Hostname: page-component-8448b6f56d-t5pn6 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-24T17:16:27.158Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

A simplified account of validity and implication for quantificational logic

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  12 March 2014

Hugues Leblanc*
Affiliation:
Temple University

Extract

As those of us who instruct him are well aware, customary accounts of validity and implication for quantificational logic often bewilder the novice. For his benefit, I present here an account of validity, due (in effect) to the late E. W. Beth, and two accounts of implication, one my own, the other Jaakko Hintikka's, which add up to what the better textbooks say, but, making no mention whatever of domains, say it far more simply.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © Association for Symbolic Logic 1968

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

2 I take ‘∼’ and ‘⊃’ to be the only primitive connectives of QC (and hence of SC), and ‘∀’ to be the only primitive quantifier letter of QC.

3 For the sake of definiteness the individual variables of QC may be understood to run in the following alphabetical order: ‘x’, ‘y’, ‘z’, ‘x’, ‘x́’, ‘ý’, etc.

4 Like conventions will hold mutatis mutandis when X or Y both are individual constants rather than variables. See §8.

5 I owe the reference to Professor Bas C. van Fraassen. What Beth showed is that a formula A of QC is valid in the standard sense if and only if it is satisfied by every assignment of truth-values to the atomic formulas of QC. But the truth-values Beth assigns to the atomic formulas of QC that do not figure among the subformulus of A are clearly idle, and hence may be discarded. The reader may wish to verify that in clause (d) of our definition of satisfaction B(Y/X) cannot do duty for B[Y/X].

6 This because every individual variable of QC may, for example, be assigned the same member d of a given domain D and ‘ƒ’ be assigned some superset of {d} short of D, in which case each one of ‘ƒ(x)’, ‘ƒ(y)’, ‘ƒ(z)’, etc., comes out true in D, but ‘(∀x)ƒ(x)’ does not. I owe the example to Professor Richmond H. Thomason.

7 I.e., where Χ1 is the member of Σ′ correlated under M with X That A1–111) cannot do duty here for A1–111], was brought to my attention by Professor van Fraassen.

8 A like convention will hold mutatis mutandis when Χ or Υ or both are individual constants rather than variables. See §8.

9 I follow here Hailperin's handling of vacuous quantifications (see Quantification theory and empty individual domains, this Journal, vol. 18 (1953), pp. 197–200).

10 As axioms and rules of inference for QC=, when the individual constants of QC= have leave to designate nothing or designate something not a value of ‘x’, ‘y’, ‘z’, etc., use those of QC1 = (which do not acknowledge as a domain) or those of QC2 = (which do) in H. Leblanc and R. H. Thomason's Completeness theorems for some presupposition-free logics, forthcoming in Fundamenta mathematicae.

11 I owe the above phrasing of (iii) to a referee.