Skip to main content
Log in

A philosophical view on singularity and strong AI

  • Open Forum
  • Published:
AI & SOCIETY Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

More intellectual modesty, but also conceptual clarity is urgently needed in AI, perhaps more than in many other disciplines. AI research has been coined by hypes and hubris since its early beginnings in the 1950s. For instance, the Nobel laureate Herbert Simon predicted after his participation in the Dartmouth workshop that “machines will be capable, within 20 years, of doing any work that a man can do”. And expectations are in some circles still high to overblown today. This paper addresses the demand for conceptual clarity and introduces precise definitions of “strong AI”, “superintelligence”, the “technological singularity”, and “artificial general intelligence” which ground in the work by the computer scientist Judea Pearl and the psychologist Howard Gardner. These clarifications allow us to embed famous arguments from the philosophy of AI in a more analytic context.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1

Source: Pearl 2018a: 28

Fig. 2

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. From those sympathies, it cannot be inferred that we would embrace Gardner’s “theory” of multiple intelligences, MI, or take it for granted which would be premature given that it has engendered abrasive criticisms due to its apparently little experimental evidence (Waterhouse 2006; Herrnstein & Murray 1994; Traub & Gardner 1999). We do not engage in psychology here, a field where this author is not qualified to contribute to, but in philosophy. And what matters for our philosophical position is that Gardner’s proposal is grounded in a systemic perspective, which is what we embrace (not the complete or exact theory by Gardner). Of course, we invite readers to critically respond to this premise, i.e., our fundamental belief (in systemics).

  2. The overly mechanistic and, thus, inadequate parlance to refer to the complex system “intelligence” aside (cf. Weaver, 1948, who shows that (organized) complexity and mechanics do not go together), the authors not only make one out of two routes to “greater intelligence” about speed (speeding up the hardware), but overall intelligence appears to be reduced to a speedup.

  3. In the very first formulation of Moore’s law in 1965 the doubling was every year. David House, an Intel executive, raised it to 18 months, and ten years later Moore (1975) himself increased it to two years. As to the singularity, Moore (2008) himself says that it will never occur.

  4. For instance, in respect to the controversy on singularity, Sandberg & Bostrom (2008: 15) assume that “brain activity is Turing-computable, or if it is uncomputable, the uncomputable aspects have no functionally relevant effects on actual behaviour”. According to Proudfoot (2012: 375), this assumption is mere speculation. Also Gödel seemed to be against computational functionalism (Wang 1996: 184).

References

  • Andrews K, Beck J (2018) Introduction. In: Andrews K, Beck J (eds) The Routledge handbook of philosophy of animal minds. Routledge, New York City, pp 1–10

    Google Scholar 

  • Baum S (2018) Superintelligence skepticism as a political tool. Information 9:209

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Benacerraf P (1967) God, the devil, and Gödel. The Monist LI 1:9–32

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Berger M (1982) The scientific approach” to intelligence: an overview of its history with special references to mental speed. In: Eysenck HJ (ed) A model for intelligence. Springer, Berlin, pp 13–43

    Google Scholar 

  • Berto F (2011) There’s something about gödel: the complete guide to the incompleteness theorem. Wiley-Blackwell, London

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Boden MA (2015) GOFAI. In: Frankish K, Ramsey WM (eds) The cambridge handbook of artificial intelligence. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 89–107

    Google Scholar 

  • Brentano F (1874/1973) Psychology from an empirical standpoint. In: Rancurello AC, Terrell DB, McAlister LL (eds) Leipzig: Duncker and Humblot. Routledge, London

  • Bringsjord S, Bringsjord A, Bello P (2012) On Schmidhuber’s “new millennium ai and the convergence of history 2012.” In: Eden AH, Moor JH, Søraker JH, Steinhart E (eds) Singularity hypotheses: a scientific and philosophical assessment. Springer, New York, pp 81–82

    Google Scholar 

  • Bringsjord S, Govindarajulu NS (2018) Artificial intelligence. In: Zalta EN (Ed) Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/artificial-intelligence/ (30–08–2020).

  • Brockman J (2015) What do you think about machines that think? Annual question. Edge.org. Available at: https://www.edge.org/annual-question/what-do-you-think-about-machines-that-think (25–11–20).

  • Brown RL (2018) Animal traditions: what they are, and why they matter. In: Andrews K, Beck J (eds) The routledge handbook of philosophy of animal minds. Routledge, New York City, pp 362–371

    Google Scholar 

  • Cantwell Smith B (2019) The promise of artificial intelligence. MIT Press, London

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers DJ (1995) Minds, machines, and mathematics: a review of shadows of the mind by Roger Penrose. J Psyche II:11–20

    Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers DJ (1996) The conscious mind. Search of a fundamental theory. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers DJ (2010) The singularity: a philosophical analysis. J Conscious Stud 17:7–65

    Google Scholar 

  • Cole D (2020) The Chinese room argument. In: Zalta EN (Ed) Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. URL https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/chinese-room/ (25–02–2021).

  • Crosby M (2020) Building thinking machines by solving animal cognition. Mind Mach 30:589–615

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Darwin C (1871) The descent of man and selection in relation to sex, 2nd edn. D. Appleton, New York City

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Davidson JE, Downing CL (2000) Contemporary models of intelligence. In: Sternberg RJ (ed) Handbook of intelligence. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 34–49

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Dehn N, Schank R (1982) Artificial and human intelligence. In: Sternberg RJ (ed) Handbook of human intelligence. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 225–307

    Google Scholar 

  • Dretske F (1988) Explaining behavior. Reasons in a World of causes. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Eden AH, Steinhart E, Pearce D, Moor JH (2012) Singularity hypotheses: an overview. Introduction. In: Eden AH, Moor JH, Søraker JH, Steinhart E (eds) Singularity hypotheses: a scientific and philosophical assessment. Springer, New York, pp 1–12

    Chapter  MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Elster J (1999) Alchemies of the mind. Rationality and the emotions. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Flynn M (1997) The concept of intelligence in psychology as a fallacy of misplaced concreteness. Interchange 28:231–244

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Franzén T (2005) Gödel’s theorem: an incomplete guide to its use and abuse. Wellesley, Peters

    Book  MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Gardner H (1983/2011) Frames of mind: the theory of multiple intelligences. Basic Books, New York

  • Garis HD, Halioris S (2009) The artilect debate. why build superhuman machines, and why not? In: Epstein R, Roberts G, Beber G (eds) Parsing the turing test: philosophical and methodological issues in the quest for the thinking computer. Springer, Heidelberg, pp 487–509

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Gödel K (1931) Über formal unentscheidbare Sätze der Principia Mathematica und verwandter Systeme I. Monatshefte Für Mathematik Und Physik 38:173–198

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Gödel K (1951/1995) Some basic theorems on the foundations of mathematics and their implications. In: S. Feferman et al (eds) Reprinted in collected works, Vol III: unpublished essays and lectures. Oxford University Press, New York, 304–323

  • Godfrey-Smith P (2018) Other minds: the octopus and the evolution of intelligent life. WilliamCollins, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Good IJ (1965) The Mystery of Go. In: The New Scientist, 172ff.

  • Haugeland J (1997) What is mind design? In: Haugeland J (ed) Mind design II: philosophy, psychology, and artificial intelligence. Bradford Books, Cambridge, pp 1–28

    Google Scholar 

  • Herrnstein R, Murray C (1994) The Bell curve. Free Press, New York City

    Google Scholar 

  • Hiraiwa-Hasegawa M (2019) Evolution of intelligence on the earth. In: Yamagishi A, Kakegawa T, Usui T (eds) Astrobiology. Springer, Singapore, pp 167–176

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Hobbes T (1651/1885) Leviathan. Routledge, London

  • Hodos W (1988) Comparative neuroanatomy and the evolution of intelligence. In: Jerison HJ, Jerison I (eds) Intelligence and evolutionary biology. Springer, New York City

    Google Scholar 

  • Hofstadter DR (1979) Gödel, escher, bach: an eternal golden braid. Basic Books, New York City

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Horgan J (2008) The consciousness conundrum. IEEE Spectr 45:36–41

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jones EE, Pittman TS (1982) Toward a general theory of strategic self-presentation. In: Suls J (ed) Psychological perspectives on the self. Erlbaum, Hillsdale, pp 231–262

    Google Scholar 

  • Kihlstrom JF, Cantor N (2000) Social intelligence. In: Sternberg RJ (ed) Handbook of intelligence. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 359–379

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Kistler M (2016) L’Esprit matériel : réduction et émergence. Ithaque, Paris

    Google Scholar 

  • Knight LN, Hargis CH (1977) Math language ability: its relationship to reading in math. Lang Arts 54:423–428

    Google Scholar 

  • Koellner P (2018a) On the question of whether the mind can be mechanized, I: from Gödel to Penrose. J Philos 7:337–360

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Koellner P (2018b) On the question of whether the mind can be mechanized, II: Penrose’s new argument. J Philos 7:453–484

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Krubitzer L (2015) Lessons from evolution. In: Marcus G, Freeman J (eds) The future of the brain. Princeton University Press, Oxford, pp 186–193

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Kurzweil R (2006) The singularity is near: when humans transcend biology. Penguin USA, New York City

    Google Scholar 

  • Kurzweil R (2012) On modis’ “why the singularity cannot happen.” In: Eden AH, Moor JH, Søraker JH, Steinhart E (eds) Singularity hypotheses: a scientific and philosophical assessment. Springer, New York, pp 343–348

    Google Scholar 

  • Levesque HJ (2018) Common sense, the Turing test, and the quest for real AI. MIT Press, Cambridge

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Loosemore R, Goertzel B (2012) Why an intelligence explosion is probable. In: Eden AH, Moor JH, Søraker JH, Steinhart E (eds) Singularity hypotheses: a scientific and philosophical assessment. Springer, New York, pp 83–96

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Lucas JR (1961) Minds, machines, and Gödel. Philosophy 36:112–127

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mack CA (2011) Fifty years of Moore’s law. IEEE Trans Semicond Manuf 24:202–207

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Marcus G (2004) The birth of the mind. How a tiny number of genes creates the complexities of human thought. Basic Books, New York City

    Google Scholar 

  • Marcus G (2018) Deep learning: a critical appraisal. Available at: https://arxiv.org/abs/1801.00631 (25–09–2020)

  • Marcus G (2020) The next decade in AI: four steps towards robust artificial intelligence. arXiv: 2002.06177v3.

  • Millikan RG (1984) Language, thought, and other biological categories: new foundations of realism. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Mindell DA (2015) Our robots, ourselves. Robotics and the myths of autonomy. Viking, New York City

    Google Scholar 

  • Modis T (2012) Why the singularity cannot happen. In: Eden AH, Moor JH, Søraker JH, Steinhart E (eds) Singularity hypotheses: a scientific and philosophical assessment. Springer, New York, pp 311–339

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Moore GE (1975) Progress in digital integrated electronics. Tech Digest IEEE Int Electron Dev Meet 21:11–13

    Google Scholar 

  • Moore GE (2008) Tech luminaries address singularity. IEEE Spectrum. June 2008. Available at: https://spectrum.ieee.org/computing/hardware/tech-luminaries-address-singularity (19–02–21). [interviewed in]

  • Moravec H (1988) Mind children. The future of robot and human intelligence. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Moravec H (1998) When will computer hardware match the human brain? J Evolut Technol 1:1–12

    Google Scholar 

  • Moravec H (1999) Robot: mere machine to transcendant mind. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Muehlhauser L, Salamon A (2012). In: Eden AH, Moor JH, Søraker JH, Steinhart E (eds) Singularity hypotheses: a scientific and philosophical assessment. Springer, New York, pp 15–40

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Nagel E, Newman JR (2001) Gödel’s proof. With a new foreword by Douglas R. Hofstadter. New York University Press, New York City

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  • National Academies of Sciences, Engineering, and Medicine (2019) Quantum computing: progress and prospects. The National Academies Press, Washington, DC

    Google Scholar 

  • Newell A, Simon HA (1963) GPS, a program that simulates human thought. In: Feigenbaum EA, Feldman JA (eds) Computers and thought. McGraw-Hill, New York City, pp 279–293

    Google Scholar 

  • Pearl J (2018a) The book of why. The new science of cause and effect. In: MacKenzie D (ed) Cowritten. Basic Books, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Pearl J (2018b) Theoretical impediments to machine learning. In: with seven sparks from the causal revolution. arXiv: 1801.04016.

  • Penrose R (1989) The emperor’s new mind. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Penrose R (1994) Shadows of the mind. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Penrose R (1996) Beyond the doubting of a shadow: a reply to commentaries on shadows of the mind. Psyche, 2.3. Available at: http://journalpsyche.org/files/0xaa2c.pdf (22–02–21).

  • Plebe A, Perconti P (2012) The slowdown hypothesis. In: Eden AH, Moor JH, Søraker JH, Steinhart E (eds) Singularity hypotheses: a scientific and philosophical assessment. Springer, New York, pp 349–362

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Proudfoot D (2012) Software immortals: science or faith? In: Eden AH, Moor JH, Søraker JH, Steinhart E (eds) Singularity hypotheses: a scientific and philosophical assessment. Springer, New York, pp 367–389

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Raatikainen P (2020) Gödel’s incompleteness theorems. In: Zalta EN (ed) Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. URL: https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/goedel-incompleteness/ (23–02–2021).

  • Rajani S (2011) Artificial intelligence—man or machine. Int J Inf Technol 4:173–176

    Google Scholar 

  • Rescorla M (2020) The computational theory of mind. In: Zalta EN (ed) Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. URL: https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/computational-mind/ (19–02–2021).

  • Robinson WS (2015) Philosophical challenges. In: Frankish K, Ramsey WM (eds) The Cambridge handbook of artificial intelligence. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 64–85

    Google Scholar 

  • Sandberg A, Bostrom N (2008) Whole brain emulation: a roadmap. In: Technical report 2008–3, future for humanity institute. Oxford University. Available at: http://www.fhi.ox.ac.uk/Reports/2008-3.pdf. (19–02–21).

  • Schank RC, Abelson RP (1977) Scripts, plans, goals, and understanding. Erlbaum, Hillsdale

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Schank RC, Towle B (2000) Artificial intelligence. In: Sternberg RJ (ed) Handbook of intelligence. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 341–356

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Schmidhuber J (2012) New millennium AI and the convergence of history: update of 2012. In: Eden AH, Moor JH, Søraker JH, Steinhart E (eds) Singularity hypotheses: a scientific and philosophical assessment. Springer, New York, pp 61–78

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Schulz L, Kushnir T, Gopnik A (2007) Learning from doing. Intervention and causal inference. In: Gopnik A, Schulz L (eds) Causal learning. Psychology, philosophy, and computation. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 67–85

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Searle J (1980) Minds, brains, and programs. Behav Brain Sci 3:417–457

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Searle J (1984) Minds, brains and science. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle J (1999) The Chinese room. In: Wilson RA, Keil F (eds) The MIT encyclopedia of the cognitive sciences. MIT Press, Cambridge, pp 115–116

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle J (2014) What your computer can’t know. New York Review of Books, October 9.

  • Select Committee on Artificial Intelligence (2018) AI in the UK: ready, willing, and able? No. HL 100 2017–19. Available from House of Lords Website at: https://publications.parliament.uk/pa/ld201719/ldselect/ldai/100/100.pdf (19–11–2020).

  • Sloman A (2002) The irrelevance of turing machines to artificial intelligence. In: Scheutz M (ed) Computationalism: new directions. MIT Press, Cambridge, pp 87–127

    Google Scholar 

  • Sternberg RJ (1997) The concept of intelligence and its role in lifelong learning and success. Am Psychol 52:1030–1045

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tegmark M (2018) Life 3.0. Being human in the age of artificial intelligence. Penguin, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Tetlock PE (2005) Expert political judgment: how good is it? How can we know? Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Google Scholar 

  • Tieszen R (2011) After gödel: platonism and rationalism in mathematics and logic. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Toulmin S (1963) Foresight and understanding: an enquiry into the aims of science. Harper Torchbooks, New York City

    Google Scholar 

  • Traub J, Gardner H (1999) A debate on multiple intelligences. The Dana Foundation. Available at: http://www.dana.org/Cerebrum/Default.aspx?id=39332.

  • Turing AM (1950) Computing machinery and intelligence. Mind 59:433–460

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Vernon PA, Wickett JC, Bazana BG, Stelmack RM (2000) The neuropsychology and psychophysiology of human intelligence. In: Sternberg RJ (ed) Handbook of intelligence. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 245–264

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Vinge V (1993) The coming technological singularity: how to survive in the post-human era. Vision 21: Interdiscip Sci Eng Era Cybersp 1: 11–22.

  • Walsh T (2017) It’s alive! Artificial intelligence from the logic piano to killer robots. La Trobe University Press, Melbourne

    Google Scholar 

  • Wang H (1996) A Logical Journey. MIT Press, From Gödel to Philosophy, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Wasserman EA, Zentall TR (2006) Comparative cognition: experimental explorations of animal intelligence. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Waterhouse L (2006) Multiple intelligences, the Mozart effect, and emotional intelligence: a critical review. Educ Psychol 41:207–225

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wechsler D (1958) The measurement and appraisal of adult intelligence. Williams & Wilkins, Baltimore

    Google Scholar 

  • Wells MJ (1966) Learning in the octopus. Symp Soc Exp Biol 20:477–507

    Google Scholar 

  • Winograd T (1990) Thinking machines: can there be? Are we? In: Partridge D, Wilks Y (eds) The foundations of artificial intelligence: a sourcebook. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 167–189

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Christian Hugo Hoffmann.

Ethics declarations

Conflict of interest

None of the authors have any competing interests in the manuscript.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Hoffmann, C.H. A philosophical view on singularity and strong AI. AI & Soc 38, 1697–1714 (2023). https://doi.org/10.1007/s00146-021-01327-5

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s00146-021-01327-5

Keywords

Navigation