Skip to main content Accessibility help
×
Hostname: page-component-76fb5796d-22dnz Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-26T11:09:29.605Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

5 - Dodgson's Rule and Young's Rule

from Part I - Voting

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 May 2016

Ioannis Caragiannis
Affiliation:
University of Patras, Greece
Edith Hemaspaandra
Affiliation:
Rochester Institute of Technology, United States of America
Lane A. Hemaspaandra
Affiliation:
University of Rochester, United States of America
Felix Brandt
Affiliation:
Technische Universität München
Vincent Conitzer
Affiliation:
Duke University, North Carolina
Ulle Endriss
Affiliation:
Universiteit van Amsterdam
Jérôme Lang
Affiliation:
Université de Paris IX (Paris-Dauphine)
Ariel D. Procaccia
Affiliation:
Carnegie Mellon University, Pennsylvania
Get access

Summary

Overview

Dodgson's and Young's election systems, dating from 1876 and 1977, are beautiful, historically resonant election systems. Surprisingly, both of these systems turn out to have highly intractable winner-determination problems: The winner problems of these systems are complete for parallel access to NP. This chapter discusses both the complexity of these winner-determination problems and approaches—through heuristic algorithms, fixed-parameter algorithms, and approximation algorithms—to circumventing that complexity.

Introduction, Election-System Definitions, and Results Overview

Charles Lutwidge Dodgson, better known under his pen name of Lewis Carroll, was a mathematics tutor at Oxford. In his 1876 pamphlet, “A Method of Taking Votes on More than Two Issues” (Dodgson, 1876), printed by the Clarendon Press, Oxford and headed “not yet published,” he defined an election system that is compellingly beautiful in many ways, and yet that also turned out to be so subtle and complex, also in many ways, that it has in recent decades been much studied by computational social choice researchers.

Dodgson's election system is very simply defined. An election will consist of a finite number of voters, each voting by casting a linear order over (the same) finite set of candidates. (Recall that linear orders are inherently antisymmetric, i.e., are “tie-free.”) A Condorcet winner (respectively, weak Condorcet winner) is a candidate a who, for each other candidate b, is preferred to b by strictly more than half (respectively, by at least half) of the voters. It is natural to want election systems to be Condorcet-consistent, that is, to have the property that if there is a Condorcet winner, he or she is the one and only winner under the election system. Dodgson's system is Condorcet-consistent. In fact, the system is defined based on each candidate's closeness to being a Condorcet winner. Dodgson's view was that whichever candidate (or candidates if there is a tie for closest) was “closest” to being Condorcet winners should be the winner(s), and his system is a realization of that view.

In particular, the Dodgson score of a candidate, a, is the smallest number of sequential exchanges of adjacent candidates in preference orders such that after those exchanges a is a Condorcet winner. All candidates having the smallest Dodgson score among the candidates are the winner(s) in Dodgson's system.

Type
Chapter
Information
Publisher: Cambridge University Press
Print publication year: 2016

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Save book to Kindle

To save this book to your Kindle, first ensure coreplatform@cambridge.org is added to your Approved Personal Document E-mail List under your Personal Document Settings on the Manage Your Content and Devices page of your Amazon account. Then enter the ‘name’ part of your Kindle email address below. Find out more about saving to your Kindle.

Note you can select to save to either the @free.kindle.com or @kindle.com variations. ‘@free.kindle.com’ emails are free but can only be saved to your device when it is connected to wi-fi. ‘@kindle.com’ emails can be delivered even when you are not connected to wi-fi, but note that service fees apply.

Find out more about the Kindle Personal Document Service.

Available formats
×

Save book to Dropbox

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Dropbox.

Available formats
×

Save book to Google Drive

To save content items to your account, please confirm that you agree to abide by our usage policies. If this is the first time you use this feature, you will be asked to authorise Cambridge Core to connect with your account. Find out more about saving content to Google Drive.

Available formats
×