Skip to main content

Goodman’s Only World

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Between Logic and Reality

Part of the book series: Logic, Epistemology, and the Unity of Science ((LEUS,volume 25))

Abstract

An incorrect interpretation of Goodman’s theory of counterfactuals is persistently being offered in the literature. I find that strange. Even more so since the incorrectness is rather obvious. In this paper I try to figure out why is that happening. First I try to explain what Goodman did say, which of his claims are ignored, and what he did not say but is sometimes ascribed to him. I emphasize one of the bad features of the interpretation: it gives counterfactuals some formal properties that neither Goodman nor (usually) the interpreter would accept. The usual interpretation (UI), which I claim should not be ascribed to Goodman, considers a counterfactual \(\mathrm{A}\rightarrow \mathrm{C}\) true iff A, together with natural laws and all contingent truths cotenable with it, entails C. (UI) makes valid the law of conditional excluded middle, which Goodman clearly rejected. Among possible reasons for which the interpreters might find (UI) adequate is that (UI), as I argue, smuggles in the idea of minimal change, which is otherwise attractive, natural to many, but not to be found anywhere in Goodman’s paper. At the end I stress the significance of Goodman’s theory by arguing that we still need some of his notions to test the adequacy of our modern theories.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

eBook
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Goodman 1947 [8], which is the subject of this paper, was reprinted in 1954 [9] and 1983 [11] and elsewhere. References here are to [11], where some changes have been made to the original 1947 paper.

  2. 2.

    Edgington [6, p. 248]. The interpretation says: “A counterfactual conditional ‘\(A\rightarrow C\)’ is true if and only if there is a conjunction of truths T which include a law of nature [and satisfy condition X] such that \(A\& T\) entails C.” And a bit later on the same page: “Then the square bracket reads ‘and are cotenable with A’.”

  3. 3.

    Loewer [15, p. 106]: “It is interesting to note that had we construed Goodman’s definition of cotenability as requiring that A be cotenable with each member of S rather than with the conjunction of the members of S we would have obtained a system in which CEM is valid.”

  4. 4.

    The rule RCK that allows the last step need not concerns us here. The book used to be available on-line at http://www.phil.gu.se/johan/johan.html and the page number refers to the version downloaded from that site.

  5. 5.

    See Nute’s classification of minimal, small, and maximal change theories in Nute and Cross [17].

  6. 6.

    This system is the same as Stalnaker’s minus CEM. Cf. Lewis [13, chapter 6].

  7. 7.

    These theories are know in the literature under different names. Lewis [13] called them “metalinguistic”, and later [14] thought that “premise semantics” was a better name. Bennett [2, p. 303] calls them “support” theories. Hansson [12] uses the term “derivability theory”. Arlo-Costa [1] calls them “cotenability theories”.

  8. 8.

    It is often just assumed that such a simple requirement as (*) is obeyed by a possible world theory, but it is not a trivial matter. In [4, chapters 4 and 5], and [5] I have argued that the so called standard theories of counterfactuals (more precisely, any total ordering minimal or small change semantics for counterfactuals based on an absolute similarity relation or selection function) cannot fulfil that requirement, which makes them inadequate.

References

  1. Arlo-Costa, Horacio. 2009. “The Logic of Conditionals.” In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2009 Edition), edited by Edward N. Zalta. Accessed Mar 20, 2010. http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2009/entries/logic-conditionals/

  2. Bennett, Jonathan. 2003. A Philosophical Guide to Conditionals. New York, NY Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  3. Cross, Charles B. 1985. “Jonathan Bennett on ‘even if’.” Linguistics and Philosophy 8:353–57.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  4. Djordjevic, Vladan. 2005. Counterfactuals. PhD Thesis. Alberta: University of Alberta.

    Google Scholar 

  5. Djordjevic, Vladan. Forthcoming. “Similarity and Cotenability.” In Between Logic and Intuition: David Lewis and the Future of Formal Methods in Philosophy, edited by J. van Bentham, V. Hendricks, J. Symons, and S. A. Pedersen. Synthese Library.

    Google Scholar 

  6. Edgington, Dorothy. 1995. “On Conditionals.” Mind 104:235–329.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  7. Gabbay, Dov M. 1972. “A General Theory of the Conditional in Terms of a Ternary Operator.” Theoria 38:97–104.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  8. Goodman, Nelson. 1947. “The Problem of Counterfactual Conditionals.” Journal of Philosophy 44:113–28.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  9. Goodman, Nelson. 1954. Fact, Fiction, and Forecast. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  10. Goodman, Nelson. 1957. “Parry on Counterfactuals.” Journal of Philosophy 54:442–45.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  11. Goodman, Nelson. 1983. Fact, Fiction, and Forecast. Fourth edition. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  12. Hansson, Sven Ove. 1995. “The Emperor’s New Clothes: Some Recurring Problems in the Formal Analysis of Counterfactuals.” In Conditionals: From Philosophy to Computer Science, edited by G. Crocco, L. Farinas del Cerro, and A. Herzig, 13–31. Oxford, NY, Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  13. Lewis, David. 1973. Counterfactuals. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  14. Lewis, David. 1981. “Ordering Semantics and Premise Semantics for Counterfactuals.” Journal of Philosophical Logic 10:217–34.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  15. Loewer, Barry. 1979. “Cotenability and Counterfactual Logics.” Journal of Philosophical Logic 8:99–115.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  16. Mårtensson, Johan. 1999. Subjunctive Conditionals and Time: A Defense of a Weak Classical Approach. Accessed April 15, 2005. http://www.phil.gu.se/johan/johan.html

  17. Nute, Donald and Charles B. Cross. 2002. “Conditional Logic.” In Handbook of Philosophical Logic 2nd edition Volume 4, edited by D.M. Gabbay and F. Guenthner, 1–98. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  18. Parry, W.T. 1957. “Reexamination of the Problem of Counterfactual Conditionals.” Journal of Philosophy 54:85–94.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  19. Pollock, John L. 1976. Subjunctive Reasoning. Dordrecht: D. Reidel Publishing Company.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  20. Quine, W.V.O. 1981. Mathematical Logic. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  21. Stalnaker, Robert. 1968. “A Theory of Conditionals.” In Studies in Logical Theory, American Philosophical Quarterly Monograph Series, No. 2, edited by Nisholas Rescher, 98–112. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  22. Stalnaker, Robert. 1981. “A Defense of Conditional Excluded Middle.” In Ifs, edited by W. Harper, R. Stalnaker, and G. Pearce, 87–104. Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Google Scholar 

  23. Stalnaker, Robert, and Richmond Thomason. 1970. A Semantic Analysis of Conditional Logic.” Theoria 36:23–42.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  24. Turner, Raymond. 1981. “Counterfactuals Without Possible Worlds.” Journal of Philosophical Logic 10:453–93.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

Acknowledgments I would like to thank Miloš Arsenijević, Bernie Linsky, Adam Morton, Jelena Ostojić, and Jeff Pelletier for helpful discussions, and an anonymous referee for pointing to some mistakes.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Vladan Djordjević .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2012 Springer Science+Business Media B.V.

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Djordjević, V. (2012). Goodman’s Only World. In: Trobok, M., Miščević, N., Žarnić, B. (eds) Between Logic and Reality. Logic, Epistemology, and the Unity of Science, vol 25. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-007-2390-0_15

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics