Hostname: page-component-8448b6f56d-c4f8m Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-24T02:33:37.459Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Simplified morasses with linear limits

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  12 March 2014

Dan Velleman*
Affiliation:
The University of Texas, Austin, Texas 78712
*
Amherst College, Amherst, Massachusetts 01002

Abstract

In a recent series of papers Kanamori ([4], [5], and [6]) defines generalizations of several combinatorial principles known to follow from the existence of morasses. Kanamori proves the consistency of his generalizations by forcing arguments which come close to satisfying the hypotheses of the Martin's Axiom-type characterizations of morasses developed independently by Shelah and Stanley [9] and the author [12]. A similar “almost application” of morasses appears in [11], in which Todorčević uses forcing to prove the consistency of the existence of Kurepa trees with no Aronszajn or Cantor subtrees. In all cases the attempted proofs using morasses fail for the same reason: the partial orders involved do not have strong enough closure properties.

In an attempt to solve this problem Shelah and Stanley strengthened their characterization of morasses to allow applications to what they called “good canonical limit” partial orders. However, for rather subtle reasons even this strengthened forcing axiom is not good enough for the proposed applications. The problem this time is that Shelah and Stanley's “weak commutativity of Lim and restriction” requirement (see [9, 3.9(iv)]) is not satisfied. Furthermore, there is reason to believe that an ordinary morass is just not good enough for these applications, since in L morasses exist at all regular uncountable cardinals, but even a weak form of Todorčević's conclusion cannot hold at ineffable cardinals (see the end of §4).

A possible solution to this problem is suggested by the fact that □κ is equivalent to a forcing axiom which applies to partial orders satisfying precisely the kind of weak closure conditions involved in the examples described above (see [13]). What is needed to make the proposed morass applications work is something which will do for morass constructions what □κ does for ordinary transfinite recursion constructions. In this paper we show how extra structure can be built into a morass to accomplish this goal.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © Association for Symbolic Logic 1984

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

REFERENCES

[1]Baumgartner, J., A new class of order types, Annals of Mathematical Logic, vol. 9 (1976), pp. 187222.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
[2]Burgess, J., Consistency proofs in model theory: a contribution to Jensenlehre, Annals of Mathematical Logic, vol. 14 (1978), pp. 112.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
[3]Devlin, K., Aspects of constructihility. Lecture Notes in Mathematics, vol. 354, Springer-Verlag, Berlin, 1973.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
[4]Kanamori, A., Morass-level combinatorial principles, Patras logic symposion (Patras, 1980; Metakides, G., editor), North-Holland, Amsterdam, 1982, pp. 339358.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
[5]Kanamori, A., On Silver's and related principles, Logic Colloquium '80 (Prague, 1980; van Dalen, D., Lascar, D. and Smiley, T., editors), North-Holland, Amsterdam, 1982, pp. 153172.Google Scholar
[6]Kanamori, A., Morasses in combinatorial set theory, Surveys in set theory (Mathias, A., editor), London Mathematical Society Lecture Note Series, vol. 87, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 1983, pp. 167196.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
[7]Laver, R., Makinq the super compactness of κ indestructible under κ-directed closed forcing, Israel Journal of Mathematics, vol. 29 (1978), pp. 385388.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
[8]Menas, T., On strong compactness and supercompactness. Annals of Mathematical Logic, vol. 7 (1974), pp. 327359.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
[9]Shelah, S. and Stanley, L., S-forcing. I: A “black-box” theorem for morasses, with applications: super-Souslin trees and generalized Martin's axiom, preliminary draft. [The final version appeared in Israel Journal of Mathematics, vol. 43 (1982), pp. 185–224 and 225236.]CrossRefGoogle Scholar
[10]Solovay, R., Box sequences and forcing, handwritten notes, 1977.Google Scholar
[11]Todorčević, S., Trees, subtrees and order types, Annals of Mathematical Logic, vol. 20 (1981), pp. 233268.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
[12]Velleman, D., Morasses, diamond, and forcing, Annals of Mathematical Logic, vol. 23 (1983), pp. 199281.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
[13]Velleman, D., On a generalization of Jensen's □κ, and strategic closure of partial orders, this Journal, vol. 48 (1983), pp. 10461052.Google Scholar
[14]Velleman, D., Simplified morasses, this Journal, vol. 49 (1984), pp. 257271.Google Scholar
[15]Donder, H.-D., Another look at gap-1 morasses, preprint, 1982.Google Scholar
[16]Donder, H.-D., Coarse morasses in L, Set theory and model theory (Bonn, 1979; Jensen, R. B. and Prestel, A., editors), Lecture Notes in Mathematics, vol. 872, Springer-Verlag, Berlin, 1981, pp. 3754.CrossRefGoogle Scholar