Hostname: page-component-8448b6f56d-qsmjn Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-04-24T22:37:38.769Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Bases for first-order theories and subtheories

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  12 March 2014

William Craig*
Affiliation:
The Pennsylvania State University

Extract

The extent to which we can grasp the content of a (non-logical) theory, expressing it economically by means of an axiom system or basis, varies greatly. In this paper we shall investigate what degree of economy, or at least regularity, can be achieved for all recursively axiomatizable first-order theories. A useful approach, also of interest in its own right, turns out to be the study of bases for subtheories, where a subtheory of a given theory consists of those theorems from which certain predicate symbols are absent. These predicate symbols might be thought of as the formal counterparts of the “purely theoretical” terms employed by a science, the theory corresponding to the science itself and the subtheory to its “observational consequences”. Roughly speaking, the types of operations involving such predicate symbols will be reduced to a minimum, so that their syntactical role in deductions will emerge more clearly.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © Association for Symbolic Logic 1960

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

[I]Ackermann, W., Untersuchungen über das Eliminationsproblem der mathe matischen Logik, Mathematische Annalen, vol. 110 (1934), pp. 390413.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
[2]Ackermann, W., Zum Eliminationsproblem der mathematischen Logik, Mathematische Annalen, vol. 111 (1935), pp. 6163.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
[3]Büchi, J. R. and Craig, W., Notes on the family PCΔ of sets of models, abstract, this Journal, vol. 21 (1956), pp. 222223.Google Scholar
[4]Craig, W., A theorem about first order functional calculus with identity, and two applications. PhD. thesis, Harvard University, 1951.Google Scholar
[5]Craig, W., Linear reasoning. A new form of the Herbrand-Genizen theorem, this Journal, vol. 22 (1957), pp. 250268.Google Scholar
[6]Craig, W., Analysis of first-order implications, Summaries of talks presented at the Summer Institute of Symbolic Logic in 1957 at Cornell University, mimeographed, 1957, pp. 175180.Google Scholar
[7]Craig, W. and Vaught, R. L., Finite axiomatizability using additional predicates, this Journal, vol. 23 (1958), pp. 289308.Google Scholar
[8]Ehrenfeucht, A., Two theories with axioms built by means of pleonasms, this Journal, vol. 22 (1957), pp. 3638.Google Scholar
[9]Henkin, L., The completeness of the first-order functional calculus, this Journal, vol. 14 (1949), pp. 159166.Google Scholar
[10]Herbrand, J., Recherches sur la theorie de la démonstration, Travaux de la Société des Sciences et des Lettres de Varsovie, Classe III sciences mathématiques et physiques, no. 33 (1930).Google Scholar
[11]Hintikka, K. J. J., Form and content in quantification theory, Two papers on symbolic logic, Acta philosophica Fennica, no. 8, Helsinki 1955, pp. 755.Google Scholar
[12]Kleene, S. C., Introduction to metamathematics, Amsterdam (North Holland), Groningen (Noordhoff), New York and Toronto (Van Nostrand), 1952.Google Scholar
[13]Kleene, S. C., Finite axiomatizability of theories in the predicate calculus using additional predicate symbols, Memoirs of the American Mathematical Society, no. 10 (Two papers on the predicate calculus). Providence, 1952, pp. 2768.Google Scholar
[14]Kleene, S. C., Permutabilily of inferences in Gentzen's Calculi LK and LJ, Memoirs of the American Mathematical Society, no. 10 (Two papers on the predicate calculus). Providence, 1952, pp. 126.Google Scholar
[15]Lyndon, R. C., Properties preserved under algebraic constructions, Bulletin of the American Mathematical Society, vol. 65 (1959), pp. 287299.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
[16]Mach, E., The science of mechanics, translation of the second German edition, Chapter IV, Section IV (The economy of science), pp. 481494, LaSalle, III. (Open Court), 1893.Google Scholar
[17]Quine, W. V., Mathematical Logic, revised edition, Cambridge (Harvard University Press), 1951.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
[18]Tarski, A., Some notions and methods on the borderline of algebra and meta-mathematics, Proceedings of the International Congress of Mathematicians (Cambridge, Mass. U.S.A., Aug. 30-Sept. 6, 1950), 1952, vol. 1, pp. 705720.Google Scholar
[19]Tarski, A., Contributions to the theory of models, I and II, Koninklijke Nederlandse Akademie van Wetenschappen, Proceedings, ser. A, vol. 57 (also Indagationes mathematicae, vol. 16) (1954), pp. 572588.Google Scholar
[20]Tarski, A. and Vaught, R. L., Arithmetical extensions of relational systems, Compositio mathematica, vol. 13 (1957), pp. 81102.Google Scholar
[21]Trahténbrot, B. A., Névozmožnost' algorifma dlá problémy razréšimosti na konéčnyh klassah (Impossibility of an algorithm for the decision problem in finite classes), Doklady Akadémii Nauk SSSR, n.s., vol. 70 (1950), pp. 569572.Google Scholar