Skip to main content

Arguing About Dynamic Meaning

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Johan van Benthem on Logic and Information Dynamics

Part of the book series: Outstanding Contributions to Logic ((OCTR,volume 5))

  • 1194 Accesses

Abstract

Whether, and if so in what sense, dynamic semantics establishes the need to move away from standard truth-conditional semantics, is a question that has been discussed in the literature on and off. This paper does not attempt to answer it, it merely wants to draw attention to an aspect that has hitherto received little attention in the discussion, viz., the question what role we assign to the use of formal systems in doing natural language semantics.

Martin Stokhof would like to thank Johan van Benthem and the editors for their comments and their patience.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 169.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 219.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Of course, the content of an assertion itself is a context-dependent entity, in many cases, but that does not turn it into a dynamic one.

  2. 2.

    Cf. Groenendijk and Stokhof [15, Sect. 5.2].

  3. 3.

    Among others, [2, 3], and the papers collected in [4].

  4. 4.

    For natural language semantics we should mention, among others, Vermeulen [34], Visser [35]. Cf. also [10] for a computational perspective on deduction in dynamic semantics, and [7] for a more recent overview.

  5. 5.

    In van Benthem [1].

  6. 6.

    It is a testimony to the impact of the generative tradition, though, that even today many authors would seem to work with a more or less principled distinction between ‘language-as-a-system’ and ‘language-as-use’, which echoes the competence—performance distinction that Chomsky used to define the proper domain of linguistics as a scientific endeavour. Cf. [30] for further discussion.

  7. 7.

    And we would do well to note that it is not that even if we accept the semiotic characterisation of semantics as a neutral starting point: what ‘the world’ is, is left underspecified in that characterisation, and there seems to be no a priori way of ruling out that information states of language users are part of ‘the world’.

  8. 8.

    Beside the older literature that has been referred to above, cf. e.g. the more recent [8, 11, 21, 24]; and [22] (already mentioned).

  9. 9.

    As was already mentioned earlier, compositionality played a key role in that discussion, and it is interesting to note that there are indeed good arguments that compositionality is not an empirical issue, but a methodological principle. Cf. [16] for more discussion.

  10. 10.

    Similar considerations apply to formal systems in other domains, e.g., in the kind of naturalistic philosophical analysis that is exemplified in dynamic epistemic logic. We can not go into these matters here, but cf. e.g. [6] for discussion.

  11. 11.

    Another explanation is that in the early days of generative grammar, natural languages were primarily studied from a syntactic point of view, often in terms of structural properties familiar from the theory of formal languages.

  12. 12.

    Of course, there are many differences as well, but these are not relevant for the main point that is at stake here.

  13. 13.

    Or ‘show’; cf. [28] for an extensive analysis of how the universalism of Wittgenstein’s early work, with its associated distinction between ‘saying’ and ‘showing’, is connected with the two conceptions of the role of formal systems in natural language analysis outlined here.

  14. 14.

    In van Benthem [5].

References

  1. van Benthem J (1986) Essays in logical semantics. Springer, New York

    Google Scholar 

  2. van Benthem J (1989) Semantic parallels in natural language and computation. In: Ebbinghaus H-D et al (eds) Logic colloquium ’87, studies in logic and the philosophy of mathematics, vol 129. North-Holland, Amsterdam, pp 331–375

    Google Scholar 

  3. van Benthem J (1991) General dynamics. Theor Linguist 17:159–201

    Google Scholar 

  4. van Benthem J (1996) Exploring logical dynamics. CSLI, Stanford

    Google Scholar 

  5. van Benthem J (1999) Wider still and wider: resetting the bounds of logic. In: The nature of logic, European review of philosophy, vol 4. The University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  6. van Benthem J (2013) Implicit and explicit stances in logic

    Google Scholar 

  7. van Benthem J, Muskens R, Visser A (1997) Dynamics. In: van Benthem JFAK, ter Meulen, Alice GB (eds) Handbook of logic and linguistics. Elsevier, Amsterdam, pp 587–648

    Google Scholar 

  8. Breheny R (2003) On the dynamic turn in the study of meaning and interpretation. In: Peregrin J (ed) Meaning: the dynamic turn. Elsevier, Dordrecht, pp 69–89

    Google Scholar 

  9. Cresswell MJ (2002) Static semantics for dynamic discourse. Linguist Philos 25:545–571

    Article  Google Scholar 

  10. van Eijck J, de Vries F-J (1992) Dynamic interpretation and Hoare deduction. J Logic Lang Inf 1(1):1–44

    Google Scholar 

  11. Gauker C (2007) Comments on dynamic semantics. APA Central Division, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  12. Groenendijk J, Janssen T, Stokhof M (eds) (1984) Truth, interpretation and information, Grass-series, vol 2. Foris, Dordrecht

    Google Scholar 

  13. Groenendijk J, Stokhof M (1990a) Dynamic Montague grammar. In: Kálmán L, Pólos L (eds) Papers from the second symposium on logic and language. Akadémiai Kiadó, Budapest, pp 3–48

    Google Scholar 

  14. Groenendijk J, Stokhof M (1990b) Two theories of dynamic semantics. In: van Eijck J (ed) Logics in AI. Springer, Berlin, pp 55–64

    Google Scholar 

  15. Groenendijk J, Stokhof M (1991) Dynamic predicate logic. Linguist Philos 14(1):39–100

    Google Scholar 

  16. Groenendijk J, Stokhof M (2005) Why compositionality? In: Carlson G, Pelletier J (eds) Reference and quantification: the Partee effect. CSLI, Stanford, pp 83–106

    Google Scholar 

  17. Groenendijk J, Stokhof M, Veltman F (1996) Coreference and modality. In: Lappin S (ed) Handbook of contemporary semantic theory. Blackwell, Oxford, pp 179–213

    Google Scholar 

  18. Heim I (1982) The semantics of definite and indefinite noun phrases. Ph.D. thesis, University of Massachusetts, Amherst (Published in 1989 by Garland, New York)

    Google Scholar 

  19. Heim I (1983) File change semantics and the familiarity theory of definiteness. In: Bäuerle R, Schwarze C, von Stechow A (eds) Meaning, use, and interpretation of language. De Gruyter, Berlin

    Google Scholar 

  20. Kamp H (1981) A theory of truth and semantic representation. In: Groenendijk J, Janssen T, Stokhof M (eds) Formal methods in the study of language, MC tracts, vol 135. Mathematical Centre, Amsterdam (Reprinted in Groenendijk et al. 1984, p 1–41)

    Google Scholar 

  21. Lewis KS (2011) Understanding dynamic discourse. Ph.D. thesis, Rutgers, New Brunswick, New Jersey

    Google Scholar 

  22. Lewis KS (2012) Discourse dynamics, pragmatics, and indefinites. Philos Stud 158(2):313–342

    Google Scholar 

  23. Rothschild D, Yalcin S (2012) On the dynamics of conversation

    Google Scholar 

  24. Schlenker P (2007) Anti-dynamics: presupposition projection without dynamic semantics. J Logic Lang Inf 16:325–356

    Article  Google Scholar 

  25. Stalnaker R (1974) Pragmatic presuppositions. In: Munitz M, Unger P (eds) Semantics and philosophy. New York University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  26. Stalnaker R (1979) Assertion. In: Cole P (ed) Syntax and semantics 9—pragmatics. Academic Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  27. Stalnaker R (1998) On the representation of context. J Logic Lang Inf 7:3–19

    Google Scholar 

  28. Stokhof M (2008) The architecture of meaning: Wittgenstein’s Tractatus and formal semantics. In: Levy D, Zamuner E (eds) Wittgenstein’s enduring arguments. Routledge, London, pp 211–244

    Google Scholar 

  29. Stokhof M (2012) The role of artificial languages. In: Russell G, Fara DG (eds) The Routledge companion to the philosophy of language. Routledge, London/New York, pp 544–553

    Google Scholar 

  30. Stokhof M, van Lambalgen M (2011) Abstraction and idealisation: the construction of modern linguistics. Theor Linguist 37(1–2):1–26

    Article  Google Scholar 

  31. Veltman F (1984) Data semantics. In: Groenendijk J, Janssen TMV, Stokhof M (eds) Truth, interpretation and information. Foris, Dordrecht, pp 43–62

    Google Scholar 

  32. Veltman F (1986) Data semantics and the pragmatics of indicative conditionals. In: Traugott E et al (eds) On conditionals. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  33. Veltman F (1996) Defaults in update semantics. J Philos Logic 25:221–261

    Google Scholar 

  34. Vermeulen CFM (1994) Incremental semantics for propositional texts. Notre Dame J Formal Logic 35(2):243–271

    Article  Google Scholar 

  35. Visser A (1998) Contexts in dynamic predicate logic. J Logic Lang Inf 7:21–52

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Martin Stokhof .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2014 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Stokhof, M. (2014). Arguing About Dynamic Meaning. In: Baltag, A., Smets, S. (eds) Johan van Benthem on Logic and Information Dynamics. Outstanding Contributions to Logic, vol 5. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-06025-5_28

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics