Skip to main content
Log in

Is ontology the key to understanding tense?

  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In this paper I claim that as bitter as the eternalist/presentist rivalry is, as far as both camps are concerned, a third position—which I defend—is more disturbing. The reason is that what eternalists and presentists agree on is more fundamental than what they disagree about. They agree that time carves, to use Orilia’s term, “ontological inventories.” This in a way answers the “fundamental question”—what is time? They disagree about the contents of the inventories, but that, I suggest, is a secondary issue. Thus, an argument against what they agree about would be more detrimental to their joint project—analyzing tense in ontological terms—than the internal disagreement they are engaged in. I develop this thesis by responding to Orilia’s paper “Two Metaphysical Perspectives on the Duration of the Present” (Orilia in Debates in the metaphysics of time. Bloomsbury, London/New York, pp 51–70, 2014). I criticize the specialized use Orilia makes of the notion of an “ontological inventory” in the context of the metaphysics of time, but also Quine’s approach to ontology, on which Orilia’s account relies. The gist of my criticism is that it is question begging to rely on the notion of an “ontological inventory” for giving content to the presentism/eternalism debate, and for arguing that there can’t be an alternative.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Orilia (2014, pp. 51–70).

  2. Meyer (2009), Savitt (2010).

  3. Orilia (2014, p. 55).

  4. Ibid., p. 51.

  5. Ibid., p. 56.

  6. Ibid., p. 58. There are several other places in which Orilia states that my position consists of an ontology.

  7. Ibid., p. 56.

  8. Ibid., p. 58.

  9. I should add that my analysis rejects the presentist notion that present events “exist” in some way events that are not present do not. I reject all reality claims in this context. Given this, Orilia certainly cannot infer that according to me parts of present events “exist”.

  10. One can wonder: does this mean Orilia is committed to Meinongism? Orilia seems to think it does not (Orilia 2016, pp. 592, 593) but fails to provide sufficient argumentation to back this claim.

  11. Orilia (2014, p. 52).

  12. Orilia adds in a footnote here: “I basically side with Meyer (2009, p. 97), when he urges that in looking at the A vs. B dispute we should not worry about how ‘real’ is used and should rather concentrate on what exists, according to the parties”.

  13. Orilia (2014, pp. 55–56). Note that similar statements are absent from his more recent paper of 2016.

  14. Thus, Orilia is presupposing from the outset that the task for the metaphysics of time is ontological, which explains his remark at the opening of his paper that “we not need not distinguish between ontology and metaphysics” (Ibid., p. 51).

  15. Appeals to events as ‘existing’ also appear in Orilia (2016), see e.g. on p. 596.

  16. Ibid., p. 60.

  17. Which must not be conflated with the general ‘exist’ as in “Higgs bosons exist”. This use of “exist” is not tenseless, rather, it states the existence in tensed time of a certain kind of entity.

  18. Putnam (1987, p. 16).

  19. See on this point Putnam (2013).

  20. In addition to the charge that my theory fails to break out from the eternalism/presentism framework, Orilia also complains that my “selection of theories from the debate is too incomplete and idiosyncratic to license any conclusion about a need to dismiss all sorts of A- and B-theories (Meyer 2009; Tallant 2009). In particular, as I see it, Dolev’s criticism of B-eternalism focuses on the new B-theory”. This is true. At the time it was not relevant to discuss it. In light of the revival it is currently seeing in the work of Oaklander and Orilia, I devote a great part of my (2014) to a critical examination of the old theory. The old theory is, admittedly, more attractive than its successor, but, as I argue in this paper, it too is grounded in, and argues for, an “inventory” of the eternalist brand. As for my “idiosyncratic selection”, it consisted of formulations of ontological theories that I thought were the most robust and illuminating, and in which the demarcation of the “ontological inventory” was the clearest. Thus, I still think that though he never meant it as a theory of time (though it became that more and more—his last book was Truth and the Past), Dummett’s antirealism gives the best defense of presentist ontology, and Mellor’s work continues to be a classical elaboration of eternalism. Discussing other works would have just resulted in unneeded repetitions.

  21. Scanlon (2014, p. 25).

  22. Scanlon (2014).

  23. In this vein let me remark that just as deriving eternalism from a tenseless language is circular, so deriving presentism from language’s inevitable tensedness would also be question begging.

References

  • Dolev, Y. (2007). Time and realism. Massachusetts: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dolev, Y. (2014). Motion and passage: The old B-theory and phenomenology. In L. N. Oaklander (Ed.), Debates in the metaphysics of time (pp. 31–50). London/New-York: Bloomsbury.

  • Meyer, U. (2009). Review of Yuval Dolev, ‘Time and Realism’ (MIT Press, 2007). Iyyun: The Jerusalem Philosophical Quarterly, 58, 91–100.

  • Orilia, F. (2016). Moderate presentism. Philosophical Studies, 173(3), 589–607.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Orilia, F. (2014). Two metaphysical perspectives on the duration of the present. In L. N. Oaklander (Ed.), Debates in the metaphysics of time (pp. 51–70). London/New-York: Bloomsbury.

    Google Scholar 

  • Orilia, F., & Oaklander, L. N. (2015). Do we really need a new B-theory of time? Topoi, 34(1), 157–170.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. (1987). The many faces of realism. Peru, IL: Open Court.

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. (2013). “Comments on Charles Parsons” Putnam on existence and ontology. In M. Baghramian (Ed.), Reading Putnam (pp. 202–204). New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Savitt, S. (2010). Relativity, locality and tense. In Mauricio Suárez, Mauro Dorato, & Miklós Rédei (Eds.), EPSA philosophical issues in the sciences (pp. 211–218). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Scanlon, T. M. (2014). Being realistic about reasons. Oxford: Oxford Uni. Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Schlesinger, G. N. (1980). Aspects of time. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tallant, J. (2009). Review of time and realism, by Yuval Dolev. Analysis, 69(2), 372–374.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Williamson, T. (2002). Necessary existents. In A. O’Hear (Ed.), Logic, thought and language (pp. 233–51). Cambridge: Cambridge Uni. Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Yuval Dolev.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Dolev, Y. Is ontology the key to understanding tense?. Synthese 195, 1741–1749 (2018). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-016-1303-x

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-016-1303-x

Keywords

Navigation