Skip to main content
Log in

Belief representation in a deductivist type-free doxastic logic

  • General Articles
  • Published:
Minds and Machines Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Konolige's technical notion of belief based on deduction structures is briefly reviewed and its usefulness for the design of artificial agents with limited representational and deductive capacities is pointed out. The design of artificial agents with more sophisticated representational and deductive capacities is then taken into account. Extended representational capacities require in the first place a solution to the intensional context problems. As an alternative to Konolige's modal first-order language, an approach based on type-free property theory is proposed. It considers often neglected issues, such as the need for a more general account of thede dicto-de re distinction, and quasi-indicators. Extended deductive capacities require a subdivision of Konolige's notion of belief into two distinct technical notions,potential anddispositional belief. The former has to do with what an artificial agent could in principle come to actively believe, given enough time and its specific logical competence; the latter with what an agent can be assumed to believe with respect to a specific goal to be fulfilled.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Subscribe and save

Springer+ Basic
$34.99 /Month
  • Get 10 units per month
  • Download Article/Chapter or eBook
  • 1 Unit = 1 Article or 1 Chapter
  • Cancel anytime
Subscribe now

Buy Now

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Explore related subjects

Discover the latest articles, news and stories from top researchers in related subjects.

References

  • Barnden, J. A. (1986), ‘Imputations and Explications: Representational Problems in Treatments of Propositional Attitudes’,Cognitive Science 10, 319–64.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bealer, G. (1982),Quality and Concept, London, England: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Belnap, N. and Gupta, A. (forthcoming),The Revision Theory of Truth.

  • Boden, M. (1980)Jean Piaget, Harmondsworth, England: Penguin Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boër, S. E. and Lycan, W. J. (1986),Knowing who, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Castañeda, H.-N., (1967), ‘Indicators and Quasi-Indicators’,American Philosophical Quarterly 4, 85–100.

    Google Scholar 

  • Castañeda, H.-N. (1974), ‘Thinking and The Structure of the World’,Philosophia 4, 3–40.

    Google Scholar 

  • Castañeda, H.-N. (1975),Thinking and Doing: The Philosophical Foundations of Institutions, Dordrecht, The Netherlands: Reidel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Castañeda, H.-N. (1977a), ‘Ontology and Grammar: I. Russell's Paradox and the General Theory of Properties in Natural Language’,Theoria 42, 44–92.

    Google Scholar 

  • Castañeda, H.-N. (1977b), ‘Perception, Belief, and The Structure of Physical Objects and Consciousness’,Syntheses 35, 285–351.

    Google Scholar 

  • Castañeda, H.-N., (1979), ‘On the Philosophical Foundations of the Theory of Communications’, in French et al. (1979), pp. 125–46.

  • Castañeda, H.-N., (1980a),On Philosophical Method., Bloomington, IN: No201-1s Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Castañeda, H.-N. (1980b), ‘Reference, Reality and Perceptual Fields’,Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association 53, 763–823.

    Google Scholar 

  • Castañeda, H.-N. (1980c), ‘The Theory of Questions, Epistemic, Powers, and the Indexical Theory of Knowledge’, in French P. A., Uehling, T. E. Jr., and Wettstein, H. W. (eds.),Midwest Studies in Philosophy 5, 193–237.

    Google Scholar 

  • Castañeda, H.-N., (1985/86), ‘Objects, Existence, and Reference’,Grazer Philosophische Studien 25/26, 3–59.

    Google Scholar 

  • Castañeda, H.-N., (1990), ‘The Semantics and Causal Roles of Proper Names in Our Thinking of Particulars: The Restricted-Variable/Retrieval View of Proper Names’, in K. Jacobi and H. Pape (eds.),Thinking and the Structure of the World, Berlin: de Gruyter, 11–56.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chierchia, G. and Turner R. (1988), ‘Semantics and Property Theory’,Linguistics and Philosophy 11, 261–302.

    Google Scholar 

  • Church, A. (1951), ‘A Formulation of the Logic of Sense and Denotation’, in P. Heule et al. (eds.)Structure, Method and Meaning: Essays in Honor of H. M. Scheffer, New York, NY: The Liberal Art Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. (1989),Microcognition, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cocchiarella, N. (1982), ‘Meinong Reconstructed Versus Early Russell Reconstructed’,Journal of Philosophical Logic 11, 183–214.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cocchiarella, N. (1986), ‘Frege, Russell, and Logicism: a Logical Reconstruction’, in L. Haaparanta and J. Hintikka (eds.),Frege Synthesized, Dordrecht, The Netherlands: Reidel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cocchiarella, N. (1989) ‘Conceptualism, Realism, and Intensional Logic’,Topoi 8, 15–34.

    Google Scholar 

  • Creswell, H. (1985),Structured Meanings: The Semantics of Propositional Attitudes, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frege, G. (1980), ‘On Sense and Meaning’, in P. Geach and M. Black (eds.),Translations from the Philosophical Writings of Gottlob Frege, Totowa: Rowman & Littlefield, (3rd ed.). Originally published in 1892.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fagin, R. and Halpern J. Y. (1988), ‘Belief, Awareness, and Limited Reasoning’,Artificial Intelligence 34, 39–76.

    Google Scholar 

  • French P. A., Uehling, T. E. Jr., and Wettstein, H. W. (1979) (eds.)Contemporary Perspectives in the Philosophy of Language, Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Geach, P. T. (1967), ‘Intentional Identity’,The Journal of Philosophy 20, 627–632.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gupta, A. (1987), ‘The Meaning of Truth’, in E. Lepore (ed.),New Directions in Semantics, London, England: Academic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haas, A. R. (1990), ‘Sentential Semantics for Propositional Attitudes’,Computational Linguistics 16, pp. 213–233.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hadley, R. F. (1991a), ‘The Many Uses of ‘Belief’ in AI’,Minds and Machine 1, pp. 55–73.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hadley, R. F. (1991b), ‘A Sense-Based, Process Model of Belief’,Minds and Machines 1, pp. 279–320.

    Google Scholar 

  • Herzberger, H. (1982), ‘Notes on naive semantics’,Journal of Philosophical Logic 11, pp. 61–102.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hewitt, C. (1972),Description and Theoretical Analysis (using Schemata) of PLANNER: A language for Proving Theorems and Manipulating Models in a Robot. Ph.D. thesis, MIT, Cambridge, MA.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hintikka, J. (1962),Knowledge and Belief, Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hobbs, J. R. (1985), ‘Ontological Promiscuity’,Proceedings of the twenty-third Annual Meeting of the Association for Computational Linguistics, 61–69.

  • Konolige, K. (1986),A Deduction Model of Belief, London, England: Pitman.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kripke, S. (1963), ‘Semantical Considerations on Modal Logic’,Acta Philosophica Fennica 16, 83–94.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kripke, S. (1980),Naming and Necessity, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jubien, M. (1988), ‘Problems with Possible Worlds’, in D. F. Austin (ed.),Philosophical Analysis, Dordrecht, The Netherlands: Kluwer, 299–322.

    Google Scholar 

  • Landini, G. (1990) ‘How to Russell another Meinongian: A Russellian Theory of Fictional Objects Versus Zalta's Theory of Abstract Objects’,Grazer Philosophische Studien 37, 93–122.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levesque, H. (1984), ‘A Logic of Implicit and Explicit Belief’,Proceedings of the Fourth Conference of the American Association for Artificial Intelligence, Austin, TX, pp. 198–202.

  • Lewis, D. (1970), ‘General Semantics’,Synthese 22, 18–67.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lycan, W. G. (1979), ‘The Troubles with Possible Worlds’, in J. Loux (ed.),The Possible and the Actual, Ithaca: Cornell University Press, pp. 274–316.

    Google Scholar 

  • Meinong, A. (1960). ‘The Theory of Objects’, in R. Chisolm (ed.)Realism and The Background of Phenomenology, Atascadero, CA: Ridgeview 1960. Originally published in 1904.

    Google Scholar 

  • Menzel, C. (1986), ‘A Complete Type-Free ‘Second-Order’ Logic and its Philosophical Foundations’, Technical report #CSLI-86-40, Center for the Study of Language and Information, Stanford University.

  • Montague, R. (1974),Formal Philosophy (R. Thomason, ed.), New Haven CN: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Montague, R. (1974a), ‘Universal Grammar’, in Montague (1974), pp. 222–46.

  • Montague, R. (1974b), ‘The Proper Treatment of Quantification in Ordinary English’, in Montague (1974), 246–70.

  • Montague, R., (1974c), ‘Syntactical Treatments of Modality, with corollaries on Reflection Principle and Finite Axiomatizability’, in Montague (1974), 286–302.

  • Orilia, F. (1986),Natural Language Semantics and Guise Theory, Ph.D. thesis, Indiana University, Bloomington, IN.

  • Orilia, F. (1989), ‘Identity Across frames’,Topoi Supplement 4, pp. 85–97.

    Google Scholar 

  • Orilia, F. (1991a), ‘Guise Theory’, in H. Burkhardt and B. Smith (eds),Handbook of Metaphysics and Ontology, Munich, Germany: Philosophia Verlag, pp. 338–41.

    Google Scholar 

  • Orilia, F. (1991b), ‘Type-Free Property Theory, Exemplification, and Russell's Paradox’,Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 32, 442–47.

    Google Scholar 

  • Parsons, T. (1980),Nonexistent Objects, New Haven, CN: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Partee, B. (1979) ‘Montague Grammar, Mental Representations and Reality’, in French et al., 195–208.

  • Powers, L. H. (1978), ‘Knowledge by Deduction’,The Philosophical Review 87, 337–71.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rapaport, W. (1976)Intentionality and the Structure of Existence, Ph.D. thesis, Indiana University, Bloomington, IN.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rapaport, W. (1986), ‘Logical Foundations for Belief Representation’,Cognitive Science 10, 371–422.

    Google Scholar 

  • Russell, B. (1905), ‘On Denoting’,Mind 14, 479–493.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shapiro S. & Rapaport W. (1987), ‘SNePS considered as a Fully Intesional Propositional Semantic Network’, pp. 262–315 of N. Cercone and G. McCalla (eds.),The Knowledge Frontier — Essays in the Representation of Knowledge, Berlin, Germany: Springer Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Strawson, P. F. (1950), ‘On Referring’,Mind 59, 320–44.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thomason, R. (1980), ‘A Note on Syntactical Treatments of Modality’,Synthese 44, 391–395.

    Google Scholar 

  • Turner, R. (1987), ‘A Theory of Properties’,Journal of Symbolic Logic 52, 455–472.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zalta, E. (1983),Abstract Objects, Dordrecht, The Netherlands: Reidel.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Orilia, F. Belief representation in a deductivist type-free doxastic logic. Mind Mach 4, 163–203 (1994). https://doi.org/10.1007/BF00974144

Download citation

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/BF00974144

Key words