Elsevier

Operations Research Letters

Volume 44, Issue 5, September 2016, Pages 672-675
Operations Research Letters

On the conjoint estimation of inconsistency and intransitivity of pairwise comparisons

https://doi.org/10.1016/j.orl.2016.07.017Get rights and content

Abstract

Consistency and transitivity are two desirable properties of valued preferences which, however, are seldom satisfied in real-world applications. Different indices have been proposed to measure inconsistency and intransitivity separately, and recently scholars tried to merge these two concepts and use them in concert to estimate the irrationality of preferences. In this paper we formally investigate the existence (or non-existence) of functions capable of capturing both phenomena at the same time.

Introduction

Very often, in the practice of operations research and multi-criteria decision making, mathematical models require the elicitation of weights of alternatives and criteria. In this framework, psychological reasons related to our cognitive limits were among the factors triggering the introduction of the method of pairwise comparisons. Such a method allows the derivation of weights of alternatives from a set of pairwise comparisons between them. Different representations of valued preferences have been proposed in the literature, but the most widely known is probably the multiplicative model, which is also (but not exclusively) employed in the Analytic Hierarchy Process  [17]. It is to the multiplicative model that the findings of this paper directly apply, bearing in mind that the same conclusions can be extended to other representations of preferences, by means of appropriate group isomorphisms  [4]. Formally, in its multiplicative form, the method of pairwise comparisons assumes that, given a set of alternatives {1,,n}, a decision maker can express pairwise judgments aij>0i,j{1,,n} on them, where the value of aij is an estimation of the ratio wi/wj where wi and wj are the weights of i and j, respectively. A pairwise comparison matrix A=(aij)n×n is nothing else but a convenient mathematical structure where the preferences of a decision maker in the form of pairwise comparisons are collected. Since reciprocity aij=1/aji is usually assumed, a pairwise comparison matrix has the following canonical and simplified forms, respectively: A=(aij)n×n=(a11a12a1na21a22a2nan1an2ann)=(1a12a1n1a121a2n1a1n1a2n1). In the following, we will call A the set of all pairwise comparison matrices,A={A=(aij)n×n|aij>0,aijaji=1i,j,n2}.

One reasonable expectation is that, for instance, a decision maker stating that wi is 2 times wj (aij=2) and wj is 3 times wk (ajk=3), should also state that wi is 6 times wk (aik=6). This intuition translates into the following condition, according to which a pairwise comparison matrix is consistent if and only if aik=aijajki,j,k. Such a condition of consistency is often called cardinal consistency. In the following, we call AA the set of all consistent pairwise comparison matrices, i.e.  A={A=(aij)n×n|AA,aik=aijajki,j,k}. Among others, Saaty claimed that a matrix should be ‘near consistent’ to represent the true preferences of a decision maker. Thus, various functions I:AR, usually called inconsistency indices, have been proposed in the literature to measure the deviation of a matrix from the consistent condition (1). One can refer to a review and numerical study of these indices  [2]. Recently, a set of properties of inconsistency indices was introduced and studied  [1], [3]. Since these properties are going to be used to derive the main results of this paper, it is convenient to recall them here.

  • P1:

    Index I attains its minimum value νR if and only if A is consistent, i.e. I(A)=νAAAA.

  • P2:

    Index I is invariant under permutation of alternatives, i.e. I(A)=I(PAPT)AA and for all permutation matrices P.

  • P3:

    As the preferences are intensified the inconsistency cannot decrease. Define A(b)=(aijb)n×n. Formally, I(A(b))I(A)AA and b>1.

  • P4:

    Consider a matrix AA and the matrix Apq(δ) which is the same as A except for entries apq and aqp which are replaced by apqδ and aqpδ, respectively. Then, I(Apq(δ)) is a quasi-convex function of δ[0,[ with minimum in δ=1.

  • P5:

    Index I is a continuous function of the entries of A for all AA.

  • P6:

    Index I is invariant under inversion of preferences, i.e. I(A)=I(AT)AA.

Although the necessity of these properties to characterize inconsistency indices is a moot point, knowing that a function satisfies P1–P6 certainly provides evidence that the function behaves reasonably when used to quantify the inconsistency.

Motivated by the excessive restrictiveness of the condition of consistency, a weaker condition has been often used to assess the rationality of pairwise comparisons. Its motivation is deeply grounded in rational choice theory where “transitivity of preferences is a fundamental principle shared by most major contemporary rational, prescriptive, and descriptive models of decision making”  [15]. The principle of transitivity simply states that a decision maker preferring i to j (aij1) and j to k (ajk1), should also prefer i to k (aik1). Thus, transposing this principle into our framework we obtain that a pairwise comparison matrix is transitive if and only if aij1andajk1aik1i,j,k. In the literature, the concept of transitivity has equivalently gone under the name of ordinal consistency, or weakly stochastic transitivity in the context of reciprocal relations  [6]. Similarly to the case of inconsistency, indices have been proposed to assess the extent of the violation of this condition in pairwise comparison matrices. Prominent examples are the studies by Kendall and Babington Smith  [11], Jensen and Hicks  [10] and Iida  [9]. It appears that a common idea behind all these evaluations of the degree of intransitivity is that the more violations of condition (2) there are in the preferences, the more intransitive these should be considered. Hence, we can formulate the following property, seemingly important to characterize the extent of the violation of transitivity, which requires a type of monotonicity of the function I with respect to the number of cycles in the preferences.

  • P7:

    Let C(A) be the number of violations of condition (2) in AA, and consider two pairwise comparison matrices A,BA of the same order. Then a function I satisfies P7 if C(A)C(B) implies I(A)I(B).

Recently, the interest of researchers has been drawn by the connections between consistency and transitivity. Kwiesielewicz and Van Uden  [13] underlined that consistency implies transitivity, but not vice versa. Li and Ma  [14] proposed a bi-objective optimization problem to minimize two objective functions related to inconsistency and intransitivity. By means of computational experiments, Siraj et al.  [18] showed that the well-known index CR has problems to quantify the intransitivity of preferences. Later on, Siraj et al.  [19] proposed both an inconsistency index (congruence) and an intransitivity index (dissonance) and they used the latter to provide additional information on the former. Very recently, Cooper and Yavuz  [5] acknowledged the existence of studies on (i) cardinal inconsistency, (ii) ordinal inconsistency, (iii) a combination of both. All in all, the literature is rich of heuristic approaches to embed both consistency and transitivity in the same mathematical model to analyze and improve the rationality of the decision maker  [8], [21], [20].

Section snippets

Results

Given the growing interest in the conjoint use of inconsistency and intransitivity, it seems relevant to try to answer the following research question.

    RQ:

    Is there any function I:AR capable of capturing both concepts of inconsistency and intransitivity of the preferences in A?

A tentative step towards an answer could come from checking whether there exists any function I:AR satisfying the properties P1–P6 for inconsistency indices and also P7 for intransitivity indices. The existence of such

Discussion

This note tried to answer the research question (RQ) related to the existence of a function capable of capturing the concepts of inconsistency and intransitivity at once. It was concluded that the answer depends on what definition of inconsistency and intransitivity we use. In other words, it depends on what properties we require this hypothetical function to satisfy. More specifically, it was shown that if continuity is required to hold, then such a function does not exist. Conversely, if

Acknowledgment

This research has been financially supported by the Academy of Finland (Decision No. 277135).

References (21)

There are more references available in the full text version of this article.

Cited by (9)

  • Distance-based measures of incoherence for pairwise comparisons

    2020, Knowledge-Based Systems
    Citation Excerpt :

    To the best of our knowledge, no index has been proposed to measure the violation of the restricted max–max transitivity. In spite of these efforts, it has been remarked the impossibility of reconciling simple counts with an approach which could capture the intensity of preferences [22]. Thus, this paper aims at introducing new incoherence indices to measure, by a cardinal point of view, the violation of coherence conditions other than consistency.

  • Inconsistency in the ordinal pairwise comparisons method with and without ties

    2018, European Journal of Operational Research
    Citation Excerpt :

    Their index allows the inconsistency degree of a set composed of binary pairwise comparisons to be determined. The results obtained by the authors were the inspiration for many other researchers in different fields of science (Bozóki, o, Poesz, & Temesi, 2013; Brunelli, 2016; Maas, Bezembinder, & Wakker, 1995; Parizet, Guyader, & Nosulenko, 2008; Siraj, Mikhailov, & Keane, 2015). Although the ordinal pairwise comparisons method is a really powerful and useful tool facilitating the right decision, in practice we very often face the problem that the two alternatives seem to be equally preferred.

  • A fuzzy-grey multicriteria decision making model for district heating system

    2018, Applied Thermal Engineering
    Citation Excerpt :

    The matrix is consistent if (aij/aji)(ajk/akj) = (aik/aki) for each i, j, k. In practice, the matrix may contain some level of inconsistency [24]. This means that we can solve the weights from the Eq. (3) only in the least squares (LSQ) sense.

  • Introduction

    2023, Multiple Criteria Decision Making
  • Ordinal Inconsistency

    2023, Multiple Criteria Decision Making
  • A New Consistency Coefficient in the Multi-criteria Decision Analysis Domain

    2021, Lecture Notes in Computer Science (including subseries Lecture Notes in Artificial Intelligence and Lecture Notes in Bioinformatics)
View all citing articles on Scopus
View full text