Skip to main content

Part of the book series: Law and Philosophy Library ((LAPS,volume 107))

Abstract

This paper aims to show what makes coherentism as an epistemological position attractive in comparison to its main competitor, foundationalism. It also aims to show that, from a general epistemological point of view, constraint satisfaction is not the most attractive way to give content to the notion of coherence. In order to achieve these purposes, the paper distinguishes between epistemic, constructive and integrated coherentism. Epistemic coherentism treats coherence as a test for knowledge about a world which exists independently (ontological realism). Constructive coherentism uses coherence as a standard to determine what the facts are in a particular domain. This is a form of ontological idealism.

Usually, both epistemic and constructive coherentism apply the coherence test to only part of the positions (beliefs etc.) which a person accepts. The definition of, and standards for coherence, just as usually logic and standards for belief revision, are kept outside the process of making a position set coherent. Integrated coherentism differs by including everything in the coherence creating process. A set of positions is integratedly coherent if and only if it satisfies the standards included in the set of positions itself.

The paper argues that integrated coherentism best fits with the ideas underlying coherentism and that, as a general epistemological theory, it is incompatible with coherence as constraint satisfaction in a strict sense.

Jaap Hage thanks Michal Araszkiewicz, Gustavo Arosenema, Bartosz Brozek, Jaakko Husa and the (other) participants of the discussion meeting in Kraków on this paper for useful comments on a draft version. The responsibility for errors remains complete his own, or course.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Arguably, this version of foundationalism is a form of empirical foundationalism. Other forms of epistemic foundationalism are also possible, as Araszkiewicz pointed out to me.

  2. 2.

    This example derives from Sosa (1991a).

  3. 3.

    I adapted this characterisation of realism from Devitt (1991, 13–17). The adaptation consist in replacing the epistemic notions ‘belief’ and ‘think’ by the more comprehensive internalist notion ‘propositional attitude’. The reason for this move lies in the step which I will argue in Sect. 1.5.1, namely the replacement of ‘belief’ by ‘position’.

  4. 4.

    It is also possible to combine the positions, and to be satisfied that there is no connection between a belief being justified as true, and the actual truth of the belief.

  5. 5.

    The beginning of an argument can be found in Hage (2005, 35–43).

  6. 6.

    The term ‘quasi-realism’ has already been taken by Blackburn. See Blackburn (1984, 180).

  7. 7.

    See also the contribution of Bermejo to the present volume.

  8. 8.

    Cf. . Downloaded on December 27, 2011.

  9. 9.

    This example illustrates that the step from being more coherent to being more justified is not an obvious one, at least not in Dancy’s eyes.

  10. 10.

    A splendid example of such coherentist foundationalism is Susan Haack’s ‘foundherentism’ (Haack 2009).

  11. 11.

    Legal decisions (e.g. convict the suspect) can both be seen as behaviour, in which case it is not amenable to acceptance and as a judgement about what should be done (the suspect should be convicted), in which case it is a potential position.

  12. 12.

    An interesting line of thinking would be to explore what the implications are if one adopts that position sets can also be held by social groups, or for instance by ‘physical science’ or ‘legal doctrine’. I owe this suggestion to Gustavo Arosenema. Popper’s work on ‘world 3’ (Popper 1972, Chaps. 3 and 4) goes in the same direction.

  13. 13.

    A possible explanation of this use of the term ‘justified’ is reluctance against the use of ‘true’ for sentences for the topic of which one uses a constructivist approach. Truth would then be confined to domains for which one adopts realism, and ‘justified’ for constructivist domains. This usage has the disadvantage that it gives the word ‘justified’ a double role. Namely to stand for a person being justified in doing something, and as a counterpart for ‘true’.

  14. 14.

    This should be read as ‘irrelevant from an argumentation-technical point of view’. The only thing that is really relevant for the truth of a conclusion is whether this conclusion corresponds with the facts. But that has nothing to do with the argument from which the conclusion follows.

  15. 15.

    This may be interpreted as a reason why justification on the deductive account of it is global too. But then the global nature does not lie in the deductively valid argument itself, but in the justification of the premises.

  16. 16.

    In fact, it is even more complicated, because apart from reasons against a position, there may be reasons why the reasons for adoption are in general not reasons after all, or are excluded in this special case. More details on the ‘logic of reasons’ in Hage (1997, Chap. 4), and in Hage (2005, Chap. 3).

  17. 17.

    Notice that the contents of a position set determine what should be added, removed or changed. The position set itself does not lead to the required modifications. Moreover, the definition of integrated coherence does not state anything about the way an integratedly coherent set should be arrived at. It only provides a test on a position set to determine whether it is coherent.

  18. 18.

    This may even be so by definition, if easy cases are defined as those cases which lead to agreement amongst those who argue by the rules of law. This position was argued in Hage et al. (1994). Presently I am less convinced of this position than I was then.

  19. 19.

    This comes near to Pierce’s circumscription of truth: ‘Truth, what can this possibly mean except it be that there is one destined upshot to enquiry with reference to the question in hand.’ Quotation taken from Kirkham (1992, 81).

  20. 20.

    An integratedly coherent position set should contain everything which should be accepted in the light of what else is accepted. Probably this involves the logical closure of the position set, and logical closure under deduction means infinitely large.

  21. 21.

    As this volume illustrates, Amaya’s work does not exhaust the constraints satisfaction approach to legal reasoning. Earlier examples are Joseph and Prakken (2009) and Araszkiewicz (2010).

  22. 22.

    My views on legal method are exposed more extensively in Hage (2011).

References

  • Albert, H. 1980. Traktat über kritische Vernunft, 4th improved edition. Tübingen: Mohr.

    Google Scholar 

  • Alexy, R. 1978. Theorie der juristischen Argumentation. Die Theorie des rationalen Diskurses als Theorie der juristischen Begründung. Frankfurt: Suhrkamp.

    Google Scholar 

  • Amaya, A. 2007. Formal models of coherence and legal epistemology. Artificial Intelligence and Law 15: 429–447.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Amaya, A. 2011. Legal justification by optimal coherence. Ratio Juris 24: 304–329.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Araszkiewicz, M. 2010. Balancing of legal principles and constraint satisfaction. In Legal knowledge and information systems, ed. R.G.F. Winkels, 7–15. Amsterdam: IOS Press. Proceedings of the Jurix 2010 conference.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bentham, J. 1982. An introduction to the principles of morals and legislation, eds. J.H. Burns and H.L.A. Hart. London: Methuen.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blackburn, S. 1984. Spreading the Word. Groundings in the philosophy of language. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bonjour, L. 1985. The structure of empirical knowledge. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chisholm, R.M. 1989. Theory of knowledge, 3rd ed. Englewood Cliffs: Prentice Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dancy, J. 2004. Ethics without principles. Clarendon Press: Oxford.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Daniels, N. 2011. Reflective equilibrium. In The stanford encyclopedia of philosophy, ed. Edward N. Zalta, (Spring 2011 Edition), http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2011/entries/reflective-equilibrium.

  • Devitt, M. 1991. Realism and truth, 2nd ed. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin, R. 1978. Taking rights seriously. Duckworth: London.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin, R. 1986. Law’s empire. London: Fontana.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ginsberg, M.L. (ed.). 1987. Readings in nonmonotonic reasoning. Los Altos: Morgan Kaufman.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goodman, N. 1979. Fact, fiction and forecast, 3rd ed. Hassocks: The Harvester Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haack, S. 2009. Evidence and inquiry, second expanded editionth ed. Amherst: Prometheus Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hage, J.C. 1997. Reasoning with rules. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hage, J.C. 2005. Studies in legal logic. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hage, J.C. 2011. The method of a truly normative legal science. In Methodologies of legal research, ed. M. Van Hoecke, 19–44. Oxford: Hart Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hage, J.C. 2012a. Legal reasoning and the construction of law. i-Lex 7 (2012), 81–105. (http://www.i-lex.it/articles/volume7/issue16/hage.pdf).

  • Hage, J.C. 2012b. Construction or reconstruction? On the function of argumentation in the law, to appear. In Legal argumentation theory: Cross-disciplinary perspectives, eds. Ch. Dahlman and E. Feteris. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hage, J.C., R.E. Leenes, and A. Lodder. 1994. Hard cases: A procedural approach. Artificial Intelligence and Law 2: 113–167.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hart, H.L.A. 1994. The concept of law, 2nd ed. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hauser, M.D. 2008. Moral minds: How nature designed our universal sense of right and wrong. London: Abacus.

    Google Scholar 

  • Joseph, S. and H. Prakken. 2009. Coherence-driven argumentation to norm consensus. Proceedings of the 12th international conference on artificial intelligence and law, 58–77. New York: ACM.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant, I. 1906. Grundlegung zur Metaphysik der Sitten. Hamburg: Felix Meiner Verlag. First edition 1785. The references use the page numbers of the Akademie Ausgabe.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kirkham, R.L. 1992. Theories of truth. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kvanvig, J. 2011. Coherentist theories of epistemic justification. In The stanford encyclopedia of philosophy, ed. Edward N. Zalta, (Summer 2011 Edition), http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2011/entries/justep-coherence.

  • Lehrer, K. 1992. Coherentism, lemma. In A companion to epistemology, eds. Jonathan Dancy and Ernest Sosa, 67–70. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lehrer, K. 2000. Theory of knowledge, 2nd ed. Boulder: Westview Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • MacCormick, N. 1978. Legal reasoning and legal theory. Oxford: University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • MacCormick, N. 2005. Rhetoric and the rule of law. Oxford: University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Peczenik, A. 2008. On law and reason, 2nd ed. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Peczenik, A., and J. Hage. 2004. Legal knowledge about what? Ratio Juris 13: 326–345.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pollock, J.L., and J. Cruz. 1999. Contemporary theories of knowledge, 2nd ed. Lanham: Rowman and Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • Popper, K.R. 1972. Objective knowledge. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. 1981. Reason, truth and history. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W.V. 1986. Philosophy of logic, 2nd ed. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, J. 1951. Outline of a decision procedure for ethics. Philosophical Review 64: 177–197. Also in J. Rawls, Collected Papers, edited by Samuel Freeman, Cambridge: Harvard University Press 1999, 1–19.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, J. 1972. A theory of justice. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Raz, J. 1992. The relevance of coherence. Boston University Law Review 72: 273–321. Also in Joseph Raz, Ethics in the Public Domain, revised edition, Oxford: Clarendon Press 1995, 277–325.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rescher, N. 1973. The coherence theory of truth. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sartor, G. 2005. Legal reasoning, a cognitive approach to the law. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J. 1979. Expression and meaning. Studies in the theory of speech acts. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sosa, E. 1991a. The raft and the pyramid: Coherence versus foundations in the theory of knowledge. Midwest Studies in Philosophy 5(1980): 3–25. Also in Ernest Sosa, Knowledge in Perspective. Selected Essays in Epistemology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 165–191.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sosa, E. 1991b. Equilibrium in coherence? In Knowledge in perspective. Selected essays in epistemology, ed. Ernest Sosa, 257–269. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Thagard, P. 2000. Coherence in thought and action. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thagard, P., and K. Verbeurgt. 1998. Coherence as constraint satisfaction. Cognitive Science 22: 1–24.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Young, J.O. 2008. The coherence theory of truth. In The stanford encyclopedia of philosophy, ed. Edward N. Zalta, (Fall 2008 Edition), http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2008/entries/truth-coherence.

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Jaap Hage .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2013 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht.

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Hage, J. (2013). Three Kinds of Coherentism. In: Araszkiewicz, M., Å avelka, J. (eds) Coherence: Insights from Philosophy, Jurisprudence and Artificial Intelligence. Law and Philosophy Library, vol 107. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-007-6110-0_1

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics