Skip to main content

Beating the Gatecrasher Paradox with Judiciary Narratives

  • Conference paper
  • First Online:
Logic, Rationality, and Interaction (LORI 2017)

Part of the book series: Lecture Notes in Computer Science ((LNTCS,volume 10455))

Included in the following conference series:

  • 1186 Accesses

Abstract

A probabilistic model for the narrative approach to reasoning in legal fact-finding is developed and applied to the gatecrasher paradox.

The research has been supported by Research Foundation Flanders.

The research was funded by National Centre for Science grant number 2016/22/E/HS1/00304.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Subscribe and save

Springer+ Basic
$34.99 /Month
  • Get 10 units per month
  • Download Article/Chapter or eBook
  • 1 Unit = 1 Article or 1 Chapter
  • Cancel anytime
Subscribe now

Buy Now

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. 1.

    The paradox is mathematically the same as the prisoners in a yard scenario [13], where a group of prisoners commits a group killing, and it’s impossible to identify the single innocent prisoner.

  2. 2.

    The content of the guilt statement is \(\mathtt {G}\) which has the form of \(G\equiv g_1\wedge \cdots \wedge g_l\) for appropriate \(g_1, \dots , g _l\in \mathcal {L}\).

  3. 3.

    In contexts in which it is irrelevant whether a narration is an accusing one or not, I will suppress the superscripts.

  4. 4.

    A set of sentences is relevant for the case if it is consistent with the background knowledge and there is a narration such that its posterior probability given all background knowledge together with that set is different from its posterior probability given all background knowledge only. A set of sentences is a minimal relevant set if no proper subset thereof is a relevant set. A sentence is relevant if it or its negation is a member of a minimal relevant subset.

References

  1. Allen, R.J.: No plausible alternative to a plausible story of guilt as the rule of decision in criminal cases. In: Cruz, L.L.J. (ed.) Proof and Standards of Proof in the Law, Northwestern University School of Law, pp. 10–27 (2010)

    Google Scholar 

  2. Allen, R.J., Pardo, M.S.: The problematic value of mathematical models of evidence. J. Legal Stud. 36(1), 107–140 (2007). doi:10.1086/508269

    Article  Google Scholar 

  3. Bernoulli, J.: Ars Conjectandi (1713)

    Google Scholar 

  4. Jonathan Cohen, L.: The Probable and the Provable. Oxford University Press, Oxford (1977). doi:10.2307/2219193

    Book  Google Scholar 

  5. Jonathan Cohen, L.: Subjective probability and the paradox of the gatecrasher. Ariz. State Law J. 627–634 (1981)

    Google Scholar 

  6. Dant, M.: Gambling on the truth: the use of purely statistical evidence as a basis for civil liability. Columbia J. Law Soc. Probl. 22, 31–70 (1988)

    Google Scholar 

  7. Di Bello, M.: Statistics and probability in criminal trials. Ph.D. thesis, University of Stanford (2013)

    Google Scholar 

  8. Haack, S.: Evidence Matters: Science, Proof, and Truth in the Law. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (2014)

    Book  Google Scholar 

  9. Haack, S.: Legal probabilism: an epistemological dissent. In: [8], pp. 47–77. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (2014)

    Google Scholar 

  10. Ho, H.L.: A Philosophy of Evidence Law: Justice in the Search for Truth. Oxford University Press, Oxford (2008)

    Book  Google Scholar 

  11. Lepage, F.: Partial probability functions and intuitionistic logic. Bull. Sect. Logic 41(3/4), 173–184 (2012)

    MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  12. Lepage, F., Morgan, C.: Probabilistic canonical models for partial logics. Notre Dame J. Formal Logic 44(3), 125–138 (2003)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  13. Nesson, C.R.: Reasonable doubt and permissive inferences: the value of complexity. Harv. Law Rev. 92(6), 1187–1225 (1979). doi:10.2307/1340444

    Article  Google Scholar 

  14. Stein, A.: Foundations of Evidence Law. Oxford University Press, Oxford (2005)

    Book  Google Scholar 

  15. Tribe, L.H.: A further critique of mathematical proof. Harv. Law Rev. 84, 1810–1820 (1971)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  16. Tribe, L.H.: Trial by mathematics: precision and ritual in the legal process. Harv. Law Rev. 84(6), 1329–1393 (1971)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  17. Underwood, B.D.: The thumb on the scale of justice: burdens of persuasion in criminal cases. Yale Law J. 86(7), 1299–1348 (1977). doi:10.2307/795788

    Article  Google Scholar 

  18. Wells, G.L.: Naked statistical evidence of liability: Is subjective probability enough? J. Pers. Soc. Psychol. 62(5), 739–752 (1992). doi:10.1037/0022-3514.62.5.739

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Rafal Urbaniak .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2017 Springer-Verlag GmbH Germany

About this paper

Cite this paper

Urbaniak, R. (2017). Beating the Gatecrasher Paradox with Judiciary Narratives. In: Baltag, A., Seligman, J., Yamada, T. (eds) Logic, Rationality, and Interaction. LORI 2017. Lecture Notes in Computer Science(), vol 10455. Springer, Berlin, Heidelberg. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-662-55665-8_44

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-662-55665-8_44

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Berlin, Heidelberg

  • Print ISBN: 978-3-662-55664-1

  • Online ISBN: 978-3-662-55665-8

  • eBook Packages: Computer ScienceComputer Science (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics