Skip to main content

Cheap Talk Under Partial Conflicts: A Dynamic Analysis of Pragmatic Meaning

  • Conference paper
  • First Online:
New Frontiers in Artificial Intelligence (JSAI-isAI 2021)

Part of the book series: Lecture Notes in Computer Science ((LNAI,volume 13856))

Included in the following conference series:

  • 172 Accesses

Abstract

In natural language, meanings of words often deviate from their literal meanings under pragmatic reasoning. As is shown in game-theoretical pragmatics, when players do not have aligned benefits, communication with non-literal meaning is even more frequent. In these situations, the pragmatic inference under iterated best response plays the essential role for building the pragmatic meaning. The paper provides a systematic analysis of the deviation from literal meaning to pragmatic meaning when the interlocutors have partial conflicts. We apply the classical Cheap Talk game and Iterated Best Response reasoning to demonstrate the result.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 64.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Farrell [5] defines a novel equilibrium notion called “neologism proofness”, under which the number of equilibrium in signaling game is reduced.

  2. 2.

    In economic literature, signaling game is often called cheap talk game. It is because the cost of the signals is usually not taken into account into the utility function.

  3. 3.

    The traditional signaling game or cheap talk game does not pre-assume that the signals are meaningful within the game.

  4. 4.

    We use \(p(\cdot |\cdot )\) representing the sender’s conditional belief about the receiver’s strategy, and \(q(\cdot | \cdot )\) reprenting the receiver’s conditional belief about the sender’s strategy.

  5. 5.

    We use \(I^k\) in the utility function to indicate the sender’s choice of the signals are within the signal structure \(I_k\). Since the meaning of the signals are assumed as common knowledge at each epistemic level, we can omit to specify the signals.

  6. 6.

    See for instance [4], p. 145 for a detailed proof of this result.

References

  1. Benz, A., Jäger, G., Van Rooij, R., Van Rooij, R.: Game Theory and Pragmatics. Springer, Cham (2005)

    Google Scholar 

  2. Crawford, V.P., Sobel, J.: Strategic information transmission. Econometrica: J. Econometr. Soc., 1431–1451 (1982)

    Google Scholar 

  3. Crawford, V.P., et al.: Let’s talk it over: Coordination via preplay communication with level-k thinking. Unpublished Manuscript (2007)

    Google Scholar 

  4. Elaydi, S.: An Introduction to Difference Equations. Springer Science and Business Media, Cham (2005)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  5. Farrell, J.: Meaning and credibility in cheap-talk games. Games Econom. Behav. 5(4), 514–531 (1993)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  6. Frank, M.C., Goodman, N.D.: Predicting pragmatic reasoning in language games. Science 336(6084), 998–998 (2012)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  7. Franke, M.: Game theoretic pragmatics. Philos Compass 8(3), 269–284 (2013)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  8. Franke, M., et al.: Meaning and inference in case of conflict. In: Proceedings of the 13th ESSLLI student session, pp. 65–74 (2008)

    Google Scholar 

  9. Goodman, N.D., Frank, M.C.: Pragmatic language interpretation as probabilistic inference. Trends Cogn. Sci. 20(11), 818–829 (2016)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  10. Grice, H.P.: Logic and conversation. In: Speech acts, pp. 41–58. Brill (1975)

    Google Scholar 

  11. Jäger, G.: Rationalizable signaling. Erkenntnis 79(4), 673–706 (2014)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  12. Kawagoe, T., Takizawa, H.: Equilibrium refinement vs. level-k analysis: an experimental study of cheap-talk games with private information. Games Econ. Behav. 66(1), 238–255 (2009)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  13. Lewis, D.: Convention: A Philosophical Study. John Wiley & Sons, Hoboken (2008)

    Google Scholar 

  14. Stalnaker, R.: Saying and meaning, cheap talk and credibility. In: Benz, A., Jager, G., van Rooji, R. (eds.) Game theory and pragmatics, pp. 83–100. Springer, Cham (2006)

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

The author is an international research fellow of Japan Society for the Promotion of Science.This research is supported by Grant-in-Aid for JSPS Fellows (No. 20F20012), Chinese National Funding of Social Science (No. 18CZX064) and the Key Project of National Social Science Foundation of China (No. 16AZX017).

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Liping Tang .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Appendix

Appendix

Theorem 2 Given a game \(G_I\) and the IBR model \(I^k\) , there exists a natural number n such that for any natural number \(m \geqslant n\) , \(I^m_S=I^m_R=[0,1]\) , and \((s_m, r_m)\) yields a pooling equilibrium.

Proof

Case 1: Suppose that \(b>= 1/4\), \(N(b)=1\), the required result holds trivially.

Case 2: Suppose that \(0<b<1/4\).

The idea is to find the connection of the sender’s inutility functions and the changes of the meanings between different levels. Then construct the convergence result of the dynamic.

First, given any \(b\in (0, \frac{1}{4})\), we can calculate \(N(b)=N\) which is the largest number of the partitions for the partition equilibrium, then the total number of the signals are \(M=\frac{(N+1)N}{2}\).

From the constructions of the IBR model, for any signal \(I_{ij}^k\), the sender’s utility function has the form \(U_{S}=-(r^k-t)^2\), where \(r^k=r-b\). List all these functions as r increases as \(U_{S}=-(r_1^k-t)^2, U_{S}=-(r_2^k-t)^2, \dots , U_{S}=-(r_M^k-t)^2\) where \(r_1^k<r_2^k<\dots <r_M^k\).

All the interval meanings of the signals at each level are derived from those utility functions, as we illustrated in Fig. 2.

Fig. 2.
figure 2

Expanded signal structure for b = 1/20

\(p_j^k\) is used to indicate those interval points. And for any level k, assume that \(p_{0}^k=0\) and \(p_{M}^k=1\). And for any \(0<i<j<M\), \(p_i<p_j\). Then by the structure of the game, r and p has the following relationships.

$$\begin{aligned} \begin{array}{ c } p_{1}^0 =\frac{1}{2}(r_{1}^0+r_{2}^0) \\[2mm] p_{2}^0 =\frac{1}{2}(r_{2}^0+r_{3}^0) \\[2mm] \cdots \\[2mm] p_{M-1}^0=\frac{1}{2}(r_{M-1}^0+r_{M}^0) \end{array} \end{aligned}$$

Moreover, we have that

$$\begin{aligned} \begin{array}{ c r } r_{1}^{k+1}=\frac{1}{2}(0+p_{1}^k)-b &{} \\[2mm] r_{2}^{k+1}=\frac{1}{2}(p_{1}^k+p_{2}^k)-b &{} \qquad [1] \\[2mm] \cdots &{} \\[2mm] r_{M}^{k+1}=\frac{1}{2}(p_{M-1}^k+1)-b &{} \\ \end{array} \end{aligned}$$

In addition, we have the following equations:

$$\begin{aligned} \begin{array}{ c r } p_{1}^{k+1}=\frac{1}{2}(r_{1}^{k+1}+r_{2}^{k+1}) &{} \\[2mm] p_{2}^{k+1}=\frac{1}{2}(r_{2}^{k+1}+r_{3}^{k+1}) &{} \qquad [2] \\[2mm] \cdots &{} \\[2mm] p_{M-1}^{k+1}=\frac{1}{2}(r_{M-1}^{k+1}+r_{M}^{k+1}) &{} \\ \end{array} \end{aligned}$$

By substituting all the \(r_{i}^{k+1}\)s in formula series [2] with all the formulas in [1], we can obtain the following equations:

$$\begin{aligned} \begin{array}{ c r } p_{1}^{k+1}=\frac{1}{4}p_{0}^k+\frac{1}{2}p_{1(n)}+\frac{1}{4}p_{2^k}-b &{} \\[2mm] p_{2}^{k+1}=\frac{1}{4}p_{1}^k+\frac{1}{2}p_{2(n)}+\frac{1}{4}p_{3^k}-b &{} \\[2mm] p_{3}^{k+1}=\frac{1}{4}p_{2}^k+\frac{1}{2}p_{3(n)}+\frac{1}{4}p_{4}^k-b &{} \qquad [3] \\[2mm] \cdots &{} \\[2mm] p_{M-1}^{k+1}=\frac{1}{4}p_{M-2}^k+\frac{1}{2}p_{M-1}^k+\frac{1}{4}p_{M}^k-b &{} \\ \end{array} \end{aligned}$$

Therefore, the formulas in [3] can be rewritten in the metric form as follows:

$$p(n+1)=Ap(n)-B$$

where

$$ A = \left( \begin{array}{cccccc} \frac{1}{2} &{}\frac{1}{4} &{} 0 &{} \cdots &{} 0 &{} 0 \\ \frac{1}{4} &{} \frac{1}{2} &{}\frac{1}{4} &{} 0 &{} \cdots &{} 0 \\ 0 &{} \frac{1}{4} &{} \frac{1}{2} &{}\frac{1}{4} &{} \cdots &{} 0 \\ \vdots &{}&{}\ddots &{}\ddots &{}\ddots &{}\vdots \\ 0 &{} 0&{} \cdots &{} \frac{1}{4} &{} \frac{1}{2}&{} \frac{1}{4}\\ 0 &{} 0&{} \cdots &{} 0&{} \frac{1}{4} &{} \frac{1}{2}\\ \end{array} \right) $$
$$B=\left( \begin{array}{c} b\\ \cdots \\ b\\ \cdots \\ \frac{1}{4}-b\\ \end{array} \right) $$

Observe that A has the exact form as the matrix known as Toeplitz Matrix. Thus its eigenvalues are given by

$$\lambda _{n}=\frac{1}{2}+\frac{1}{4}\cos (\frac{n\pi }{k+1}), n=1, 2, \cdots , M-1$$

Therefore, \(|\lambda |<1\) for all n. According to the following mathematical result: Assuming that A is any \(k \times k\) matrix, then \(\lim \limits _{n \rightarrow \infty }A^n=0\) iff \(|\lambda |<1\) for all eigenvalues \(\lambda \) of A,Footnote 6 we thus have that \(\lim \limits _{n \rightarrow \infty }A^n=0\). It follows that \(p_{n+1}<0\) as \(n \rightarrow \infty \). As all the \(p_i\)s are becoming negative, there will be no divided point in the interval [0, 1]. That is to say, there is only one signal that is considered from the sender’s point of view for \(t \in [0, 1]\). Thus, the babbling equilibrium eventually occurs.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2023 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this paper

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this paper

Tang, L. (2023). Cheap Talk Under Partial Conflicts: A Dynamic Analysis of Pragmatic Meaning. In: Yada, K., Takama, Y., Mineshima, K., Satoh, K. (eds) New Frontiers in Artificial Intelligence. JSAI-isAI 2021. Lecture Notes in Computer Science(), vol 13856. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-031-36190-6_19

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-031-36190-6_19

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Cham

  • Print ISBN: 978-3-031-36189-0

  • Online ISBN: 978-3-031-36190-6

  • eBook Packages: Computer ScienceComputer Science (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics