\}\). Consequently \(R^*=\{(x,y) \in \mathbb {N}^2 : x \le y\}\) and in particular \(R^*\) is transitive. Now, \((0,0) \in E \setminus S\). Further, \((0,1) \in S \setminus E\). It follows that \(E \ne R^*\ne S\). \(\square \)

Fact 6

The propositions \({ Jp }\) and \(\lnot K \lnot Kp\) are logically independent of each other.

Proof

Consider a model in which \(S(w)\) is justificatorily homogeneous, but there is \(x \notin S(w)\) with \(wEx\). Letting \(p = S(w)\), we have \(w \in { Jp }\). Suppose, then, that \(wR^*v\). We have \(wEv\), because \(S(w)\) is justificatorily homogeneous. Consequently \(vEx\) and therefore \(x \in R^*(v)\). Yet \(x \notin p\), whence \(w \notin \lnot K \lnot Kp\). That is, \({ Jp }\) does not entail \(\lnot K \lnot Kp\). Recall, then, the example of Alice and the tomato (Sect. 5). Let \(w\) (respectively \(v\)) be a scenario in which the tomato weighs 3.0 oz (respectively 3.5 oz). Let \(p = R^*(v)\). If \(u\) is a scenario in which the tomato weighs 2.25 oz, neither \(uEv\) nor \(u \in S(v)\). Consequently, \(u \in S(w)\) but \(u \notin R^*(v)\). Therefore \(S(w) \not \subseteq R^*(v)=p\), whence \(w \notin { Jp }\). On the other hand, we have \(w \in \lnot K \lnot Kp\), because \(wR^*v\) and \(v \in { Kp }\). That is, \(\lnot K \lnot Kp\) does not entail \({ Jp }\). \(\square \)

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Tulenheimo, T. The two faces of compatibility with justified beliefs. Synthese 193, 15–30 (2016). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-015-0742-0

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-015-0742-0

Keywords

Navigation