Abstract
We outline a novel theory of natural language meaning, Rich Situated Semantics [RSS], on which the content of sentential utterances is semantically rich and informationally situated. In virtue of its situatedness, an utterance’s rich situated content varies with the informational situation of the cognitive agent interpreting the utterance. In virtue of its richness, this content contains information beyond the utterance’s lexically encoded information. The agent-dependence of rich situated content solves a number of problems in semantics and the philosophy of language (cf. [14, 20, 25]). In particular, since RSS varies the granularity of utterance contents with the interpreting agent’s informational situation, it solves the problem of finding suitably fine- or coarse-grained objects for the content of propositional attitudes. In virtue of this variation, a layman will reason with more propositions than an expert.
We would like to thank two anonymous referees for LENLS 13, Robin Cooper, Sebastian Löbner, Markus Werning, and Dietmar Zaefferer for their valuable comments and suggestions. The research for this paper is supported by the German Research Foundation (via K. Liefke’s grant LI 2562/1-1) and by LMU Munich’s Institutional Strategy LMUexcellent within the framework of the German Excellence Initiative.
Similar content being viewed by others
Notes
- 1.
We hereafter sometimes use the expression ‘content of a sentence’ (or ‘sentential content’), instead of ‘content of an utterance of a sentence’. This is merely a terminological shortcut. The reader is asked to keep in mind that sentences are uttered by a speaker (with certain background information) in a spatiotemporal and communicative situation, and are directed at an addressee (with a certain, likely different, background information). The relevance of the addressee’s information for the interpretation of the utterance is the central topic of this paper.
- 2.
- 3.
- 4.
To avoid the inclusion of information that does not regard the subject matter, we demand (contra Perry) that both conjuncts be aboutness-relevant. This also avoids the problem of obtaining aboutness-‘relevant’ conjunctions by combining an aboutness-irrelevant sentence with a trivially aboutness-relevant verum, or with falsum.
- 5.
This is due to the fact that the available information about the sentence’s subject matter at these situations will include the sentence’s lexical information. Since we have excluded impossible situations from our considerations (cf. fn. 3), no situation contains both an item of information and its complement.
- 6.
The identification of these sentences’ traditional contents in possible world semantics is due to the fact that, in the actual world at the current time (cf. the adjective exist-ing in (10)), groundhogs are the largest marmot species.
- 7.
The ability of (11b) to extend the reasoner’s knowledge depends on this unfamiliarity.
- 8.
Admittedly, the reasoner may wrongly assume that Len also knows (10). This assumption explains why the reasoner may still make the inference from (12). It can be captured by replacing the reasoner’s required awareness of the inclusion of a particular item of information in the agent’s information state by the reasoner’s belief about this inclusion (which does not entail the factivity of this inclusion).
- 9.
Entailment is here defined in terms of (subset) inclusion of sets of possible worlds.
- 10.
This inference assumes that the complements of the two occurrences of remember from (22) describe the same remembered situation. The intuitive validity of this type of inference is discussed in detail in [20, Sects. 4, 5].
- 11.
These include Pierre’s simultaneous belief that London is pretty and that London is not pretty (cf. [16]).
- 12.
References
Barsalou, L.W.: Frames, concepts, and conceptual fields. In: Lehrer, A., Kittay, E.F. (eds.) Frames, Fields, and Contrasts: New Essays in Semantic and Lexical Organization. Erlbaum Associate, Erlbaum (1992)
Barwise, J., Cooper, R.: Generalized quantifiers and natural language. Linguist. Philos. 4(2), 159–219 (1981)
Barwise, J., Perry, J.: Situations and Attitudes. MIT Press, Cambridge (1983)
Carston, R.: Explicit communication and ‘free’ pragmatic enrichment. In: Soria, B., Romero, E. (eds.) Explicit Communication: Robyn Carston’s Pragmatics. Palgrave Macmillan, Basingstoke (2010)
Chalmers, D.: The representational character of experience. In: Leiter, B. (ed.) The Future for Philosophy. Oxford UP, Oxford (2004)
Egan, A., Hawthorne, J., Weatherson, B.: Epistemic modals in context. In: Preyer, G., Peter, G. (eds.) Contextualism in Philosophy. Oxford UP, Oxford (2005)
Fara, D.G.: Specifying desires. Noüs 47(2), 250–272 (2013)
Fox, C., Lappin, S., Pollard, C.: A higher-order fine-grained logic for intensional semantics. In: Proceedings of the 7th International Symposium on Logic and Language (2002)
Fox, C., Lappin, S.: Foundations of Intensional Semantics. Blackwell, Hoboken (2005)
Frege, G.: Über Sinn und Bedeutung. Gottlob Frege: Kleine Schriften. Edition Classic Verlag Dr. Müller (2006)
Groenendijk, J., Stokhof, M.: Dynamic predicate logic. Linguist. Philos. 14(1), 39–100 (1991)
Hintikka, J.: Impossible possible worlds vindicated. J. Philos. Logic 4(4), 475–484 (1975)
Kaplan, D.: Demonstratives: an essay on the semantics, logic, metaphysics, and epistemology of demonstratives and other indexicals. In: Almog, J., Perry, J., Wettstein, H. (eds.) Themes from Kaplan. Oxford UP, Oxford (1989)
King, J., Soames, S., Speaks, J.: New Thinking about Propositions. Oxford UP, Oxford (2014)
Kratzer, A.: An investigation into the lumps of thought. Linguist. Philos. 12(5), 607–653 (1989)
Kripke, S.: A puzzle about belief. In: Margalit, A. (ed.) Meaning and Use: papers presented at the Second Jerusalem Philosophy Encounter. Reidel, Kufstein (1979)
Lewis, D.: Index, context, and content. In: Kanger, S., Ōhman, S. (eds.) Philosophy and Grammar. Synthese Library, vol. 143. Springer, Netherlands, Dordrecht (1981). doi:10.1007/978-94-009-9012-8_6
Liefke, K.: A single-type semantics for natural language. Doctoral dissertation, Center for Logic and Philosophy of Science, Tilburg (2014)
Liefke, K.: Towards an account of rich situated semantic content. In: Gamerschlag, T., et al. (eds.) Abstracts of Cognitive Structures: Linguistic, Philosophical, and Psychological Perspectives, Düsseldorf, 15–17 September 2016. http://cognitive-structures.phil.hhu.de/wp-content/uploads/2016/09/Updated-program-brochure-14-09.pdf
Liefke, K., Werning, M.: Evidence for single-type semantics - an alternative to e/t-based dual-type semantics (submitted)
Löbner, S.: Evidence for frames from human language. In: Gamerschlag, T., Gerland, D., Osswald, R., Petersen, W. (eds.) Frames and Concept Types. SLP, vol. 94, pp. 23–67. Springer, Cham (2014). doi:10.1007/978-3-319-01541-5_2
MacFarlane, J.: Epistemic modals are assessment-sensitive. In: Egan, A., Weatherson, B. (eds.) Epistemic Modality. Oxford UP, Oxford (2011)
Moltmann, F.: Part structures in situations: the semantics of individual and whole. Linguist. Philos. 28(5), 599–641 (2005)
Moltmann, F.: Abstract Objects and the Semantics of Natural Language. Oxford UP, Oxford (2013)
Moltmann, F.: Propositions, attitudinal objects, and the distinction between actions and products. Can. J. Philos. 43(5–6), 679–701 (2013)
Moltmann, F.: Cognitive products and the semantics of attitude verbs and deontic modals. In: Moltmann, F., Textor, M. (eds.) Act-Based Conceptions of Propositional Content: Contemporary and Historical Perspectives. Oxford UP, Oxford (forthcoming)
Montague, R.: The proper treatment of quantification in ordinary English. In: Thomason, R.H. (ed.) Formal Philosophy: selected papers of Richard Montague. Yale UP, New Haven (1974)
Muskens, R.: Meaning and Partiality. CSLI Publications, Stanford (1995)
Muskens, R.: Sense and the computation of reference. Linguist. Philos. 28(4), 473–504 (2005)
Perry, J.: Possible worlds and subject matter. In: Sturé, A. (ed.) Possible Worlds in Humanities, Arts and Sciences. Walter de Gruyter, Berlin (1989)
Pollard, C.: Hyperintensions. J. Logic Comput. 18(2), 257–282 (2008)
Pollard, C.: Agnostic hyperintensional semantics. Synthese 192, 535–562 (2015)
Prior, A.: Objects of Thought. Clarendon Press, Wotton-under-Edge (1971)
Recanati, F.: Pragmatic enrichment. In: Russell, G., Fara, D.G. (eds.) The Routledge Companoin to Philosophy of Language. Routledge, Abingdon (2012)
Rantala, V.: Quantified modal logic: non-normal worlds and propositional attitudes. Stud. Logica. 41(1), 41–65 (1982)
Salmon, N.: The resilience of illogical belief. Noûs 40(2), 369–375 (2006)
Schiffer, S.: The mode-of-presentation problem. In: Anderson, C.A., Owens, J. (eds.) Propositional Attitudes: The Role of Content in Logic, Language, and Mind. CSLI Lecture Notes, vol. 20. CSLI Publications, Stanford (1990)
Schiffer, S.: Belief ascription. J. Philos. 89(10), 499–521 (1992)
Searle, J.: Proper names. Mind 67(266), 166–173 (1958)
Stanovic, K.E.: Who is Rational?: Studies of Individual Differences in Reasoning. Routledge Psychology Press, Abingdon (2011)
Thomason, R.H.: A model theory for the propositional attitudes. Linguist. Philos. 4(1), 47–70 (1980)
Veltman, F.: Defaults in update semantics. J. Philos. Logic 25(3), 221–261 (1996)
Author information
Authors and Affiliations
Corresponding author
Editor information
Editors and Affiliations
Rights and permissions
Copyright information
© 2017 Springer International Publishing AG
About this paper
Cite this paper
Liefke, K., Bowker, M. (2017). Rich Situated Attitudes. In: Kurahashi, S., Ohta, Y., Arai, S., Satoh, K., Bekki, D. (eds) New Frontiers in Artificial Intelligence. JSAI-isAI 2016. Lecture Notes in Computer Science(), vol 10247. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-61572-1_4
Download citation
DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-61572-1_4
Published:
Publisher Name: Springer, Cham
Print ISBN: 978-3-319-61571-4
Online ISBN: 978-3-319-61572-1
eBook Packages: Computer ScienceComputer Science (R0)