Hostname: page-component-76fb5796d-r6qrq Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-26T19:20:19.962Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Redundancies in the Hilbert-Bernays derivability conditions for Gödel's second incompleteness theorem1

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  12 March 2014

R. G. Jeroslow*
Affiliation:
Carnegie-Mellon University, Pittsburgh, Pennsylvania 15213

Extract

This paper presents three generalizations of the Second Incompleteness Theorem of Gödel (see [2]) which apply to a broader class of formal systems than previous generalizations (as, e.g., the generalization in [1]).

The content of all three of our results is that it is versions of the third derivability condition of Hilbert and Bernays (see p. 286 of [3]) which are crucial to Gödel's theorem. The second derivability condition plays some role in certain logics, but even there, only in the far weaker form of a definability condition (see Theorem 2).

The elimination of the first derivability condition allows the application of the Consistency Theorem to cut-free logics which cannot prove that they are closed under cut.

It is Theorem 1 which will probably have primary interest for readers who are not concerned with technical proof theory or with foundations, for it treats logics with quantifiers, and in that case one can dispose entirely of the first and second derivability conditions. The derivation of this result requires a “new twist” on old arguments. Specifically, we use a new variation on the standard self-referential lemma (this is Lemma 5.1 of [l]) to obtain a somewhat different self-referential construction than has previously been employed (this is our lemma in §2 below). With this new construction, we consider the sentence φ which “expresses” the fact: “My negation is provable.” Then, using hypotheses associated with Gödel's First Incompleteness Theorem, one shows that ⊢¬φ is impossible in a consistent logic. Finally, using only a version of the third Hilbert-Bernays derivability condition, one shows that the provability of the consistency statement implies ⊢¬φ, and hence that consistency is unprovable.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © Association for Symbolic Logic 1973

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

1

Theorem 2 of this paper was presented by the author at the AMS 1971 Summer Meeting at State College, Pennsylvania, on September 3, 1971. The three results of this paper were reported in an earlier manuscript, On Gödel's consistency theorem, in October, 1971. The present paper constitutes a revision of the earlier manuscript.

References

REFERENCES

[1]Feferman, S., Arithmetization of metamathematics in a general setting, Fundamenta Mathematicae, vol. 44 (1960), pp. 3592.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
[2]Gödel, K., Ueber formal unentscheidbare Sätze der Principia Mathematica und verwandter Systeme, Monatshefte für Mathematik und Physik, vol. 38 (1931), pp. 173198.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
[3]Hilbert, D. and Bernays, P., Grundlagen der -Mathematik, vol. 2, Springer, Berlin, 1934/1939; Zweite Auflage, Springer-Verlag, 1968/70, 498 pp.Google Scholar
[4]Hilbert, D., On the infinite, From Frege to Gödel (Heijenoort, J. Van, Editor), Harvard University Press, Cambridge, 1967, 660 pp.Google Scholar
[5]Jeroslow, R., On Gödel's consistency theorem, 07 1971, mimeographed, 72 pp.Google Scholar
[6]Kreisel, G., Mathematical logic, Lectures on modern mathematics. Vol. 3 (Saaty, T. L., Editor), Wiley, New York, 1963/1965.Google Scholar
[7]Kreisel, G., Topics in proof theory, Lecture notes from Mathematisch Instituut der Rijksuniversiteit, Utrecht, Holland, 06 1971, 30 pp., mimeographed.Google Scholar
[8]Mendelson, E., Introduction to mathematical logic, Van Nostrand, Princeton, New Jersey, 1964, 257 pp.Google Scholar