A characterization of Σ11-reflecting ordinals

https://doi.org/10.1016/j.apal.2021.103009Get rights and content

Abstract

We consider clopen game formulae, analogous to the open game formulae widely studied in admissible recursion theory. This leads to characterizing the locally countable Σ11-reflecting ordinals α as those for which, over Lα, the clopen-game–definable relations are not precisely those which are both open-game and closed-game definable.

Introduction

An admissible ordinal α is Σ11-reflecting if for every γ<α and every Σ11 formula (in the language of set theory), we haveLαϕ(γ) implies β<α(γ<βLβϕ(γ)). This article is concerned with those ordinals α which are both Σ11-reflecting and locally countable, in the sense that every β<α is countable in Lα; its purpose is to characterize these ordinals in game-theoretic terms.

Let us recall some background. An ordinal α is said to be admissible if Lα is a model of KP, Kripke-Platek set theory. Every Σ11-reflecting ordinal is admissible and a limit of admissible ordinals. Given an admissible α, a subset A of α is α-recursively enumerable (α-r.e.) if it is Σ1-definable over Lα; it is α-recursive if both A and αA are α-r.e. By usual methods, finite or ω-length sequences of elements of α which belong to Lα can be coded by single elements of α, so we may speak of α-recursive sets of sequences in α, etc.

A classical theorem due to Kripke and Platek states that the supremum of lengths of recursive wellorderings of ω is ω1ck, the least admissible ordinal greater than ω. An admissible ordinal α is said to be Gandy if the supremum of α-recursive wellorderings of subsets of α is α+, the least admissible ordinal greater than α. Gostanian [9] has characterized the locally countable Σ11-reflecting ordinal as those which are not Gandy. By a theorem of Abramson and Sacks [2], (ωωL)+ is Gandy, so not every Gandy ordinal is locally countable. Harrington (unpublished) has shown that, in L, the least uncountable Gandy ordinal has cardinality ω1.

The least Σ11-reflecting ordinal is commonly denoted by σ11. Aczel and Richter [4] showed that this is the closure ordinal for Σ11 inductive definitions; by a theorem of Grilliot,1 it is thus the closure ordinal for monotone Σ11 inductive definitions. Solovay (see Kechris [11] or Moschovakis [14]) showed that for every Σ20 game on N, if Player I has a winning strategy for it, then she has one in Lσ11 (and this is the least such ordinal); this has applications in the reverse mathematics of determinacy (see e.g., Tanaka [18]). Ackerman, Freer, and Lubarsky [3] show that σ11 is the least ordinal which is not parallel-feedback computable. Other characterizations can be found in [7]. By a theorem of Aanderaa [1], σ11 is greater than π11, the least Π11-reflecting ordinal. σ11 is stable precisely to the supremum of the σ11-recursive wellorderings (see [5]).

We define the classes

,
, and
. The definition makes sense for arbitrary acceptable structures, though we restrict our attention to admissible initial segments of the constructible hierarchy. Let α be an admissible ordinal and fix a simple coding scheme assigning ordinals α0,α1,,αn smaller than α to finite tuples (α0,α1,,αn) of ordinals smaller than α. We say that a subset of α is
(“open-game definable”) if it can be defined over Lα by a formula of the formα0αα1αα2αnNφ(α0,,αn,β,x) where β<α is a parameter and φ is Σ1. Here, the infinite quantifier string is interpreted in the natural way: (1) is said to hold if Player I has a winning strategy in the infinite game in which Players I and II alternate turns playing ordinals αi<α, after which Player I wins if and only if φ(α0,,αn,β,x) holds in Lα, for some initial subsequence α0,,αn of the play. We refer to these games as α-open games.

The

sets are those definable over Lα by a formula of the formα0αα1αα2αnNφ(α0,,αn,β,x) where β<α is a parameter and φ is Π1. Observe that we assume (by adding dummy moves if necessary) that all α-open and all α-closed games begin with a move by Player I. These games are determined by the Gale-Stewart theorem [8], so the
sets are precisely those whose complements are
.

Finally, we may define the class of

(“clopen-game definable”) subsets of α to be those definable over Lα by a formula of the form (1) with the added condition that there exist β<α and a Σ1 formula φ such that for every (α0,α1,)αω and every xLα, exactly one of the following holds:
  • (1)

    there exist nN such that φ(α0,,αn,β,x), or

  • (2)

    there exist nN such that φ(α0,,αn,β,x).

Associated to each of these sets is an α-clopen game in which Players I and II alternate turns playing ordinals αi<α, after which Player I wins if and only if φ(α0,,αn,β,x) holds in Lα for some initial subsequence α0,,αn of the play. The formulae φ and φ, as well as the parameters β,β, and x, can be regarded as the “rules” of the game, and as x varies, the rules might differ (although they are given uniformly). By the clopenness condition, Player II wins if and only if φ(α0,,αn,β,x) holds in Lα for some initial subsequence α0,,αn of the play. We refer to{(α0,α1,)αω:nNLαφ(α0,,αn,β,x)} as the payoff of the game. The main relevant property of α-clopen games is that every time one is played, the outcome is decided after only a finite number of turns.

Remark 1

If α=ω, then α-open (closed, clopen) games are equivalent to the usual open (closed, clopen) games on natural numbers, and their payoff sets are open (closed, clopen) in the product space ωω.

We shall prove the following theorem:

Theorem 2

Let α be a locally countable admissible ordinal. The following are equivalent:

  • (1)

    α is Σ11-reflecting;

  • (2)

    over Lα,

    .

Section snippets

Proof of the theorem

We begin with a lemma which asserts that the theory of many models of the form Lβ is

-definable over Lα. Here, we assume that formulas in first-order logic are coded by ordinals through some fixed Gödel numbering.

Lemma 3

Suppose α is an admissible ordinal and suppose that there is an α-recursive wellordering of a subset α of length β. Then, the theory of Lβ is

-definable over Lα. More specifically, the set Tβ of all formulas φ in the language of set theory with additional constants for

Acknowledgements

I would like to thank the anonymous reviewer for his or her comments and suggestions. This work was partially supported by FWO grant 3E017319 and by FWF grant I-4513.

References (19)

There are more references available in the full text version of this article.

Cited by (0)

View full text