Skip to main content
Log in

Conceptual analysis and x-phi

  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This paper does two things. First, it argues for a metaphilosophical view of conceptual analysis questions; in particular, it argues that the facts that settle conceptual-analysis questions are facts about the linguistic intentions of ordinary folk. The second thing this paper does is argue that if this metaphilosophical view is correct, then experimental philosophy (or “x-phi”) is a legitimate methodology to use in trying to answer conceptual-analysis questions.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. For discussions of the kinds of things that x-phi can be used for, see, e.g., Knobe and Nichols (2007) and O’Neill and Machery (2014).

  2. The negative project of x-phi is (roughly) to criticize the use of intuitions in philosophy; see, e.g., Alexander et al. (2010).

  3. It’s still not entirely exhaustive because you might endorse a non-factualist view of type-C questions; i.e., you might claim that type-C questions aren’t settled by facts at all and that they don’t have factual answers.

  4. Of course, different philosophers give slightly different definitions of these terms, so there are actually more than two concepts that can be treated as Humean and libertarian kinds of free will. But we can ignore this complication here.

  5. Of course, if an analysis picks out an incoherent concept, call it C1, then there won’t be any (actual or possible) objects that instantiate C1, and you might think that facts like this could be relevant to whether C1 is identical to the relevant folk concept C, i.e., the one we’re trying to analyze. I will consider this suggestion below, in Sect. 6.5.

  6. See, e.g., Broad (1952), Strawson (1986), and Pereboom (2001).

  7. Consider the concept green and a Toyota; this seems more gerrymandered than green is; at any rate, it’s more arbitrary and it has a more complicated decompositional structure; but green Toyotas resemble each other more than green things do.

  8. The idea that facts about naturalness can be relevant to questions about meaning is sometimes called the best-candidate theory of meaning. This idea was first introduced by Merrill (1980) and developed by Lewis (1983, 1986). See also Sider (2001).

  9. I actually don’t think it’s true that rabbit (or unified, entire rabbit) is more natural than rabbit stage or simples arranged rabbitwise, but that obviously doesn’t matter here.

  10. Even if I stop trying to figure out what ‘C’ means in English and just try to figure out what it means in my own private language, this is still empirical. For, again, we don’t in general have a priori epistemic access to what we mean by our words.

  11. This doesn’t matter here, but we don’t need to endorse the existence of abstract objects to endorse this view of sentences like (O) and (M). For we can endorse a fictionalistic view according to which these sentences are strictly speaking false (because they refer to non-existent objects) but useful fictions. I defend this view in Balaguer (1998) and (2009).

  12. This is related to a widely discussed question, namely, the question of whether philosophers can be thought of as experts in relation to type-C questions. I would hesitate to put it this way; if they’re expert at anything in this connection, it’s knowing how to call up stable, reliable intuitions that accurately reflect their own concepts. Now, I certainly don’t think philosophers are infallible at this, but it’s plausible to suppose that they’re better at it than most people. For other discussions of these issues, see, e.g., Knobe and Nichols (2007) and Kauppinen (2007).

References

  • Alexander, J., Mallon, R., & Weinberg, J. M. (2010). Accentuate the negative. Review of Philosophy and Psychology, 1, 297–314.

  • Balaguer, M. (1998). Platonism and anti-platonism in mathematics. New York: Oxford University Press.

  • Balaguer, M. (2009). Fictionalism, theft, and the story of mathematics. Philosophia Mathematica, 17, 131–162.

  • Balaguer, M. (2010). Free will as an open scientific problem. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

  • Broad, C. D. (1952). Determinism, indeterminism, and libertarianism. In Ethics and the history of philosophy (pp. 195–217). London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.

  • Chalmers, D. (1996). The conscious mind. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goodman, N. (1955). Fact, fiction, and forecast. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jackson, F. (1998). From metaphysics to ethics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kaplan, D. (1989). Demonstratives. In J. Almog, J. Perry, & H. Wettstein (Eds.), Themes from Kaplan (pp. 481–563). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kauppinen, A. (2007). The rise and fall of experimental philosophy. Philosophical Explorations, 10, 95–118.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Knobe, J., & Nichols, S. (2007). An experimental philosophy manifesto. In J. Knobe & S. Nichols (Eds.), Experimental philosophy (pp. 3–14). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kornblith, H. (2013). Is there room for armchair theorizing in epistemology. In M. Haug (Ed.), Philosophical methodology: The armchair or the laboratory? (pp. 195–216). New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1983). New work for a theory of universals. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 61, 343–377.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1986). On the plurality of worlds. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Machery, E., Mallon, R., Nichols, S., & Stich, S. (2004). Semantics, cross-cultural style. Cognition, 92, B1–B12.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McKenna, M. (2014). The metaphysical importance of the compatibility question: Comments on Mark Balaguer’s Free will as an open scientific problem. Philosophical Studies, 169, 39–50.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Merrill, G. H. (1980). The model-theoretic argument against realism. Philosophy of Science, 47, 69–81.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mortensen, K., & Nagel, J. (forthcoming). Armchair-friendly experimental philosophy. In W. Buckwalter & J. Sytsma (Eds.), Blackwell companion to experimental philosophy.

  • Murray, D., & Nahmias, E. (2014). Explaining away incompatibilist intuitions. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 88, 434–467.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • O’Neill, E., & Machery, E. (2014). Experimental philosophy: What is it good for? In E. Machery & E. O’Neill (Eds.), Current controversies in experimental philosophy (pp. vii–xxix). New York: Routledge.

  • Pereboom, D. (2001). Living without free will. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. (1975). The meaning of ‘meaning’. In H. Putnam (Ed.), Language, mind and reality. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Rawls, J. (1971). A theory of justice. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sider, T. (2001). Four dimensionalism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sosa, E. (2007). Experimental philosophy and philosophical intuitions. Philosophical Studies, 132, 99–107.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stich, S., & Tobia, K. (forthcoming). Experimental philosophy and the philosophical tradition. In W. Buckwalter & J. Sytsma (Eds.), Blackwell companion to experimental philosophy.

  • Strawson, G. (1986). Freedom and belief. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vargas, M. (2009). Revisionism about free will: A statement and defense. Philosophical Studies, 144(1), 45–62.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weinberg, J., Nichols, S., & Stich, S. (2001). Normativity and epistemic intuitions. Philosophical Topics, 29, 429–460.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Williamson, T. (2007). The philosophy of philosophy. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Book  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I would like to thank David Pitt and Talia Bettcher for commenting on an earlier version of this paper. Also, versions of this paper were read at the University of Arizona and at a conference at the University of San Francisco, and I would like to thank the members of those two audiences. Special thanks go to Michael McKenna, Shaun Nichols, Terry Horgan, Uriah Kriegel, Carolina Sartorio and Manuel Vargas.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Mark Balaguer.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Balaguer, M. Conceptual analysis and x-phi. Synthese 193, 2367–2388 (2016). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-015-0848-4

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-015-0848-4

Keywords

Navigation