Skip to main content

General Homeostasis, Passive Life, and the Challenge to Autonomy

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Fundamental Issues of Artificial Intelligence

Part of the book series: Synthese Library ((SYLI,volume 376))

  • 5065 Accesses

Abstract

The paper argues that the conception of life as generalized homeostasis developed by W.R. Ashby in Design for a Brain and his other writings is orthogonal to the traditional distinction between autonomy and heteronomy that underlies much recent work in cellular biology, evolutionary robotics, ALife, and general AI. The distinction is well-entrenched in the Western philosophical canon but it fails to do justice to Ashby’s conception of life. We can assess the philosophical and technical viability of the general homeostasis thesis Ashby advocated, the paper argues, through the construction of virtual cognitive agents (i.e. simulated robots in a physically plausible environment) that replicate the architecture of Ashby’s original homeostat through a Ctrnn-like network architecture, whose outline implementation is then discussed.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 189.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 249.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 249.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Classical loci of this distinction are the so-called “function of man argument” in book I of Aristotle’s Nichomachean Ethics Aristotle (1984, v. 1, 1097b22–1098a18) and the argument for the tri-partite composition of the psyche in Phaedrus (Plato 1997, 237c–241d) and Republic (Plato 1997, 435e–441c). Both Aristotle and Plato stress that animal life is propelled by “drives” (or “passions”). The structure of this argument is repeated almost verbatim in Descartes’s study of the passions (see Descartes (1988), esp. articles 7–37 of Part 1).

  2. 2.

    Eth. Nic. I,7, 1098a7:

  3. 3.

    I am skipping over a few important details here, in order to get the main point across. A fuller analysis on Kantian grounds would have to specify the exact reasoning that led the human to dive. Kant himself provided the blueprint for all such analysis of autonomy in the well-known example of the shopkeeper he discusses in the Groundworks (1999, AK 397ff.). Hans Jonas (1966, 115ff.) built directly on this argument in his rebuttal of early cybernetics’ claim that a self-driven target-seeking torpedo would be acting autonomously.

  4. 4.

    This passage from Ashby’s notebooks is reported by Andrew Pickering (2010, p. 112) and discussed by Helge Malmgren (2013) in his response to Franchi (2013). I discuss some of the possible relationships between cybernetics and psychoanalysis and give a very brief review of the sparse literature on the subject in Franchi (2011a).

  5. 5.

    For a more detailed discussion of Ashby’s relationships with his predecessors, the cybernetics movement in general, and the relationship between physiological and cybernetic homeostases, see Franchi (2011b).

  6. 6.

    Walter Cannon coined the term in 1929, although Claude Bernard had introduced the fundamental idea about 50 years earlier (1966[1878–1879]). Next, Lawrence Joseph Henderson in the United States and John Scott Haldane in Britain (Henderson 1928; Haldane 1917 and especially Haldane 1922) popularized it in the English speaking world. The title of Cannon’s celebrated 1932 book, The Wisdom of the Body, pays homage to William Starling’s homonym lecture, which had dealt with the self-compensating mechanisms of the heart (Starling 1923). As Pickering (2010, fn. 12, pp. 422–424) makes clear, Ashby elaborated his theory well before he became familiar with Cannon’s work, although he only started to use the term “homeostasis” after reading it.

  7. 7.

    See Franchi (2013) and more extensively Franchi (2011b) for a discussion of this point.

References

  • Aristotle. (1984). The complete works of Aristotle. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ashby, W. R. (1952a). Can a mechanical chess-player outplay its designer? The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, III(9), 44–57.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ashby, W. R. (1952b). Design for a brain (1st ed.). New York: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ashby, W. R. (1954). The application of cybernetics to psychiatry. The British Journal of Psychiatry, 100(418), 114–214.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ashby, W. R. (1956). An introduction to cybernetics. London: Chapman and Hall.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Ashby, W. R. (1960). Design for a brain (2nd ed.). New York: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barandiaran, X., & Ruiz-Mirazo, K. (2008). Modelling autonomy: Simulating the essence of life and cognition. Biosystems, 91(2), 295–304.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Beer, R. D. (1995). On the dynamics of small continuous-time recurrent neural networks. Adaptive Behavior, 3(4), 471–511.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Beer, R. D. (1996). Toward the evolution of dynamical neural networks for minimally cognitive behavior. In P. Maes, M. J. Mataric, J. A. Meyer, J. Pollack, & S. W. Wilson (Eds.), From Animals to Animats 4: Proceedings of the Fourth International Conference on Simulation of Adaptive Behavior (pp. 419–429). Cambridge: MIT.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bekey, G. A. (2005). Autonomous robots: From biological inspiration to implementation and control. Cambridge: MIT.

    Google Scholar 

  • Berg, H. C. (2004). E. coli in motion. New York: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bernard, C. (1966[1878–1879]). Leçons sur les phénomènes de la vie communs aux animaux et aux vegetaux. Paris: Vrin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bernard, C. (1974). Lectures on the phenomena of life common to animals and plants. Springfield: Charles C. Thomas.

    Google Scholar 

  • Braitenberg, V. (1984). Vehicles. Experiments in synthetic psychology. Cambridge: MIT.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cannon, W. (1929). Organization for physiological homeostasis. Physiological Reviews, 9, 399–431.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cannon, W. (1939[1932]). The wisdom of the body (2nd ed.). New York: W.W. Norton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Capehart, B. L., & Terry, R. (1968). Digital simulation of homeostat modified to show memory and learning. IEEE Transactions on Systems Science and Cybernetics, SSC4(3), 188.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Descartes, R. (1988). The passions of the soul (Vol. 1, pp. 325–404). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Di Paolo, E. (2000). Homeostatic adaptation to inversion of the visual field and other sensorimotor disruptions. In J. A. Meyer, A. Berthoz, D. Floreano, H. L. Roitblat, & S. W. Wilson (Eds.), From Animals to Animats 6: Proceedings of the 6th International Conference on the Simulation of Adaptive Behavior (pp. 440–449). Cambridge: MIT.

    Google Scholar 

  • Di Paolo, E. (2005). Autopoiesis, adaptivity, teleology, agency. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 4(4), 429–452.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Di Paolo, E., Rohde, M., & Jaegher, H. D. (2010). Horizons for the enactive mind: Values, social interaction, and play. In J. Stewart, O. Gapenne, & E. Di Paolo (Eds.), Enaction: Towards a new paradigm for cognitive science. Cambridge: MIT.

    Google Scholar 

  • Egbert, M. D., Barandiaran, X. E., & Di Paolo, E. A. (2010). A minimal model of metabolism-based chemotaxis. PLoS Computational Biology, 6(12), e1001004.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Franchi, S. (2011a). Jammed machines and contingently fit animals: Psychoanalysis’s biological paradox. French Literature Series, 38, 213–256.

    Google Scholar 

  • Franchi, S. (2011b). Life, death, and resurrection of the homeostat. In S. Franchi & F. Bianchini (Eds.), The search for a theory of cognition: Early mechanisms and new ideas (pp. 3–51) Amsterdam: Rodopi.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Franchi, S. (2013). Homeostats for the 21st century? Lessons learned from simulating Ashby simulating the brain. Constructivist Foundations, 8(3), 501–532, with open peer commentaries and author’s response

    Google Scholar 

  • Haldane, J. S. (1917). Organism and environment as illustrated by the physiology of breathing. New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Haldane, J. S. (1922). Respiration. New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Haroules, G. G., & Haire, P. F. (1960). Jenny: An improved homeostat (Tech. Rep. AFCRC-TN-60-379), Air Force Cambridge Research Center.

    Google Scholar 

  • Henderson, L. J. (1928). Blood: A study in general physiology. New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husbands, P., & Holland, O. (2008). The ratio club: A hub of british cybernetics. In P. Husbands, O. Holland, & M. Wheeler (Eds.), The mechanical mind in history (pp. 91–148). Cambridge: MIT.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Ikegami, T., & Suzuki, K. (2008). From a homeostatic to a homeodynamic self. Biosystems, 91(2), 388–400.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Izquierdo, E. J., Aguilera, M., & Beer, R. D. (2013). Analysis of ultrastability in small dynamical recurrent neural networks. In Advances in Artificial Life, ECAL 2013. Proceedings of the Twelfth European Conference on the Synthesis and Simulation of Living Systems (pp. 51–58). Cambridge: MIT.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jonas, H. (1966). The phenomenon of life: Towards a philosophical biology. New York: Harper and Row.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jonas, H. (1984). The imperative of responsibility. Foundations of an ethics for the technological age. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jonas, H. (1996). Evolution and freedom: On the continuity among life-forms. In Mortality and morality. A search for the good after Auschwitz (pp. 59–74). Evanston: Northwestern University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant, I. (1952). The critique of judgment. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant, I. (1993). Opus postumum. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kant, I. (1999). Practical philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Malgrem, H. (2013). From Fechner, via Freud and Pavlov, to Ashby. Constructivist Foundations, 9(1), 104–105.

    Google Scholar 

  • Michel, O. (2004). Webots: Professional mobile robot simulation. Journal of Advanced Robotics Systems, 1(1), 39–42.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pfeifer, R., & Bongard, J. (2007). How the body shapes the way we think: A new view of intelligence (A Bradford book). Cambridge: MIT.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pickering, A. (2010). The cybernetic brain: Sketches of another future. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Plato. (1997). Complete works. Indianapolis: Hackett.

    Google Scholar 

  • Starling, E. H. (1923). The wisdom of the body. The Harveian oration, delivered before the royal college of physicians of London on St. Luke’s day, 1923. British Medical Journal, 2(3272), 685–690.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Varela, F. J. (1979). Principles of biological autonomy. New York: North-Holland.

    Google Scholar 

  • von Foerster, H., Mead, M., & Teuber, H. L. (Eds.). (1953). Cybernetics. Circular Causal and Feedback Mechanisms in Biological and Social Systems, Josiah Macy, Jr. Foundation, New York, transactions of the Ninth Conference, New York, March 20–21, 1952.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walter, W. G. (1961). The living brain. Harmondsworth: Penguin Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weber, A., & Varela, F. J. (2002). Life after Kant: Natural purposes and the autopoietic foundations of biological individuality. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 1(2), 97–125.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wilkins, M. G. (1968). A new homeostat (Tech. Rep. 8.3, bcl), Biological Computer Laboratory, University of Illinois at Urbana-Champaign.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Stefano Franchi .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2016 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Franchi, S. (2016). General Homeostasis, Passive Life, and the Challenge to Autonomy. In: Müller, V.C. (eds) Fundamental Issues of Artificial Intelligence. Synthese Library, vol 376. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-26485-1_17

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics