Skip to main content

Testing Minimax for Rational Ignorant Agents

  • Conference paper
  • First Online:

Part of the book series: Lecture Notes in Computer Science ((LNTCS,volume 10455))

Abstract

Richard Pettigrew [13, 14] defends the following theses: (1) epistemic disutility can be measured with strictly proper scoring rules (like the Brier score) and (2) at the beginning of their credal lives, rational agents ought to minimize their worst-case epistemic disutility (Minimax). This leads to a Principle of Indifference for ignorant agents. However, Pettigrew offers no argument in favour of Minimax, suggesting that the epistemic conservatism underlying it is a “normative bedrock.” Is there a way to test Minimax? In this paper, we argue that, since Pettigrew’s Minimax is impermissive, an argument against credence permissiveness constitutes an argument in favour of Minimax, and that arguments for credence permissiveness are arguments against Minimax.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   39.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD   54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    We borrowed this example from Schoenfield [18, p. 640].

  2. 2.

    In such a case Pria is facing a situation akin to the one an agent faces in the famous Ellsberg paradox. In our framework, however, there is no need to make a distinction between risk and uncertainty, since in all cases, Pria is maximally ignorant. Indeed, since she has no prior information, she is always dealing with uncertainty. Minimax does not in fact solve the Ellsberg paradox: it simply avoids it when it is used by a maximally ignorant agent.

  3. 3.

    Readers interested in the formal aspects of strictly proper scoring rules and the Principle of Indifference may consult [13,14,15], and also [19] for a discussion on the relation between the Principle of Indifference and inductive inference.

  4. 4.

    See [3].

  5. 5.

    The expected result is sometimes called the weighted mean result. For example, suppose that, in a fair lottery, 5 participants each have 1 chance in 5 to win a single prize of $50. In that lottery, 4 participants won’t win a prize, and 1 participant will win $50. Since (40 + 150)/5 = 10, the weighted mean value of this lottery is $10. This means that $10 is the expected prize to each participant.

  6. 6.

    For various recent arguments against credence uniqueness, one may consult [2, 9, 10, 12, 15, 16]. For various recent arguments in favour of credence uniqueness, one may consult [5, 6, 20, 21].

  7. 7.

    Specifically, while every agent could be bound to a specific impermissive scoring rule and a specific impermissive decision rule, different agents could be bound to distinct incompatible scoring rules or distinct incompatible decision rules.

  8. 8.

    What we here call a “carving” is sometimes called a partition elsewhere. The reason for this terminological choice is that, in the literature from which our paper draws, “carving” is a much more popular term.

  9. 9.

    Decidability should be understood in its most basic sense: given an input (evidential carving), there is always an effective method for returning an output (credence assignment).

  10. 10.

    Horowitz refers to Pettigrew’s book Accuracy and the Laws of Credence [13], where he uses the expression “Maximin”. We refer to his paper “Accuracy, Risk and the Principle of Indifference” [14] where he uses the expression “Minimax”. Both terms refer to the same decision rule.

  11. 11.

    See [13], Sect. 4.3] for formal definitions and the importance of calibration. Decomposition is crucial to Pettigrew’s account of accuracy: it allows him to exclude uncalibrated divergence measures. Roughly, an agent has a calibrated credence X in P if, relative to a body of evidence, X is the proportion of all propositions of a certain type (P) that appear to be true. This is the distinctive feature of strictly proper scoring rules: an agent’s expected score is maximized by assigning calibrated credences in P. For example, the following improper scoring rule respects Alethic vindication, Perfectionism, Divergence Additivity and Divergence Continuity but violates Decomposition:

    1. 1.

      Relative to an agent’s credence X in P, if P is true, then the agent’s score is \((1-X);\)

    2. 2.

      Relative to an agent’s credence X in P, if P is false, then the agent’s score is \(|0-X|\).

    See also [13, pp. 37–40, 48].

  12. 12.

    Some authors have suggested that there are no distinct consistency requirements of rationality. Specifically, it is possible that process requirements of rationality, which govern how rational agents form and revise beliefs, secure consistency [11]. What matters in this paper is that inconsistent agents violated at least one rationality requirement. See also [4, sect. 9.2] on consistency requirements.

  13. 13.

    We simply calculated the derivative of this function to find its optimum. The derivative of the function \(f(X) = 0.8 \cdot ((1-X)^{3/2}) + 0.2 \cdot ((0-X)^{3/2})\) is equal to 0 when \(X \approx 0.941\).

  14. 14.

    The derivative of the function \(f(X) = 0.8 \cdot ((1-X)^3) + 0.2 \cdot ((0-X)^3)\) is equal to 0 when \(X \approx 0.666\).

  15. 15.

    While we focused on two instances of improper scoring rules, the same problem would arise with any improper scoring rule. The fact that a scoring rule is not uniquely optimized when \(Z = X\) explains why an agent could end up with an inconsistent combination of attitudes. Only improper scoring rules are not uniquely optimized when \(Z = X\).

References

  1. Aumann, R.J.: Agreeing to disagree. Annals Stat. 4, 1236–1239 (1976)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  2. Ballantyne, N., Coffman, E.J.: Uniqueness, evidence, and rationality. Philos. Impr. 11(18), 1–13 (2011)

    Google Scholar 

  3. Brier, G.W.: Verification of forecasts expressed in terms of probability. Mon. Weather Rev. 78(1), 1–3 (1950)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  4. Broome, J.: Rationality Through Reasoning. Wiley, Oxford (2013)

    Book  Google Scholar 

  5. Christensen, D.: Conciliation, Uniqueness and Rational Toxicity. Noûs. doi:10.1111/nous.12077 (2014)

  6. Horowitz, S.: Immoderately Rational. Philos. Stud. 167(1), 41–56 (2014)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  7. Horowitz, S.: Laws of credence and laws of choice. Episteme 14(1), 31–37 (2017). doi:10.1017/epi.2016.49

    Article  Google Scholar 

  8. Kelly, T.: The Epistemic Significance of Disagreement. In: Gendler, T.S., Hawthorne, J. (eds.) Oxford Studies in Epistemology, pp. 167–96. Clarendon Press, Oxford (2005)

    Google Scholar 

  9. Kelly, T.: Peer disagreement and higher-order evidence. In: Warfield, T., Feldman, R. (eds.) Disagreement, pp. 111–72. Oxford University Press, Oxford (2010)

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  10. Kelly, T.: Evidence can be permissive. In: Steup, M., Turri, J., Sosa, E. (eds.) Contemporary Debates in Epistemology, pp. 298–312. Wiley, Boston (2014)

    Google Scholar 

  11. Kolodny, N.: State or process requirements? Mind 116(462), 372–385 (2007)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  12. Meacham, C.G.: Impermissive Bayesianism. Erkenntnis 79(6), 1185–1217 (2014)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  13. Pettigrew, R.: Accuracy and the Laws of Credence. Oxford University Press, Oxford (2016a)

    Book  Google Scholar 

  14. Pettigrew, R.: Accuracy, risk, and the principle of indifference. Philos. Phenomenol. Res. 92(1), 35–59 (2016b). doi:10.1111/phpr.12097

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  15. Predd, J.B., Seiringer, R., Lieb, E.H., Osherson, D.N., Vincent Poor, H., Kulkarni, S.R.: Probabilistic coherence and proper scoring rules. IEEE 55(10), 4786–4792 (2009)

    MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  16. Sharadin, N.: A paritial defense of permissivism. Ratio 30, 57–71 (2015). http://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/rati.12115/full

    Article  Google Scholar 

  17. Schoenfield, M.: Permission to believe: why permissivism is true and what it tells us about irrelevant influences on belief. Noûs. 48(2), 193–218 (2014)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  18. Schoenfield, M.: Bridging rationality and accuracy. J. Philos. 112(12), 633–57 (2015). doi:10.5840/jphil20151121242

    Article  Google Scholar 

  19. Smithson, R.: The principle of indifference and inductive scepticism. Brit. J. Phil. Sci. 68, 253–272 (2017)

    MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  20. White, R.: Epistemic Permissiveness. Philos. Perspect. 19(1), 445–459 (2005)

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  21. White, R.: Evidence cannot be permissive. In: Steup, M., Turri, J., Sosa, E. (eds.) Contemporary Debates in Epistemology, pp. 312–23. Wiley, Boston (2014)

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Marc-Kevin Daoust .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2017 Springer-Verlag GmbH Germany

About this paper

Cite this paper

Daoust, MK., Montminy, D. (2017). Testing Minimax for Rational Ignorant Agents. In: Baltag, A., Seligman, J., Yamada, T. (eds) Logic, Rationality, and Interaction. LORI 2017. Lecture Notes in Computer Science(), vol 10455. Springer, Berlin, Heidelberg. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-662-55665-8_37

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-662-55665-8_37

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Berlin, Heidelberg

  • Print ISBN: 978-3-662-55664-1

  • Online ISBN: 978-3-662-55665-8

  • eBook Packages: Computer ScienceComputer Science (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics