Abstract
Recent foundational work on the nature of defeasible inference has appealed to an epistemic context principle (ECP): βfollows defeasibly from α (α β )if and only if follows classically from C(α), where C(α) is the given epistemic context for α. Since nothing requires that C(α) ⊆ C(α ^ γ), the induced notion of consequence is nonmonotonic. We will focus on a particular manner of articulating ECP where C(α) is an autoepistemic (AE) extension of {α}.
Robert Stalnaker proposed in [25] a substantial way of understanding this defeasible notion of AE-consequence. The gist of the proposal is: (P) what is non-monotonically entailed by a sentence α is what is meant or implicated, but not explicitly said by uttering α. He suggested that a defeasible notion of consequence (explicated via ECP) could be used to formally encode Grice’s notion of conversational implicature — and to understand its context-dependent behavior.
This article makes three main contributions. First, we will focus on the tenability of (P). Paul Grice considered in [10] some minimal constraints on implicature needed in order to handle G.E. Moore’s paradox of ‘saying and disbelieving’. We will show that (P) is incompatible with those constraints. Secondly we will offer an alternative account of AE consequence based on several remarks made by Grice in [10]. According to this account C(α) encodes the body of full beliefs to which someone is committed after uttering α. Thirdly we will offer a preliminary account of the formal properties of this new notion of consequence.
AE logic assumes that introspective reasoners do not subscribe to the alethic principle (T) — establishing that the AE-operator L obeys L(A) → A. This is due to a tacit interpretation of L as an operator of ‘weak’ belief. This is done even when (T) is satisfied post hoc in every AE-extension. The price paid by this maneuver is that AE logic, unlike most defeasible logics, is not cumulative — although (T) is satisfied in every extension, the principle cannot be used in the reasoning to arrive at the extension (see [13], page 228). We verify that our notion of AE-consequence is not affected by this problem by showing that (with certain provisos) the notion is cumulative.
Preview
Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.
Similar content being viewed by others
References
Aitchison-Costa, H., ‘Assertion, acceptance and defeasible inference,’ manuscript, CMU, March 1999.
Aitchison, H., ‘Qualitative and probabilistic models of full belief,’ Proceedings of the Logic Colloquium’ 98, ASL European Summer Meeting, Springer Verlag, 1999.
Clark, H. H.; Carlson, T. B., ‘Context for comprehension, in Attention and Performance IX, ed. Long and Baddeley, Erlbaum, 1981, 313–330.
Arló-Costa, H., Shapiro, S. (1992) “Maps between non-monotonic and conditional logics,” Principles of Knowledge Representation and Reasoning: Proceedings of the Third International Conference (eds.) Nebel, B., Rich, C., Swartout, W.: 553–564.
L. Fari~nas del Cerro, G. Crocco, A. Herzig, (eds.), Conditionals, from Philosophy to Computer Science, Oxford University Press, Oxford, 1995.
Fitting, M. ‘Moore’s nonmonotonic logic and S5,’ manuscript, CUNY, November 1983.
Gabbay, D. “Theoretical foundations for non-monotonical reasoning in expert systems” Logics and Models of Concurrent Systems, K.R. Apt., ed., 1985.
Gabbay, D.M., Hogger, C.J., Robinson, J.A., (eds.) Handbook of Logic in Artificial Intelligence and Logic programming, Volk. 3 Nnonmonotonic reasoning and uncertain reasoning, Oxford Science Publications, Oxford, 1994.
Ginsberg, M., ‘Counterfactuals,’ Artificial Intelligence 30, 1986, 35–79.
Grice, P., Studies in the way of words, Cambridge, Mass., Harvard University Press, 1989.
Hild, M., ‘The diachronic coherence of ungraded beliefs,’ manuscript, Christ’s College, Cambridge, November, 1998.
Kelly, K., ‘The learning power of belief revision,’ TARK VII, Theoretical Aspects of Rationality and Knowledge, Morgan Kaufman, 1998.
Konologige, K., ‘Autoepistemic Logic,’ in Handbook of Philosophical Logic, second edition, Vol III Extensions of Classical Logic (eds.) D. Gabbay and F. Guenthner, Reidel, Dordrecht, 1998.
Lamarre, P., “S4 as the conditional logic of nonmonotonicity” Proceedings KR’91, 1991.
Lehmann, D., Magidor, M., “Rational logics and their models; A study in cumulative logics.” Technical Report TR 88-16 of the Dept. of Computer Science, Hebrew University of Jerusalem, November 1988.
Levi, I., ‘The logic of full belief,’ in The Covenant of Reason: Rationality and the Commitments of Thought, CUP, 1997, 40–69,.
Levi, I., For the Sake of Argument: Ramsey Test Conditionals, Inductive Inference, and Nonmonotonic Reasoning. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, England, 1996.
Lewis, D. Counterfactuals (1973).
Makinson, D., “General Theory of Cumulative Inference” Non-Monotonic Reasoning, M. Reinfrank, J. de Kleer, M. Ginsberg, and E. Sandewall eds., 1988.
Makinson, D., ‘Five faces of minimality,’ Studia Logica 52, 1993, 339–379.
Moore, G.E., ‘Russell’s ‘Theory of Descriptions,’ in Philosophical Papers by G.E. Moore, ed. H.D. Lewis, London: Muirhead Library of Philosophy, 1959, [2nd ed. 1963].
Moore, R., Logic and Representation, CSLI Lecture Notes No. 39, 1995.
Stalnaker, R., ‘A note on non-monotonic modal logic,’ Artificial Intelligence 64, 1993, 183–196.
Pearl, J., ‘Probability of causation: Three counterfactual interpretations and their identification,’ Technical Report R-261, UCLA, 1998.
Stalnaker, R., ‘What is a non-monotonic consequence relation? Fundamenta Informaticae 21, 1994, 7–21.
van Fraassen, B., ‘Fine-grained opinion, probability, and the logic of full belief,’ Journal of Philosophical Logic 24, 1955, 349–377.
Author information
Authors and Affiliations
Editor information
Editors and Affiliations
Rights and permissions
Copyright information
© 1999 Springer-Verlag Berlin Heidelberg
About this paper
Cite this paper
Costa, H.A. (1999). Epistemic Context, Defeasible Inference and Conversational Implicature. In: Bouquet, P., Benerecetti, M., Serafini, L., Brézillon, P., Castellani, F. (eds) Modeling and Using Context. CONTEXT 1999. Lecture Notes in Computer Science(), vol 1688. Springer, Berlin, Heidelberg. https://doi.org/10.1007/3-540-48315-2_2
Download citation
DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/3-540-48315-2_2
Published:
Publisher Name: Springer, Berlin, Heidelberg
Print ISBN: 978-3-540-66432-1
Online ISBN: 978-3-540-48315-1
eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive