Skip to main content
Log in

Models of \({{\textsf{ZFA}}}\) in which every linearly ordered set can be well ordered

  • Published:
Archive for Mathematical Logic Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

We provide a general criterion for Fraenkel–Mostowski models of \({\textsf{ZFA}}\) (i.e. Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory weakened to permit the existence of atoms) which implies “every linearly ordered set can be well ordered” (\({\textsf{LW}}\)), and look at six models for \({\textsf{ZFA}}\) which satisfy this criterion (and thus \({\textsf{LW}}\) is true in these models) and “every Dedekind finite set is finite” (\({\textsf{DF}}={\textsf{F}}\)) is true, and also consider various forms of choice for well-ordered families of well orderable sets in these models. In Model 1, the axiom of multiple choice for countably infinite families of countably infinite sets (\({\textsf{MC}}_{\aleph _{0}}^{\aleph _{0}}\)) is false. It was the open question of whether or not such a model exists (from Howard and Tachtsis “On metrizability and compactness of certain products without the Axiom of Choice”) that provided the motivation for this paper. In Model 2, which is constructed by first choosing an uncountable regular cardinal in the ground model, a strong form of Dependent choice is true, while the axiom of choice for well-ordered families of finite sets (\({\textsf{AC}}^{{\textsf{WO}}}_{{\textsf{fin}}}\)) is false. Also in this model the axiom of multiple choice for well-ordered families of well orderable sets fails. Model 3 is similar to Model 2 except for the status of \({\textsf{AC}}^{{\textsf{WO}}}_{{\textsf{fin}}}\) which is unknown. Models 4 and 5 are variations of Model 3. In Model 4 \({\textsf{AC}}_{\textrm{fin}}^{{\textsf{WO}}}\) is true. The construction of Model 5 begins by choosing a regular successor cardinal in the ground model. Model 6 is the only one in which \(2{\mathfrak {m}} = {\mathfrak {m}}\) for every infinite cardinal number \({\mathfrak {m}}\). We show that the union of a well-ordered family of well orderable sets is well orderable in Model 6 and that the axiom of multiple countable choice is false.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Data Availability

Data sharing not applicable to this article as no datasets were generated or analysed during the current study.

Notes

  1. Notice that \({\mathscr {V}}\models {\textsf{MC}}_{\aleph _0}^{\aleph _0}\), since \({\mathscr {V}}\models {\textsf{DC}}\) and \({\textsf{DC}}\Rightarrow {\textsf{MC}}_{\aleph _0}^{\aleph _0}\).

  2. The model \({\mathcal {N}}15\) in [5] is actually a variant of a model constructed by Brunner and Howard [1]. In particular, this FM model of [1] is determined by the same set A of atoms, the same normal ideal I (of the countable subsets of A), but by the weak direct product of the \({{\mathscr {G}}}_{\alpha }\)’s instead of the their unrestricted product. In this model, \({\textsf{LW}}\), \({\textsf{DC}}\), and \({\textsf{AC}}^{{\textsf{WO}}}_{{\textsf{fin}}}\) are all true (but \({\textsf{MC}}^{{\textsf{WO}}}_{\aleph _{0}}\) is false), whereas it is unknown whether \({\textsf{AC}}^{{\textsf{WO}}}_{{\textsf{fin}}}\) is valid in \({\mathcal {N}}15\).

References

  1. Brunner, N., Howard, P.: Russell’s alternative to the axiom of choice. Z. Math. Log. Grundlagen Math. 38, 529–534 (1992)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  2. Dixon, J.D., Neumann, P.M., Thomas, S.: Subgroups of small index in infinite symmetric groups. Bull. Lond. Math. Soc. 18, 580–599 (1986)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  3. Halpern, J.D., Howard, P.E.: Cardinals \(m\) such that \(2m=m\). Proc. Am. Math. Soc. 26(3), 487–490 (1970)

    MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  4. Halpern, J.D., Howard, P.E.: The law of infinite cardinal addition is weaker than the axiom of choice. Trans. Am. Math. Soc. 220, 195–204 (1976)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  5. Howard, P., Rubin, J.E.: Consequences of the Axiom of Choice, Mathematical Surveys and Monographs. American Mathematical Society, Providence (1998)

    Book  Google Scholar 

  6. Howard, P., Tachtsis, E.: On metrizability and compactness of certain products without the axiom of choice. Topol. Appl. 290, 107591 (2021)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  7. Jech, T.J.: The Axiom of Choice, Studies in Logic and the Foundations of Mathematics, p. 4561. North-Holland Publishing Co, Amsterdam (1973)

    Google Scholar 

  8. Onofri, L.: Teoria delle sostituzioni che operano su una infinità numerabile dielementi. Ann. Math. Pura Appl. 4(7), 103–130 (1930)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  9. Sageev, G.: An independence result concerning the axiom of choice. Ann. Math. Log. 8, 1–184 (1975)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  10. Tachtsis, E.: Infinite hausdorff spaces may lack cellular families or discrete subsets of cardinality \(\aleph _{0}\). Topol. Appl. 275, 106997 (2020)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

We are most grateful to the anonymous referee for careful reading and valuable suggestions which helped us improve the quality and the exposition of our paper.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Paul Howard.

Ethics declarations

Conflict of interest

The authors declare that they have no conflict of interest.

Additional information

This paper is dedicated to the memory of James Daniel Halpern.

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Appendix

Appendix

The following theorem provides general information about certain types of permutation models, and thus it is interesting in its own right. Furthermore, the theorem shows that Models 1 and 4 (of Sects. 3 and 6) are respectively equal to the models determined (by the same set of atoms and the same normal ideal, and) by weak direct products of groups (see Remark 1 of Subsect. 2.1) rather than unrestricted direct products. Obvious adjustments to this theorem can be made so that to obtain analogous results for Model 5 (of Sect. 7) and for generalizations of Models 1 and 4.

Theorem 11

Assume that the set A of atoms of the ground model M (of \({{\textsf{ZFA}}}+{{\textsf{AC}}}\)) is a union of a disjoint, denumerable family \(\{A_{n}:n\in \omega \}\), where each \(A_{n}\) is denumerable. For each \(n\in \omega \), let \({{\mathscr {G}}}_{n}\) be a group of permutations of \(A_{n}\), and also let G be the weak direct product of the \({{\mathscr {G}}}_{n}\)’s. Let I be the ideal which is generated by all unions \(\bigcup \{A_{n}:n\in E\}\), \(E\in [\omega ]^{<\omega }\). Let \({\mathcal {M}}\) be the permutation model determined by M, G, and I.

Let \({{\mathscr {G}}}\) be the unrestricted direct product of \({{\mathscr {G}}}_{n}\) (\(n\in \omega \)), and also let \({\mathcal {N}}\) be the permutation model determined by M, \({{\mathscr {G}}}\), and I. Then \({\mathcal {N}}={\mathcal {M}}\).

Proof

We prove by \(\in \)-induction that for every \(x\in M\), \(\Phi (x)\) is true, where

$$\begin{aligned} \Phi (x):\ x \in {\mathcal {M}} \Longleftrightarrow x \in {\mathcal {N}}. \end{aligned}$$

Clearly \(\Phi (x)\) is true, if \(x = \emptyset \), or if \(x\in A\). Assume that \(y \in M\) and that for all \(x \in y\), \(\Phi (x)\) is true. We will show that \(\Phi (y)\) is true. Assume that \(y \in {\mathcal {M}}\). Then the following hold:

  1. (1)

    y has a (countable) support \(E\subset A\) relative to the group G (i.e., for every \(\psi \in \textrm{fix}_{G}(E)\), \(\psi (y)=y\));

  2. (2)

    for every \(x \in y\), \(x \in {\mathcal {M}}\) (\({\mathcal {M}}\) is a transitive class);

  3. (3)

    for every \(x \in y\), \(x \in {\mathcal {N}}\) (by (2) and the induction hypothesis).

We assert that E is a support of y relative to the group \({{\mathscr {G}}}\). It suffices to show that for all \(\phi \in \textrm{fix}_{{{\mathscr {G}}}}(E)\) and for all \(x \in y\), \(\phi (x) \in y\) (since then \(\phi (y) =y\) follows from “\(\phi (y) \subseteq y\) and \(\phi ^{-1}(y) \subseteq y\)").

To this end, let \(\phi \in \textrm{fix}_{{{\mathscr {G}}}}(E)\) and let \(x \in y\). By (3), x has a (countable) support \(E'\subset A\) relative to \({{\mathscr {G}}}\). The permutation \(\phi \) may not be in G, but we construct a permutation \(\phi ' \in \textrm{fix}_{G}(E)\) which agrees with \(\phi \) on \(E'\) as follows: For each \(a \in E'\), the set \(\{ \phi ^n(a) : n \in {\mathbb {Z}} \}\) is countable. Therefore, since \(E'\) is countable, so is \(D = \bigcup \{\{ \phi ^n(a) : n \in {\mathbb {Z}} \}:a \in E'\}\). Furthermore, D contains \(E'\) and is closed under \(\phi \).

We define a mapping \(\phi ': A \rightarrow A\) by

$$\begin{aligned} \phi '(a) = {\left\{ \begin{array}{ll} \phi (a), &{} \text{ if }\ a \in D; \\ a, &{} \text{ otherwise. } \end{array}\right. } \end{aligned}$$

Then the following hold:

  1. (4)

    \(\phi '\in G\);

  2. (5)

    \(\phi '\) fixes E pointwise (since \(\phi \) fixes E pointwise); and

  3. (6)

    \(\phi '\) agrees with \(\phi \) on \(E'\).

By (4) and (5), \(\phi ' \in \textrm{fix}_{G}(E)\) so \(\phi '(y) = y\). It follows that \(\phi '(x) \in y\). Now, (6) gives \(\phi '(x) = \phi (x)\), and hence \(\phi (x) \in y\).

Conversely, assume that \(y \in {\mathcal {N}}\) and that y has a support \(E'\) relative to \({{\mathscr {G}}}\). Then \(E'\) is a support of y relative to G since \(G \subset {{\mathscr {G}}}\). By the induction hypothesis, every element of y is in \({\mathcal {M}}\), and so \(y \in {\mathcal {M}}\). \(\square \)

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor (e.g. a society or other partner) holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Howard, P., Tachtsis, E. Models of \({{\textsf{ZFA}}}\) in which every linearly ordered set can be well ordered. Arch. Math. Logic 62, 1131–1157 (2023). https://doi.org/10.1007/s00153-023-00871-9

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s00153-023-00871-9

Keywords

Mathematics Subject Classification

Navigation