Hostname: page-component-7c8c6479df-nwzlb Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-03-29T15:30:25.716Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

On measurable limits of compact cardinals

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  12 March 2014

Arthur W. Apter*
Affiliation:
Department of Mathematics, Baruch College of CunyNew York, New York 10010., USA, E-mail: awabb@cunyvm.cuny.eduURL: http://math.baruch.cuny.edu/~ apter

Abstract

We extend earlier work (both individual and joint with Shelah) and prove three theorems about the class of measurable limits of compact cardinals, where a compact cardinal is one which is either strongly compact or supercompact. In particular, we construct two models in which every measurable limit of compact cardinals below the least supercompact limit of supercompact cardinals possesses non-trivial degrees of supercompactness. In one of these models, every measurable limit of compact cardinals is a limit of supercompact cardinals and also a limit of strongly compact cardinals having no non-trivial degree of supercompactness. We also show that it is consistent for the least supercompact cardinal κ to be a limit of strongly compact cardinals and be so that every measurable limit of compact cardinals below κ has a non-trivial degree of supercompactness. In this model, the only compact cardinals below κ with a non-trivial degree of supercompactness are the measurable limits of compact cardinals.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © Association for Symbolic Logic 1999

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

REFERENCES

[1]Apter, A., On the least strongly compact cardinal, Israel Journal of Mathematics, vol. 35 (1980), pp. 225233.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
[2]Apter, A., Patterns of compact cardinals, Annals of Pure and Applied Logic, vol. 89 (1997), pp. 101115.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
[3]Apter, A., Laver indestructibility and the class of compact cardinals, this Journal, vol. 63 (1998), pp. 149157.Google Scholar
[4]Apter, A. and Shelah, S., Menas' result is best possible, Transactions of the American Mathematical Society, vol. 349 (1997), pp. 20072034.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
[5]Burgess, J., Forcing, Handbook of mathematical logic (Barwise, J., editor), North-Holland, Amsterdam, 1977, pp. 403452.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
[6]Hamkins, J., Destruction or preservation as you like it, Annals of Pure and Applied Logic, vol. 91 (1998), pp. 191229.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
[7]Kanamori, A., The higher infinite, Springer-Verlag, Berlin and New York, 1994.Google Scholar
[8]Kanamori, A. and Magidor, M., The evolution of large cardinal axioms in set theory, Lecture notes in mathematics, no. 669, Springer-Verlag, Berlin and New York, 1978, pp. 99275.Google Scholar
[9]Kimchi, Y. and Magidor, M., The independence between the concepts of compactness and supercompactness, circulated manuscript.Google Scholar
[10]Laver, R., Making the supercompactness of κ indestructible under κ-directed closed forcing, Israel Journal of Mathematics, vol. 29 (1978), pp. 385388.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
[11]Lévy, A. and Solovay, R., Measurable cardinals and the continuum hypothesis, Israel Journal of Mathematics, vol. 5 (1967), pp. 234248.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
[12]Mekler, A. and Shelah, S., Does κ-free imply strongly κ-free?, Proceedings of the third conference on abelian group theory, Gordon and Breach, Salzburg, 1987, pp. 137148.Google Scholar
[13]Menas, T., On strong compactness and supercompactness, Annals of Mathematical Logic, vol. 7 (1974), pp. 327359.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
[14]Solovay, R., Reinhardt, W., and Kanamori, A., Strong axioms of infinity and elementary embeddings, Annals of Mathematical Logic, vol. 13 (1978), pp. 73116.CrossRefGoogle Scholar