Skip to main content
Log in

The Game Between a Biased Reviewer and His Editor

  • Original Paper
  • Published:
Science and Engineering Ethics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This paper shows that, for a large range of parameters, the journal editor prefers to delegate the choice to review the manuscript to the biased referee. If the peer review process is informative and the review reports are costly for the reviewers, even biased referees with extreme scientific preferences may choose to become informed about the manuscript’s quality. On the contrary, if the review process is potentially informative but the reviewer reports are not costly for the referees, the biased reviewer has no incentive to become informed about the manuscript. Furthermore, if the reports are costly for referees but the peer review processes are not potentially informative, the biased reviewers will never become informed. In this paper, we also present a web resource that helps editors to experiment with the review process as a device for information transmission.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2
Fig. 3
Fig. 4
Fig. 5

Similar content being viewed by others

References

  • Braben, D. W. (2004). Pioneering research: A risk worth taking. Hoboken, NJ: Wiley-Interscience.

    Google Scholar 

  • Burnham, J. C. (1990). The evolution of editorial peer review. JAMA, 263(10), 1323–1329.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Callon, M. (2002). From science as an economic activity to socioeconomics of scientific research, the dynamics of emergent and consolidated techno-economic networks. In P. P. Mirowski & E. M. Sent (Eds.), Science bought and sold: Essays in the economics of science (pp. 277–317). Chicago: University of Chicago.

    Google Scholar 

  • Campanario, J. M., & Martin, Brian. (2004). Challenging dominant physics paradigms. Journal of Scientific Exploration, 18(3), 421–438.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chubin, D. E., & Hackett, E. J. (1990). Peerless science: Peer review and U.S. science policy. Stony Brook, NY: State University of New York Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Diermeier, D., & Feddersen, T. J. (2000). Information and congressional hearings. American Journal of Political Science, 44(1), 51–65.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fiske, D. W., & Fogg, L. (1990). But the reviewers are making different criticisms of my paper! Diversity and uniqueness in reviewer comments. American Psychologist, 45, 591–598.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fudenberg, D., & Tirole, J. (1991). Game theory. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. ISBN 9780262061414.

    Google Scholar 

  • Garcia, J. A., Rodriguez-Sanchez, R., & Fdez-Valdivia, J. (2015a). The author–editor game. Scientometrics, 104(1), 361–380. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11192-015-1566-x.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Garcia, J. A., Rodriguez-Sanchez, R., & Fdez-Valdivia, J. (2015b). Bias and effort in peer review. Journal of the Association for Information Science and Technology, 66(10), 2020–2030. https://doi.org/10.1002/asi.23307.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Garcia, J. A., Rodriguez-Sanchez, R., & Fdez-Valdivia, J. (2016). Authors and reviewers who suffer from confirmatory bias. Scientometrics, 109(2), 1377–1395. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11192-016-2079-y.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • House of Commons, Science and Technology Committee. (2011). Peer review in scientific publications. Eighth Report of Session 2010-2012, Volume II. The Stationery Office Limited.

  • Jelicic, M., & Merckelbach, H. (2002). Peer-review: Let’s imitate the lawyers!. Cortex, 38, 406–407.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn, Thomas S. (2012). The structure of scientific revolutions 50th anniversary edition (p. 264). Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Lee, Carole J., Sugimoto, Cassidy R., Zhang, Guo, & Cronin, Blaise. (2013). Bias in peer review. Journal of the American Society for Information Science and Technology, 64(1), 2–17.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mahoney, M. J. (1977). Publication prejudices: An experimental study of confirmatory bias in the peer review system. Cognitive Therapy and Research, 1(2), 161175.

    Google Scholar 

  • Martin, B. (1997). Suppression stories. Wollengong: Fund for Intellectual Dissent.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nature editorial. (2003). Coping with peer rejection. Nature, 425(6959), 645.

  • Rodriguez-Sanchez, R., Garcia, J. A., & Fdez-Valdivia, J. (2016). Evolutionary games between authors and their editors. Applied Mathematics and Computation, 273, 645–655. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.amc.2015.10.034.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Roth, W.-M. (2002). Editorial power/authorial suffering. Research in Science Education, 32(2), 215–240. https://doi.org/10.1023/A:1016030212572.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Souder, Lawrence. (2011). The ethics of scholarly peer review: A review of the literature. Learned Publishing, 24(1), 55–72.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Travis, G. D. L., & Collins, H. M. (1991). New light on old boys: Cognitive and institutional particularism in the peer review system. Science, Technology, & Human Values, 16(3), 322–341.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wesseley, S. (1998). Peer review of grant applications: What do we know? The Lancet, 352(9124), 301–305.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

This research was sponsored by the Spanish Board for Science, Technology, and Innovation under Grant TIN2017-85542-P, and co-financed with European FEDER funds.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to J. A. García.

Appendices

Appendix 1: Basic Model

The reviewer–editor game consists of two players, the uninformed editor and the biased reviewer. Players (editor and reviewer) have diverse scientific preferences over the consequences of editorial decisions. Let \({\mathscr {A}}\) denote the set of possible editorial decisions. Following Garcia et al. (2016), each editorial decision d selects a particular course of action from a set \({\mathscr {A}}\) of a large number of possibilities, \(d \in {\mathscr {A}}\): e.g., accept outright, without editorial revisions; accept, with one or more revisions; invite the manuscript authors to address specific concerns before a final decision is reached; reject, but recommending a resubmission after further work; reject on different grounds such as lack of novelty, insufficient originality, or major technical problems. A large number of possibilities for editorial decisions is represented assuming that \({\mathscr {A}} = {\mathbb {R}}\), i.e., editorial decisions are real numbers.

We suppose that the consequences of editorial decisions x are related to such decisions d by the linear function \(x = d - \beta\), with \(\beta \in \{ 0,1\}\) being the realization of a random variable that represents the stochastic relationship between editorial decisions d and their realized outcomes x. Here, \(\beta =1\) represents mistaken editorial decisions, such as, accepting the manuscript would result in future authors with lower quality standards, or its rejection would decrease the journal’s impact; whereas \(\beta =0\) represents better editorial decisions. When the reviewer–editor game begins, neither the editor nor the reviewer knows the value of parameter \(\beta\), but both of them have a common prior p which represents the probability that \(\beta =1\). When the author submits a manuscript for consideration to the journal, the editorial process involves one review stage preceding one decision stage. The sequence of events begins with two probabilistic choices by nature (see Fig. 2). In our model, the choices nature makes represent the source of uncertainty, i.e., how editorial decisions translate into consequences. Thus, nature chooses a value for the state of the world \(\beta\) according to probability \(p= \Pr [ \beta =1 ]\). Suppose that \(p_0\) denotes the conditional probability that a peer review produces message \(m=1\), given that \(\beta =0\). On the other hand, \(p_1\) denotes the conditional probability that a peer review produces message \(m=1\), given that \(\beta =1\). Then, nature chooses a value for the realized message of the peer review process (if it is held), \(m \in \{ 0,1\}\), according to conditional probabilities \(p_0\) and \(p_1\). If \(p_0 = p_1\) the peer review process is not informative. On the contrary, if \(p_0 = 0\) and \(p_1 =1\) then, after observing the peer-review message m, the editor knows the true state \(\beta\). Thus, the larger the ratio \(p_0/p_1\) the less informative the peer review process.

After nature makes its two choices for \(\beta\) and m, the editor decides whether to delegate the choice to review the manuscript to one expert (see Fig. 2). If the editor does not delegate the choice to evaluate the paper, she will learn the peer review message m at cost \(\varepsilon >0\). In this case, the editor chooses an editorial decision d without external review (e.g., special accept or special reject). Recall that given the large number of possibilities for editorial decisions, they are represented as real numbers. The subgame without external review is denoted by \(H_{WER}\).

When the editor delegates the manuscript’s evaluation to the expert, the submission is sent out for external review. The resulting subgame \(H_{ER}\) is a peer review game (see Fig. 2). In this game, the referee first decides whether he will read through the entire manuscript to learn the value of \(\beta\). This will be the ‘reading stage’ of the peer review game. If the reviewer reads through the submission, he incurs a cost \(k>0\) that includes time spent reading the manuscript and related literature to become versed in the topic. The referee’s choice is represented by s, with \(s=1\) if the reviewer decides to read the manuscript to become informed about its quality, and \(s=0\) otherwise. \(H_{0}\) represents a peer review subgame in which the referee has chosen not to become informed about the manuscript’s quality. Moreover, \(H_{1}\) denotes the peer review subgame in which the reviewer has chosen to read through the entire manuscript to become informed (see Fig. 2). In this case, she can condition her choice s on the observed value of \(\beta\).

Next, the reviewer decides whether to write a review report (see Fig. 2). This will be the ‘writing stage’ of the peer review. There, the referee chooses a, with \(a=1\) if he submits the review report in a timely manner, while a takes the value of 0 if the reviewer does not submit a timely report. When reviewers comment on a manuscript, they are likely to raise different issues. But reviewers incur a cost \(c \ge 0\) while they are drafting a review report rather than their own papers or doing other academic work. Therefore, if a review report is submitted, the editor observes the peer-review message \(m \in \{0,1 \}.\) If the review report is not submitted, the editor observes \(\phi\). After the handling editor observes one of the three possible messages, she makes an editorial decision (see Fig. 2).

After the editor makes an editorial decision, the outcome x is realized. Fiske and Fogg (1990) show that, in the typical case, different evaluations of the same manuscript have no critical point in common; instead, individuals wrote about different topics, and their recommendations about editorial decisions hardly showed any agreement. As a result of these differing opinions, the editor’s decision may not match all reviewers’ recommendations, and this issue will be much more relevant when we consider a biased reviewer and his editor. In our model, to represent different scientific opinions, we assume a spatial model of preferences over the realized outcomes in which outcomes are points in the one-Euclidean space. We also assume that an individual (editor or reviewer) is characterized by her ‘ideal point’ in that same space, and that outcomes are judged as good as they are close to the ideal point. Editor and reviewer are assumed to have specific utilities over a one-dimensional outcome space. The editor’s utility function is

$$\begin{aligned} u_{e} (x) = - | x - x_{e} | \end{aligned}$$
(1)

where \(x_{e}\) is the ideal point of the editor. The reviewer’s utility function is

$$\begin{aligned} u_{r} (x) = - | x - x_{r} | \end{aligned}$$
(2)

where \(x_{r}\) is the ideal point of the reviewer. To represent a biased reviewer, we assume that the ideal point of the reviewer is \(x_{r} \ge 1\), while the ideal point of the editor is \(x_{e}=0\).

Appendix 2: Proof of Proposition 1

Let \(\Delta\) represent the odds that nature chooses \(\beta =1\), and thus,

$$\begin{aligned} \Delta = \frac{p}{1-p} \end{aligned}$$

with \(p = \Pr [ \beta =1 ]\). Recall that the peer-review outcome is a message \(m \in \{ 0,1\}\), and nature chooses a value for the message m according to conditional probabilities \(p_0 = \Pr [ m = 1 / \beta =0]\) and \(p_1 = \Pr [ m = 1 / \beta =1]\), with the ratio \(p_0/p_1\) being the informative content of the peer review process.

Let h be a strategy profile for each peer-review subgame H. A Bayesian Nash equilibrium is defined as a strategy profile that maximizes the expected utility for each player given their beliefs. To refine the equilibria generated by the Bayesian Nash solution, we then apply the perfect Bayesian equilibrium that demands that subsequent play be optimal. Let \(h^*\) be a perfect Bayesian equilibrium for H.

Let \(EU_e (h_{WER}^*)\) be the expected utility to the editor of choosing a special decision without external review; \(EU_e (h_{ER}^*)\) be the expected utility to the editor of delegating the manuscript evaluation to the biased expert.

We have to prove that when the review cost \(\varepsilon\) at which the editor can learn the review message m is below a critical value, \(0< \varepsilon < (p_1 - p_0)/2\), and the odds that nature chooses \(\beta =1\), i.e. \(\Delta\), is in the range \(\left( 1, \frac{1- \varepsilon -p_0}{1 + \varepsilon - p_1} \right)\) then the editor prefers to review the manuscript herself because of its optimality, i.e., \(EU_e (h_{ER}^*) < EU_e (h_{WER}^*)\). Otherwise, when \(\Delta <1\) or \(\Delta > \frac{1- \varepsilon -p_0}{1 + \varepsilon - p_1}\)the editor prefers to delegate the choice to review the manuscript to the biased referee since \(EU_e (h_{ER}^*) > EU_e (h_{WER}^*)\).

