Elsevier

Fuzzy Sets and Systems

Volume 401, 15 December 2020, Pages 150-162
Fuzzy Sets and Systems

Reflections on an old problem: That of preserving the logical forms and symmetry

https://doi.org/10.1016/j.fss.2019.10.008Get rights and content

Abstract

This paper is devoted to analyze and discuss some of the new aspects about the preservation of the logical forms appearing in ordinary reasoning and fuzzy logic. Considering a Basic Fuzzy Algebra (BFA) as the basic formal model for representing imprecise predicates, several classical properties of logical forms which can be not valid depending on the representation of the logical connectives in a BFA are studied. Special emphasis is put on the general symmetry property, or its absence in some logical forms that, in some particular cases and in some sense, can become symmetrical as they are, for instance, the linguistic negation, the law of perfect repartition, or the additive law of measures. In any case, the difference between what is supposed in a mathematical model and what can be checked in the reality cannot be forgotten since any reality, and the study of the ordinary reasoning in natural language is a clear example of that, is but an ‘observed reality’. Anyway, if what is in a mathematical fuzzy model is not always symmetrical, and since these models represent linguistic statements affected by imprecision and uncertainty, it can be concluded that, in general, neither plain language, nor commonsense or ordinary reasoning, show the same level of symmetry exhibited by the specialized language and the deductive reasoning allowing mathematical proofs.

Introduction

For most, even illustrated and well educated people, “reasoning” consists in deducing, rationality consists in deductive reasoning, and irrationality in any other way of reasoning. Of course, this kind of “ideology” is deeply mistaken since in more than the 75% of the times people ordinarily reasons by means of abductive, speculative, or analogical forms that are, essentially, conjectural forms of reasoning [17]. For instance, in science the establishment of hypotheses is one of its main objectives, and it is often reached by analogy with some previously known and similar problems. It should be pointed out that all those types of non deductive reasoning do not show the typically deductive property of monotonicity, that is, the growing of the number of conclusions when that of premises grows. On the contrary, the number of conclusions either can decrease, or there is no any foreseeable property of monotonicity; that is, these types of reasoning are either anti-monotonic, or just non-monotonic. Rationality is shown when arguing by means of reasons, when the conclusions of reasoning are reached from the best available previous information or premises, and through the most convincing than possible methodology that can support them in the base of the given premises. Nobody will say that a scientist that makes an apparently well founded hypothesis on something, is irrational by just this fact. Hence, the branch of Philosophy known as Pragmatics cannot be reduced to only taking into account deductive reasoning; to confuse inference with deduction. This even considering, in a first place, that formal deduction is the safest way of searching for conclusions, but not ignoring, in a second place, that the word “deduction” is just understood as “formal deduction” that strongly requires to be done in a given formal framework. A formal framework like it is a Boolean algebra for the classical propositional logic, or the orthomodular lattice of the closed linear subspaces of an infinite dimensional Hilbert Space for quantum physics' logic. Such a formal framework almost never is at our hands when doing ordinary, everyday, or commonsense reasoning. What in ordinary reasoning is sometimes called “deduction”, and although it should be necessarily monotonic, is not exactly “formal deduction”, and yet deserves a comprehensive study. For instance, it is not clear if in commonsense deduction, either the premises are to be considered as conclusions, or the set of conclusions of the conclusions is coincidental with this last.

One of the topics that Pragmatics should consider is the analysis of the play of the logical constants in the language that, thanks to some of them, allow to establish the so-called logical forms as we will see later, for instance, the associative and the commutative laws of the constant “and”. All that, places the problem known by the “preservation of the logical forms” into a new perspective, and in particular it seems to show that the term “logical constants” does be currently avoided.

To illustrate such a new perspective it is a good example to consider the case of the linguistic use of imprecise predicates, something that is pervasive in common speeches [19]. As it is known the standard way for representing vague predicates is that facilitated by fuzzy sets. If ([0,1]X,,+,) is a Basic Fuzzy Algebra (BFA) [14] in which the imprecise linguistic expressions are represented, the classical law (or form) of “perfect repartition”, A=AB+AB, is not generally verified except if, for instance, the BFA is isomorphic to that given by the triplet of functionally expressible connectives =W, +=prod, and =1id[0,1], with W(a,b)=max(0,a+b1), prod(a,b)=a+bab, and a=1a. And it should be pointed out that the standard algebras of fuzzy sets isomorphic to the standard algebra ([0,1]X,W,prod,1id[0,1]) are neither distributive, nor dual, nor verify the laws of non-contradiction and excluded-middle. That is, in the setting of fuzzy sets, perfect repartition, duality, distributivity, non-contradiction, and excluded-middle, are not coexistent logical forms. Of course, this example places the preservation of logical forms in a different perspective than that usual in Philosophy. Let's notice again that perfect repartition follows, in the case of precise predicates that is, in the formal setting of Boolean algebras, from distributivity and excluded-middle: AB+AB=A(B+B)=A1=A.

This formal reasoning shows that in the case of quantum logic, where distributivity is known to not holding, the “form” A=AB+AB cannot be used for all A and B. Hence, both in the precise speeches of quantum logic, and in the imprecise ones of common language, it is not generally possible to freely use this form. In the second case, it is possible to use the form, but under the mandatory condition of working in a BFA allowing it, and like it is, for instance, ([0,1]X,W,prod,1id[0,1]). Hence, the current use of the constants “and”, “or”, and “not”, is essential for taking into account the preservation of the “perfect repartition” form.

Obviously, these argumentations place the problem of the preservation of logical forms in a new perspective. The ordinary reasoning shows this problem in multiple examples and Fuzzy Sets Theory has allowed to study some of those cases of lack of preservation of some common properties of the logical forms depending on the modeling of the logical operators used. However, a representation of logical operators closest to ordinary reasoning remains open and Fuzzy Logic is the best known field to continue deepening in this field.

Section snippets

Logical form and grammatical form: a historical review of some agreements and disagreements (with a final eye on the symmetry)

Language is a cognitive tool for representing the world and explaining it. Explanations are given by offering arguments and logic is the science that diagnoses its correctness. The arguments are made by chained sentences and, so, the logical form of the arguments should be related with the grammatical structure of the sentences.

Regarding the relationship between logic and language there are, at least, two opposing views: one sees ordinary language as a veil or mask of what is really meant and

On fuzzy sets, meaning and symmetry

Fuzzy sets, introduced by Lotfi A. Zadeh in 1965 [26], essentially try to mathematically represent the big amount of words that, in plain language, are used with an imprecise, or flexible meaning and, as some “Sorites” type arguments show, cannot be represented by sets; simultaneously, in particular those that are with a precise, or rigid meaning, are also represented by Zadeh's theory ([9], [10], [13], [15], [16]). That is, the theory of fuzzy sets includes as a particular case that of

Some hints on fuzzy logic, inference, and symmetry

Mainly, fuzzy logic deals with the reasoning with imprecise concepts, that is, the concepts that can be represented by the membership functions of the fuzzy sets generated by the words naming them; fuzzy logic is based on fuzzy sets, the operations between them, and their associated linguistic variables. Even if it is not universal but contextual, fuzzy logic is a formal calculus with the fuzzy sets that try to mimic such an imprecise type of commonsense reasoning; anyway, it is mainly devoted

Antonyms, negations, and symmetry

As it was said, negation is not always involutive, symmetrical; a statement p and its double negation (p) can be either inferentially not comparable, p(p), or verify p<(p)—weak negation—, or (p)<p—intuitionistic negation—, or both in which case p and (p) are inferentially equivalent, p(p), and the negation is called strong; but the situation is different with antonyms or opposites [5]. The negation of p, regardless of how it is contextually represented in fuzzy logic by negation

Symmetry and some formal laws

In addition to the symmetry of relations, that of membership functions, and the symmetric character of antonyms and also of some negations, it can be considered some ‘logical’ laws that show some kind of symmetry. Let's only stop at those of ‘duality’ and ‘perfect repartition’.

The two laws of duality,(p+q)=pq, and (pq)=p+q, valid in the classical calculus with rigid concepts, do not always hold with the flexible ones. For instance, with membership functions and the connectives ⋅

Conclusion

As it has been shown, symmetry is pervasive among the concepts concerning the logical calculus with precise concepts, but it reduces considerably when passing to the calculus with imprecise concepts given by the algebras of fuzzy sets. A reason for it lies in the fact that the almost perfect mathematical model Boolean algebras offer for the first, just disappears within the second in which the mathematical model is not unique, and in all of them the big number of laws that Boolean algebras

Acknowledgements

The authors dedicate this paper to Professor Miguel Delgado, to celebrate their joint and long- term friendship.

References (27)

  • S. Adolphs et al.

    Caught between professional requirements and interpersonal needs: vague language in healthcare contests

  • Aristotle, Prior Analytics I.4-6, Robin Smith (ed.), Hackett Publishing Company,...
  • C. Alsina

    On a family of connectives for fuzzy sets

    Fuzzy Sets Syst.

    (1985)
  • C. Alsina et al.

    Charming Proofs. A Journey Into Elegant Mathematics

    (2010)
  • A.R. de Soto et al.

    On antonym and negate in fuzzy logic

    Int. J. Intell. Syst.

    (1999)
  • A.R. de Soto

    Graduated conjectures

  • G. Frege

    Function and concept

  • G. Lakoff

    Hedges: a study in meaning criteria and the logic of fuzzy concepts

  • J.N. Mordeson et al.

    Fuzzy Mathematics: An Introduction for Engineers and Scientists

    (2010)
  • H.T. Nguyen et al.

    A First Course on Fuzzy Logic

    (1999)
  • K. Popper

    Conjectures and Refutations: The Growth of Scientific Knowledge

    (1987)
  • V.W.O. Quine

    Two dogmas of empiricism

    Philos. Rev.

    (1951)
  • D. Ruan et al.

    Fuzzy Logic: A Spectrum of Theoretical and Practical Issues

    (2007)
  • Cited by (0)

    1

    This research was funded by the Spanish Ministry of Economy and Competitiveness and the European Regional Development Fund (ERDF/FEDER program) under grants TIN2014-56633-C3-1-R and TIN2017-84796-C2-1-R.

    View full text