Abstract
While studies in the philosophy of mathematics often emphasize reliability over clarity, much study of the explanatory power of proof errs in the other direction. We argue that Hanna’s distinction between ‘formal’ and ‘acceptable’ proof misunderstands the role of proof in Hilbert’s program. That program explicitly seeks the existence of a justification; the notion of proof is not intended to represent the notion of a ‘good’ proof. In particular, the studies reviewed here of mathematical induction miss the explanatory heart of such a proof; how to proceed from suggestive example to universal rule. We discuss the role of algebra in attaining the goal of generalizability and abstractness often taken as keys to being explanatory. In examining several proofs of the closed form for the sum of the first n natural numbers, we expose the hidden inductive definitions in the ‘immediate arguments’ such as Gauss’s proof. This connection with inductive definition leads to applications far beyond verifying numerical identities. We discuss some objections, which we find more basic than those in the literature, to Lange’s general argument that proofs by mathematical induction are not explanatory. We conclude by arguing that whether a proof is explanatory depends on a context of clear hypothesis and understanding what is supposedly explained to who.
Access this chapter
Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout
Purchases are for personal use only
Similar content being viewed by others
Notes
- 1.
Page 26 of [Cof91].
- 2.
Section 3 of [HM05] give several specific examples of mathematicians using ‘explain’ in various senses.
- 3.
He and another U.I.C. mathematician, Neil Rickert, once held the record for the largest pair of twin primes.
- 4.
I added the parenthetical descriptions. And, I modified the question because as originally phrased, the first question is not asked. But the explanations proffered by Hanna all deal with it.
- 5.
There are various logics for studying this topic [Lin14]; but they are not considered in the papers under discussion.
- 6.
- 7.
While this statement is appealing to students, a more formal version with the same proof is: How many edges are there in the complete symmetric graph on n vertices?.
- 8.
This assertion of course depends on where I begin my arithmetic. There is no trace of arithmetic, if my assumption is that \((N,+,\times )\) is a semi-ring (ring without additive inverse). But there is if I go back one step further and define multiplication inductively from addition.
- 9.
There is also a geometrical picture to understand the algebra in the numerator of this calculation. Represent \(n(n+1)\) by an n high by \(n+1\) wide rectangle. Then to add \(2(n+1)\), place two 1 by n strips on top of the rectangle.
- 10.
Paul Sally presented this argument at a University of Chicago class for high school teachers on Aug. 3/4, 2012. Doubtless, the approach is old; the use of telescoping series dates at least to the Bernoulli’s, Euler and Goldbach [BVP06]. Sally was not only a distinguished researcher in p-adic analysis and representation theory but a national leader in Mathematics Education.
- 11.
A set X is defined by generalized inductive definition if there is rule assigning to each finite subset \(X_0\) of X some larger set \(X_0'\) (the closure of \(X_0\)) and for each \(X_0 \subset X\), \(X_0' \subset X\). This notion is given a more inductive format if one starts with a set Y and successively closes it to obtain X [Sho67].
- 12.
We take the version form [Mar02] but similar accounts can be found in any modern logic text.
- 13.
- 14.
This ignores, of course, the many uses of mathematical induction to prove P(n) and for each \(k\ge n\), \(P(k) \rightarrow P(k+1)\) then for all \(k\ge n\), P(k). His argument could be complicated to handle this case as well as it does the one it explicitly addresses, but he doesn’t even consider such situations.
- 15.
Baker [Bak10] notes this objection but does not develop it.
- 16.
If one were to develop this argument in first order logic, Q would be a formula. However, in the spirit of the general discussion of induction we describe here informal mathematical arguments.
- 17.
Here, Q is the set of possible coordinatizations.
- 18.
In fact, Hanna’s article in an educational journal reflects the common use of Gauss’ proof for future American teachers of middle school mathematics. The goal of the activity is not understanding the step from example to universal but just some notion of justification.
References
Anon. Montrous moonshine. https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Monstrous_moonshine. Accessed Apr 2016
Baker, A.: Mathematical induction and explanation. Analysis 70, 681–689 (2010)
Baldwin, J.T.: Formalization, primitive concepts, and purity. Rev. Symb. Log. 6, 87–128 (2013). http://homepages.math.uic.edu/ jbaldwin/pub/purityandvocab10.pdf
Baldwin, J.T.: Completeness and categoricity (in power): formalization without foundationalism. Bull. Symb. Log. 20, 39–79 (2014). http://homepages.math.uic.edu/jbaldwin/pub/catcomnovbib2013.pdf
Baldwin, J.T.: Formalization Without Foundationalism; Model Theory and the Philosophy of Mathematics Practice. Book manuscript available on request (2015)
Burgess, J.P.: Putting structuralism in its place. Preprint (2010)
Bussey, W.H.: The origin of mathematical induction. Am. Math. Mon. 24, 199–207 (1917)
Bibiloni, L., Viader, P., Paradís, J.: On a series of Goldbach and Euler. Bull. AMS 113, 206–221 (2006)
Cajori, F.: Origin of the name “mathematical induction”. Am. Math. Mon. 25, 197–201 (1918). https://archive.org/stream/jstor-2972638/2972638_djvu.txt
Cariani, F.: Mathematical induction and explanatory value in mathematics. Preprint (2016)
Coffa, A.: The Semantic Traditin from Kant to Carnap: To the Vienna Station. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (1991)
Dedekind, R.: Essays on the Theory of Numbers. Dover, New York (1963). As first published by Open Court Publications 1901: first German 1888th
Hanna, G.: Some pedagogical aspects of proof. Interchange 21, 6–13 (1990)
Harris, M.: Mathematics Without Apologies: Portrait of a Problematic Vocation. Princeton University Press, Princeton (2015)
Hafner, J., Mancosu, P.: The varieties of mathematical explanation. In: Mancosu, P., Jørgensen, K.F., Pedersen, S. (eds.) Visualization, Explanation, and Reasoning Styles in Mathematics. Synthese Library, vol. 327, pp. 215–250. Springer, Netherlands (2005)
Lange, A.M.: Explanation by induction. Preprint
Lange, M.: Why proofs by mathematical induction are generally not explanatory. Analysis 69, 203–211 (2009)
Linnebo, Ø.: Plural quantification. In: The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2014th edn.) (2014). http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2014/entries/plural-quant/
Mancosu, P.: Mathematical explanation: why it matters. In: Mancosu, P. (ed.) The Philosophy of Mathematical Practice, pp. 134–150. Oxford University Press, Oxford (2008)
Marker, D.: Model Theory: An Introduction. Graduate Texts in Mathematics, vol. 217. Springer, New York (2002)
Quine, W.V.O.: Set Theory and Its Logic. Harvard, Cambridge (1969)
Resnik, M., Kushner, D.: Explanation, independence, and realism in mathematics. Ann. Math. Log. 38, 141–158 (1987)
Shoenfield, J.: Mathematical Logic. Addison-Wesley, Reading (1967)
Steiner, M.: Mathematical explanation. Philos. Stud. 34, 135–151 (1978)
Tappenden, J.: Proof style and understanding in mathematics I: visualization, unification and axiom choice. In: Mancosu, P., Jørgensen, K.F., Pedersen, S. (eds.) Visualization, Explanation, and Reasoning Styles in Mathematics. Synthese Library, vol. 327, pp. 147–214. Springer, Netherlands (2005)
Thurston, W.P.: On proof and progress in mathematics. Bull. Am. Math. Soc. 30, 161–177 (1994)
Wysocki, T.: Mathematical induction, grounding, and causal explanation. Presentation at APA meeting Chicago, March 2016
Author information
Authors and Affiliations
Corresponding author
Editor information
Editors and Affiliations
Rights and permissions
Copyright information
© 2016 Springer-Verlag Berlin Heidelberg
About this paper
Cite this paper
Baldwin, J.T. (2016). Foundations of Mathematics: Reliability and Clarity: The Explanatory Role of Mathematical Induction. In: Väänänen, J., Hirvonen, Å., de Queiroz, R. (eds) Logic, Language, Information, and Computation. WoLLIC 2016. Lecture Notes in Computer Science(), vol 9803. Springer, Berlin, Heidelberg. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-662-52921-8_5
Download citation
DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-662-52921-8_5
Published:
Publisher Name: Springer, Berlin, Heidelberg
Print ISBN: 978-3-662-52920-1
Online ISBN: 978-3-662-52921-8
eBook Packages: Computer ScienceComputer Science (R0)