Following equations (19) and (21) in Diermeier and Feddersen (2000), if \(\Delta \in \left( 1, \frac{1-p_0}{1 - p_1} \right)\), we have

$$\begin{aligned} EU_e (h_{ER}^*) - EU_e (h_{WER}^*) = \varepsilon + 2p - p p_1 + p_0 - pp_0 -1 \end{aligned}$$
(3)

Therefore, it follows that \(EU_e (h_{ER}^*) - EU_e (h_{WER}^*) >0\) if and only if

$$\begin{aligned} \varepsilon + 2p - p p_1 + p_0 - pp_0 -1 >0 \end{aligned}$$

or equivalently

$$\begin{aligned} p > \frac{1 -\varepsilon - p_0}{2 - p_0 - p_1} \end{aligned}$$

or equivalently

$$\begin{aligned} \Delta = \frac{p}{1-p} > \frac{1 -\varepsilon - p_0}{1 + \varepsilon - p_1} \end{aligned}$$

where \(\frac{1 -\varepsilon - p_0}{1 + \varepsilon - p_1} >1\) if and only if \(0< \varepsilon < (p_1 - p_0)/2\).

Again, from equations (19) and (21) in Diermeier and Feddersen (2000), if \(\Delta > \frac{1-p_0}{1 - p_1}\) or \(\Delta <1\) and \(c < p_0\), we have

$$\begin{aligned} EU_e (h_{ER}^*) - EU_e (h_{WER}^*) = \varepsilon \end{aligned}$$
(4)

Therefore, it follows that \(EU_e (h_{ER}^*) - EU_e (h_{WER}^*) >0\) since \(\varepsilon >0\).

If \(\Delta <p_0/p_1\) and \(c > p_0\), we have

$$\begin{aligned} EU_e (h_{ER}^*) - EU_e (h_{WER}^*) = \varepsilon + p\frac{p_1-p_0}{1-p_0} \end{aligned}$$
(5)

from equations (19) and (21) in Diermeier and Feddersen (2000). Therefore, it follows that \(EU_e (h_{ER}^*) - EU_e (h_{WER}^*) >0\) since \(\varepsilon + p\frac{p_1-p_0}{1-p_0}>0\).

If \(p_0/p_1< \Delta <1\) and \(c > p_0\), we have

$$\begin{aligned} EU_e (h_{ER}^*) - EU_e (h_{WER}^*) = \varepsilon + p - p p_1 + (1-p)p_0 - p\frac{1-p_1}{1-p_0} \end{aligned}$$
(6)

from equations (19) and (21) in Diermeier and Feddersen (2000). To see that

$$\begin{aligned} \varepsilon + p - p p_1 + (1-p)p_0 - p\frac{1-p_1}{1-p_0}>0 \end{aligned}$$

we divide by \((1-p)\) to obtain

$$\begin{aligned} \frac{\varepsilon }{1-p} + \Delta -\Delta p_1 + p_0 - \Delta \frac{1-p_1}{1-p_0} = \frac{\varepsilon }{1-p} + p_0 \left( 1 - \Delta \frac{1-p_1}{1-p_0} \right) >0 \end{aligned}$$

since \(\Delta <1\) and \(p_0/p_1 < 1\).

Appendix 3: Proof of Proposition 2

We now use these perfect equilibria to show how even biased reviewers become informed about the manuscript’s quality given that the peer review process is potentially informative (\(p_1 > p_0\)) and costly for the referee (\(c > 0\)). We simply have to compare the reviewer’s ex-ante expected utility for the peer review subgame in which the referee does not become informed, \(H_{0}\), with the reviewer’s ex-ante expected utility for the subgame in which the reviewer decides to become informed about the manuscript’s quality, \(H_{1}\).

Let h be a strategy profile for each peer-review subgame H. A Bayesian Nash equilibrium is defined as a strategy profile that maximizes the expected utility for each player given their beliefs. To refine the equilibria generated by the Bayesian Nash solution, we then apply the perfect Bayesian equilibrium that demands that subsequent play be optimal.

Let \(h^*\) be a perfect Bayesian equilibrium for H; \(EU_r (h_{0}^*)\) be the reviewer’s ex-ante expected utility from the peer review subgame in which the referee does not become informed about the manuscript’s quality; and \(EU_r (h_{1}^*)\) be the reviewer’s ex-ante expected utility from the subgame in which the reviewer decides to become informed about the manuscript’s quality. If \(EU_r (h_{1}^*) - EU_r (h_{0}^*) > 0\), then the biased reviewer will choose to become informed about the manuscript’s quality because of its optimality.

  1. 1.

    If the cost of writing reports is \(0< c < p_0\) and the odds that nature is in state one are \(\Delta <p_0/p_1\), then following Propositions 1 and 2 in Diermeier and Feddersen (2000), we have

    $$\begin{aligned} EU_r (h_{0}^*) = - x_r - p \end{aligned}$$
    (7)

    and

    $$\begin{aligned} EU_r (h_{1}^*) = \frac{p p_1 c - p_0 p - p c p_0 - x_r p_0}{p_0} - k \end{aligned}$$
    (8)

    Therefore, it follows that

    $$\begin{aligned} EU_r (h_{1}^*) - EU_r (h_{0}^*) = p c \frac{p_1-p_0}{p_0} - k > 0 \end{aligned}$$
    (9)

    since specialization cost k is low enough, \(k < pc\frac{(p_1-p_0)}{p_0}\), and \(p_1 > p_0\).

  2. 2.

    If reports are sufficiently costly to the reviewer, \(p_0< c < p_0 + p(p_1- p_0)\), and the odds of nature being in state one \(\beta =1\) are high enough, \(p_0/p_1 < \Delta\), then following Propositions 1 and 2 in Diermeier and Feddersen (2000) we have

    $$\begin{aligned} EU_r (h_{0}^*) = -c -p + p p_1 + p_0 - x_r - p p_0 \end{aligned}$$
    (10)

    and

    $$\begin{aligned} EU_r (h_{1}^*) = \frac{-p - p p_1 c + p p_1 + p c p_0 - x_r - p p_0}{1- p_0} - k \end{aligned}$$
    (11)

    Therefore, it follows that

    $$\begin{aligned} EU_r (h_{1}^*) - EU_r (h_{0}^*) = (c-p_0)\left( 1 - \frac{ p(p_1-p_0)}{1-p_0}\right) - k > 0 \end{aligned}$$
    (12)

    since specialization cost is low enough, \(k < (c-p_0)\left( 1 - \frac{ p(p_1-p_0)}{1-p_0}\right)\).

  3. 3.

    If reports are very costly to the reviewer, \(p_0 + p(p_1- p_0) < c\), then following Propositions 1 and 2 in Diermeier and Feddersen (2000) we have

    $$\begin{aligned} EU_r (h_{1}^*) - EU_r (h_{0}^*) = p\frac{(p_1-p_0) - c(p_1-p_0) }{1-p_0}- k \end{aligned}$$
    (13)

    Therefore, it follows that \(EU_r (h_{1}^*) - EU_r (h_{0}^*) >0\) since specialization cost is low enough, \(k < p\frac{(p_1-p_0) - c(p_1-p_0) }{1-p_0}\).

Appendix 4: Proof of Proposition 3

We have to prove that when the cost at which the referee can write a reviewer report is zero, \(c =0\), and the peer review is potentially informative, \(p_1 > p_0\), then a biased reviewer decides not to become informed about the manuscript’s quality because of its optimality, i.e., \(EU_r (h_{0}^*) > EU_r (h_{1}^*)\). We will distinguish two cases, the first when \(\Delta <p_0/p_1\) and the second when \(1> \Delta > p_0/p_1\).

If the odds that nature is in state one are \(\Delta <p_0/p_1\) then, following Propositions 1 and 2 in Diermeier and Feddersen (2000), we have

$$\begin{aligned} EU_r (h_{0}^*) = - x_r - p \end{aligned}$$
(14)

and following Proposition 3 in Diermeier and Feddersen (2000), we have, for the perfect Bayesian equilibrium \(h_{1}^*\), the maximum expected utility is \(-p - x_r - k\). Therefore, \(EU_r (h_{0}^*) > EU_r (h_{1}^*)\) since specialization cost \(k >0\).

If the odds that nature is in state one are \(1> \Delta > p_0/p_1\) then, following Propositions 1 and 2 in Diermeier and Feddersen (2000), we have

$$\begin{aligned} EU_r (h_{0}^*) = - x_r - p + p (p_1 -p_0) + p_0 \end{aligned}$$
(15)

and following Proposition 3 in Diermeier and Feddersen (2000), for the perfect Bayesian equilibrium \(h_{1}^*\), the maximum expected utility is \(-p - x_r - k\) or \(- x_r - p + p (p_1 - p_0) + p_0 - k\). Therefore, in both cases, \(EU_r (h_{0}^*) > EU_r (h_{1}^*)\) since specialization cost \(k >0\).

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

García, J.A., Rodriguez-Sánchez, R. & Fdez-Valdivia, J. The Game Between a Biased Reviewer and His Editor. Sci Eng Ethics 25, 265–283 (2019). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11948-017-9998-8

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11948-017-9998-8

Keywords

Navigation