Abstract
Konolige's technical notion of belief based on deduction structures is briefly reviewed and its usefulness for the design of artificial agents with limited representational and deductive capacities is pointed out. The design of artificial agents with more sophisticated representational and deductive capacities is then taken into account. Extended representational capacities require in the first place a solution to the intensional context problems. As an alternative to Konolige's modal first-order language, an approach based on type-free property theory is proposed. It considers often neglected issues, such as the need for a more general account of thede dicto-de re distinction, and quasi-indicators. Extended deductive capacities require a subdivision of Konolige's notion of belief into two distinct technical notions,potential anddispositional belief. The former has to do with what an artificial agent could in principle come to actively believe, given enough time and its specific logical competence; the latter with what an agent can be assumed to believe with respect to a specific goal to be fulfilled.
Similar content being viewed by others
Explore related subjects
Discover the latest articles, news and stories from top researchers in related subjects.References
Barnden, J. A. (1986), ‘Imputations and Explications: Representational Problems in Treatments of Propositional Attitudes’,Cognitive Science 10, 319–64.
Bealer, G. (1982),Quality and Concept, London, England: Oxford University Press.
Belnap, N. and Gupta, A. (forthcoming),The Revision Theory of Truth.
Boden, M. (1980)Jean Piaget, Harmondsworth, England: Penguin Books.
Boër, S. E. and Lycan, W. J. (1986),Knowing who, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Castañeda, H.-N., (1967), ‘Indicators and Quasi-Indicators’,American Philosophical Quarterly 4, 85–100.
Castañeda, H.-N. (1974), ‘Thinking and The Structure of the World’,Philosophia 4, 3–40.
Castañeda, H.-N. (1975),Thinking and Doing: The Philosophical Foundations of Institutions, Dordrecht, The Netherlands: Reidel.
Castañeda, H.-N. (1977a), ‘Ontology and Grammar: I. Russell's Paradox and the General Theory of Properties in Natural Language’,Theoria 42, 44–92.
Castañeda, H.-N. (1977b), ‘Perception, Belief, and The Structure of Physical Objects and Consciousness’,Syntheses 35, 285–351.
Castañeda, H.-N., (1979), ‘On the Philosophical Foundations of the Theory of Communications’, in French et al. (1979), pp. 125–46.
Castañeda, H.-N., (1980a),On Philosophical Method., Bloomington, IN: No201-1s Publications.
Castañeda, H.-N. (1980b), ‘Reference, Reality and Perceptual Fields’,Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association 53, 763–823.
Castañeda, H.-N. (1980c), ‘The Theory of Questions, Epistemic, Powers, and the Indexical Theory of Knowledge’, in French P. A., Uehling, T. E. Jr., and Wettstein, H. W. (eds.),Midwest Studies in Philosophy 5, 193–237.
Castañeda, H.-N., (1985/86), ‘Objects, Existence, and Reference’,Grazer Philosophische Studien 25/26, 3–59.
Castañeda, H.-N., (1990), ‘The Semantics and Causal Roles of Proper Names in Our Thinking of Particulars: The Restricted-Variable/Retrieval View of Proper Names’, in K. Jacobi and H. Pape (eds.),Thinking and the Structure of the World, Berlin: de Gruyter, 11–56.
Chierchia, G. and Turner R. (1988), ‘Semantics and Property Theory’,Linguistics and Philosophy 11, 261–302.
Church, A. (1951), ‘A Formulation of the Logic of Sense and Denotation’, in P. Heule et al. (eds.)Structure, Method and Meaning: Essays in Honor of H. M. Scheffer, New York, NY: The Liberal Art Press.
Clark, A. (1989),Microcognition, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Cocchiarella, N. (1982), ‘Meinong Reconstructed Versus Early Russell Reconstructed’,Journal of Philosophical Logic 11, 183–214.
Cocchiarella, N. (1986), ‘Frege, Russell, and Logicism: a Logical Reconstruction’, in L. Haaparanta and J. Hintikka (eds.),Frege Synthesized, Dordrecht, The Netherlands: Reidel.
Cocchiarella, N. (1989) ‘Conceptualism, Realism, and Intensional Logic’,Topoi 8, 15–34.
Creswell, H. (1985),Structured Meanings: The Semantics of Propositional Attitudes, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Frege, G. (1980), ‘On Sense and Meaning’, in P. Geach and M. Black (eds.),Translations from the Philosophical Writings of Gottlob Frege, Totowa: Rowman & Littlefield, (3rd ed.). Originally published in 1892.
Fagin, R. and Halpern J. Y. (1988), ‘Belief, Awareness, and Limited Reasoning’,Artificial Intelligence 34, 39–76.
French P. A., Uehling, T. E. Jr., and Wettstein, H. W. (1979) (eds.)Contemporary Perspectives in the Philosophy of Language, Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.
Geach, P. T. (1967), ‘Intentional Identity’,The Journal of Philosophy 20, 627–632.
Gupta, A. (1987), ‘The Meaning of Truth’, in E. Lepore (ed.),New Directions in Semantics, London, England: Academic Press.
Haas, A. R. (1990), ‘Sentential Semantics for Propositional Attitudes’,Computational Linguistics 16, pp. 213–233.
Hadley, R. F. (1991a), ‘The Many Uses of ‘Belief’ in AI’,Minds and Machine 1, pp. 55–73.
Hadley, R. F. (1991b), ‘A Sense-Based, Process Model of Belief’,Minds and Machines 1, pp. 279–320.
Herzberger, H. (1982), ‘Notes on naive semantics’,Journal of Philosophical Logic 11, pp. 61–102.
Hewitt, C. (1972),Description and Theoretical Analysis (using Schemata) of PLANNER: A language for Proving Theorems and Manipulating Models in a Robot. Ph.D. thesis, MIT, Cambridge, MA.
Hintikka, J. (1962),Knowledge and Belief, Ithaca: Cornell University Press.
Hobbs, J. R. (1985), ‘Ontological Promiscuity’,Proceedings of the twenty-third Annual Meeting of the Association for Computational Linguistics, 61–69.
Konolige, K. (1986),A Deduction Model of Belief, London, England: Pitman.
Kripke, S. (1963), ‘Semantical Considerations on Modal Logic’,Acta Philosophica Fennica 16, 83–94.
Kripke, S. (1980),Naming and Necessity, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Jubien, M. (1988), ‘Problems with Possible Worlds’, in D. F. Austin (ed.),Philosophical Analysis, Dordrecht, The Netherlands: Kluwer, 299–322.
Landini, G. (1990) ‘How to Russell another Meinongian: A Russellian Theory of Fictional Objects Versus Zalta's Theory of Abstract Objects’,Grazer Philosophische Studien 37, 93–122.
Levesque, H. (1984), ‘A Logic of Implicit and Explicit Belief’,Proceedings of the Fourth Conference of the American Association for Artificial Intelligence, Austin, TX, pp. 198–202.
Lewis, D. (1970), ‘General Semantics’,Synthese 22, 18–67.
Lycan, W. G. (1979), ‘The Troubles with Possible Worlds’, in J. Loux (ed.),The Possible and the Actual, Ithaca: Cornell University Press, pp. 274–316.
Meinong, A. (1960). ‘The Theory of Objects’, in R. Chisolm (ed.)Realism and The Background of Phenomenology, Atascadero, CA: Ridgeview 1960. Originally published in 1904.
Menzel, C. (1986), ‘A Complete Type-Free ‘Second-Order’ Logic and its Philosophical Foundations’, Technical report #CSLI-86-40, Center for the Study of Language and Information, Stanford University.
Montague, R. (1974),Formal Philosophy (R. Thomason, ed.), New Haven CN: Yale University Press.
Montague, R. (1974a), ‘Universal Grammar’, in Montague (1974), pp. 222–46.
Montague, R. (1974b), ‘The Proper Treatment of Quantification in Ordinary English’, in Montague (1974), 246–70.
Montague, R., (1974c), ‘Syntactical Treatments of Modality, with corollaries on Reflection Principle and Finite Axiomatizability’, in Montague (1974), 286–302.
Orilia, F. (1986),Natural Language Semantics and Guise Theory, Ph.D. thesis, Indiana University, Bloomington, IN.
Orilia, F. (1989), ‘Identity Across frames’,Topoi Supplement 4, pp. 85–97.
Orilia, F. (1991a), ‘Guise Theory’, in H. Burkhardt and B. Smith (eds),Handbook of Metaphysics and Ontology, Munich, Germany: Philosophia Verlag, pp. 338–41.
Orilia, F. (1991b), ‘Type-Free Property Theory, Exemplification, and Russell's Paradox’,Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 32, 442–47.
Parsons, T. (1980),Nonexistent Objects, New Haven, CN: Yale University Press.
Partee, B. (1979) ‘Montague Grammar, Mental Representations and Reality’, in French et al., 195–208.
Powers, L. H. (1978), ‘Knowledge by Deduction’,The Philosophical Review 87, 337–71.
Rapaport, W. (1976)Intentionality and the Structure of Existence, Ph.D. thesis, Indiana University, Bloomington, IN.
Rapaport, W. (1986), ‘Logical Foundations for Belief Representation’,Cognitive Science 10, 371–422.
Russell, B. (1905), ‘On Denoting’,Mind 14, 479–493.
Shapiro S. & Rapaport W. (1987), ‘SNePS considered as a Fully Intesional Propositional Semantic Network’, pp. 262–315 of N. Cercone and G. McCalla (eds.),The Knowledge Frontier — Essays in the Representation of Knowledge, Berlin, Germany: Springer Verlag.
Strawson, P. F. (1950), ‘On Referring’,Mind 59, 320–44.
Thomason, R. (1980), ‘A Note on Syntactical Treatments of Modality’,Synthese 44, 391–395.
Turner, R. (1987), ‘A Theory of Properties’,Journal of Symbolic Logic 52, 455–472.
Zalta, E. (1983),Abstract Objects, Dordrecht, The Netherlands: Reidel.
Author information
Authors and Affiliations
Rights and permissions
About this article
Cite this article
Orilia, F. Belief representation in a deductivist type-free doxastic logic. Mind Mach 4, 163–203 (1994). https://doi.org/10.1007/BF00974144
Issue Date:
DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/BF00974144