Skip to main content

Gödel’s Reception of Turing’s Model of Computability: The “Shift of Perception” in 1934

  • Conference paper
  • First Online:
Unveiling Dynamics and Complexity (CiE 2017)

Part of the book series: Lecture Notes in Computer Science ((LNTCS,volume 10307))

Included in the following conference series:

  • 670 Accesses

Abstract

The emergence of the mathematical concept of computability in the 1930 s was marked by an interesting shift of perspective, from viewing the intuitive concept, “human calculability following a fixed routine” in terms of calculability in a logic, to viewing the concept as more adequately expressed by Turing’s model.

Juliette Kennedy: I thank Liesbeth de Mol for the invitation to address a special session of CiE2017, and to contribute this extended abstract to its proceedings.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 39.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Gandy quote. See below.

  2. 2.

    See, e.g. Sieg [3], p. 387.

  3. 3.

    Some of the text below is adapted from the author’s [4].

  4. 4.

    [1], Sect. 14.8. Following Gandy we use the term “effectively computable,” or just “effective,”to mean “intuitively computable.”.

  5. 5.

    See [7], which relies on Church’s [8]. See also [9]. Emphasis the author’s.

  6. 6.

    The phrase “Church’s Thesis” was coined by Kleene in 1943. See his [10].

  7. 7.

    The proof of the equivalence developed in stages. See Davis, [11] and Sieg, [12].

  8. 8.

    Church, letter to Kleene November 29, 1935. Quoted in Sieg, op. cit., and in Davis [11].

  9. 9.

    Church, op.cit. In this talk and elsewhere we distinguish the axiomatic from the logical method, viewing the former as an informal notion, and the latter as involving a formalism.

  10. 10.

    [13], p. 357.

  11. 11.

    In detail, recursive enumerability would be guaranteed here by the so-called step-by-step argument: if each step is recursive then f will be recursive; and three conditions: (i) each rule must be a recursive operation, (ii) the set of rules and axioms must be recursively enumerable, (iii) the relation between a positive integer and the expression which stands for it must be recursive. Conditions i-iii are Sieg’s formulation of Church’s conditions. See Sieg, [12], p. 165. For Gandy’s formulation of the step-by-step argument, see [1], p. 77.

  12. 12.

    See also Sieg’s discussion of the “semi-circularity” of the step-by-step argument in his [12].

  13. 13.

    [1], p. 71. Of course this shift presaged a much more dramatic shift of perspective in 1936, inaugurated by the work of Turing together with Post’s earlier work.

  14. 14.

    See Gandy’s [1], p. 72.

  15. 15.

    Gödel was careful not to claim complete generality for the Second Incompleteness Theorem in his 1931 paper:

    For this [formalist JK] viewpoint presupposes only the existence of a consistency proof in which nothing but finitary means of proof is used, and it is conceivable that there exist finitary proofs that cannot be expressed in the formalism of P (or of M and A).Footnote 16

  16. 16.

    [15], p. 195. P is a variant of Principia Mathematica.

  17. 17.

    Sieg [16], p. 554.

  18. 18.

    [15], p. 346 and 349, resp. Emphasis added.

  19. 19.

    As Gödel would later write to Martin Davis, “...I was, at the time of these lectures, not at all convinced that my concept of recursion comprises all possible recursions.” Quoted in [15], p. 341.

  20. 20.

    [15], p. 361.

  21. 21.

    As Gödel wrote to Kreisel in 1965:

    That my [incompleteness] results were valid for all possible formal systems began to be plausible for me (that is since 1935) only because of the Remark printed on p. 83 of ‘The Undecidable’ ...But I was completely convinced only by Turing’s paper.Footnote 22

  22. 22.

    Quoted in Sieg [17], in turn quoting from an unpublished manuscript of Odifreddi, p. 65.

  23. 23.

    Or quintuples, in Turing’s original presentation.

  24. 24.

    As Sieg puts it [14], “The work of Gödel, Church, Kleene, and Hilbert and Bernays had intimate historical connections and is still of deep interest. It explicated calculability of functions by exactly one core notion, namely calculability of their values in logical calculi via (a finite number of) elementary steps. But no one gave convincing and non-circular reasons for the proposed rigorous restrictions on the steps that are permitted in calculations.”.

  25. 25.

    Remark to Hao Wang, [18], p. 203. Emphasis added.

  26. 26.

    [2], p. 80.

  27. 27.

    ibid, p. 85.

  28. 28.

    See Gödel’s letter to van Heijenoort of February 22, 1964, in [20].

References

  1. Gandy, R.: The confluence of ideas in 1936. In: The universal turing machine: A half-century survey, pp. 55–111. Oxford Science Publications, Oxford University Press, New York (1988)

    Google Scholar 

  2. Kripke, S.: The church-turing “Thesis” as a special corollary of gödel’s completeness theorem. In: Copeland, B.J., Posy, C.J., Shagrir, O. (eds.) Computability: Gödel, Church, and Beyond. MIT Press, Cambridge (2013)

    Google Scholar 

  3. Sieg, W.: Hilbert’s Programs and Beyond. Oxford University Press, Oxford (2013)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  4. Kennedy, J.: Turing, Gödel and the “Bright Abyss”. In: Philosophical Explorations of the Legacy of Alan Turing, vol. 324 of Boston Studies in Philosophy (Springer)

    Google Scholar 

  5. Gödel, K.: Über formal unentscheidbare Sätze der Principia Mathematica und verwandter Systeme I. Monatsh. Math. Phys. 38, 173–198 (1931)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  6. Church, A.: A set of postulates for the foundation of logic I, II. Ann. Math. 33(2), 346–366 (1932)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  7. Kleene, S.C., Rosser, J.B.: The inconsistency of certain formal logics. Ann. Math. 36(2), 630–636 (1935)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  8. Church, A.: The richard paradox. Amer. Math. Monthly 41, 356–361 (1934)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  9. Kleene, S.C.: Origins of recursive function theory. Ann. Hist. Comput. 3, 52–67 (1981)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  10. Kleene, S.C.: Recursive predicates and quantifiers. Trans. Am. Math. Soc. 53, 41–73 (1943)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  11. Davis, M.: Why Gödel didn’t have church’s thesis. Inf. Control 54, 3–24 (1982)

    Article  MATH  Google Scholar 

  12. Sieg, W.: Step by recursive step: Church’s analysis of effective calculability. Bull. Symbolic Log. 3, 154–180 (1997)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  13. Church, A.: A note on the Entscheidungsproblem. J. Symbolic Log. 1(1), 40–41 (1936). (Correction 1:101–102)

    Article  MATH  Google Scholar 

  14. Sieg, W.: Church without dogma: Axioms for computability. In: Cooper, S.B., Löwe, B., Sorbi, A. (eds.) New Computational Paradigms, pp. 139–152. Springer, New York (2008)

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  15. Gödel, K.: Collected works. Vol. I. The University Press, New York (1986). Publications 1929–1936, Edited and with a preface by Solomon Feferman. Clarendon Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  16. Sieg, W.: On computability. In: Philosophy of Mathematics. Handbook of the Philosophy of Science, pp. 535–630. Elsevier/North-Holland, Amsterdam (2009)

    Google Scholar 

  17. Sieg, W.: Gödel on computability. Philos. Math. 14(3), 189–207 (2006)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  18. Wang, H.: A Logical Journey. Representation and Mind. MIT Press, Cambridge (1996)

    Google Scholar 

  19. Post, E.L.: Recursively enumerable sets of positive integers and their decision problems. Bull. Am. Math. Soc. 50, 284–316 (1944)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  20. Gödel, K.: Collected Works. V: Correspondence H-Z. Oxford University Press, Oxford (2003). Feferman, S., et al. (eds.)

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Juliette Kennedy .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2017 Springer International Publishing AG

About this paper

Cite this paper

Kennedy, J. (2017). Gödel’s Reception of Turing’s Model of Computability: The “Shift of Perception” in 1934. In: Kari, J., Manea, F., Petre, I. (eds) Unveiling Dynamics and Complexity. CiE 2017. Lecture Notes in Computer Science(), vol 10307. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-58741-7_5

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-58741-7_5

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Cham

  • Print ISBN: 978-3-319-58740-0

  • Online ISBN: 978-3-319-58741-7

  • eBook Packages: Computer ScienceComputer Science (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics