Hostname: page-component-8448b6f56d-qsmjn Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-19T00:28:51.473Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

A note on definable Skolem functions

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  12 March 2014

Philip Scowcroft*
Affiliation:
Department of Mathematics, Ohio State University, Columbus, Ohio 43210 Department of Mathematics, Stanford University, Stanford, California 94305

Extract

This note arose out of my efforts to understand results of van den Dries, Denef, and Weispfenning on definable Skolem functions in the elementary theory of Qp. The first person to prove their existence was van den Dries, who devised and applied a model-theoretic criterion for theories, admitting elimination of quantifiers, which also admit definable Skolem functions [3]. The proof, though elegant, does not describe how one defines the Skolem functions. In the particular case of Qp, Denef found an ingenious, easily described method for writing out the definitions [2, pp. 14–15]. Unfortunately, his argument directly applies only in the following special case: if

and there is a fixed m ≥ 1 such that

for all , then can be given as a definable function of . While this special case includes many of interest, van den Dries' theorem seems more general. Weispfenning suggested how his results on primitive-recursive quantifier elimination could produce algorithms yielding definitions of Skolem functions in the specific theories van den Dries considered [10, pp. 470–471]. Though these algorithms provide a more concrete version of van den Dries' theorem, and do not suffer the lack of generality of Denef's result, Weispfenning's argument is extremely subtle and applies only to certain theories of valued fields.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © Association for Symbolic Logic 1988

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

REFERENCES

[1]Cherlin, G. and Dickmann, M. A., Real closed rings. II: Model theory, Annals of Pure and Applied Logic, vol. 25 (1983), pp. 213231.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
[2]Denef, J., The rationality of the Poincaré series associated to the p-adic points on a variety, Inventiones Mathematicae, vol. 77 (1984), pp. 123.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
[3]van den Dries, L., Algebraic theories with definable Skolem functions, this Journal, vol. 49 (1984), pp. 625629.Google Scholar
[4]Hilbert, D. and Bernays, P., Grundlagen der Mathematik, Vol. II, 2nd ed., Springer-Verlag, Berlin, 1970.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
[5]Macintyre, A., On definable subsets of p-adic fields, this Journal, vol. 41 (1976), pp. 605610.Google Scholar
[6]Poizat, B., Une théorie de Galois imaginaire, this Journal, vol. 48 (1983), pp. 11511170.Google Scholar
[7]Prestel, A. and Roquette, P., Formally p-adic fields, Lecture Notes in Mathematics, vol. 1050, Springer-Verlag, Berlin, 1984.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
[8]Takeuti, G., Proof theory, North-Holland, Amsterdam, 1975.Google Scholar
[9]Weispfenning, V., On the elementary theory of Hensel fields, Annals of Mathematical Logic, vol. 10 (1976), pp. 5993.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
[10]Weispfenning, V., Quantifier elimination and decision procedures for valued fields, Models and sets (proceedings of Logic Colloquium '83), Lecture Notes in Mathematics, vol. 1103, Springer-Verlag, Berlin, 1984, pp. 419472.Google Scholar