Skip to main content
Log in

Limits of price competition: cost asymmetry and imperfect information

  • Original Paper
  • Published:
International Journal of Game Theory Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In a class of asymmetric-cost duopoly price competition games, price-elastic individual demand reveals a threshold of informed buyers below which equilibrium is in monopoly prices. Even if the threshold is met, unless all buyers are informed, monopoly prices are listed and are more likely between less alike sellers. An increase in the efficient seller’s cost weakly reduces its rival’s price (in a first order stochastic dominated sense) without disturbing its profit. Lastly, increasing the number of sellers increases competitive pricing incentives.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Although the model allowing for multiple types of heterogeneity in Holt (1994) considers price elastic buyers, the author imposes unit demand to characterize the case of cost asymmetry because “it is possible to have gaps in the support of the mixed distribution” without unit demand.

  2. This classification of buyers is also used in Wilde and Schwartz (1979); Png and Hirshleifer (1987); Gale (1988); and Dana (1994). Some papers also impose non-informational restrictions of access on buyers (Shilony 1977; Rosenthal 1980) that result in similar conditions—of buyers being captive to one seller.

  3. Notice that inelastic (unit) individual demand (\(q(p)=1, \forall p \le v\)), would lead to \(p_1^m=p_2^m=v\); this is discussed later.

  4. This also shows up in Deneckere and Kovenock (1996) and Holt (1994), although in the former when the higher cost seller’s capacity is too small, the inequality reverses (refer to \(k_2<\theta (k_1)\) in Figure 2 or Theorem 3 in their paper).

  5. That is, the class of games is discontinuous at \(f=1\) because sellers no longer prefer their minimum guaranteed profit to competitive price undercutting in some interval above their cost.

  6. Refer to Appendix 1

  7. De los Santos et al. (2012) using data from web browsing and online purchases, reject the hypothesis that buyers search prices sequentially with knowledge of the distribution of prices. Incidentally, Nermuth et al. (2013) provide an interesting illustration of buyers increasing their levels of non-sequential search.

  8. Various versions of this result are commonly known in the literature, for example in Burdett and Judd (1983) and Holt (1994).

  9. As in Deneckere and Kovenock (1996), profit from a tie is possible, even if the probability of the tie is zero.

  10. Notice that \(f=1\) is equivalent to \(\underline{p}_2 =c_2\), giving \(\frac{(1+f)}{2} \pi _2^m(\underline{p}_2) = \frac{(1-f)}{2} \pi _2^m(p_2^m) = 0\). That is, for \(f=1\), any price larger than its rival’s (or equal to its own cost) earns seller 2 zero profit which is also its minimum guaranteed profit; \(p_2^m\) need not be in \(S_2\) then.

  11. This is because \(\pi _1^m(p_1^m) [\frac{1}{2} + f(\frac{1}{2} - G_2(p_1^m) + \frac{P_2(p_1^m)}{2})]> \pi _1^m(p_1^m) [\frac{1}{2} + f(\frac{1}{2} - \{G_2(\bar{p}) - P_2(\bar{p})\} + \frac{P_2(p_1^m)}{2})] = \pi _1^m(p_1^m) [\frac{1}{2} + f(\frac{1}{2} - G_2(\bar{p}) + P_2(\bar{p}) + \frac{P_2(p_1^m)}{2})] \ge \pi _1^m(p_1^m) [\frac{1}{2} + f(\frac{1}{2} - G_2(\bar{p}) + \frac{P_2(\bar{p})}{2})] > \pi _1^m(\bar{p}) [\frac{1}{2} + f(\frac{1}{2} - G_2(\bar{p}) + \frac{P_2(\bar{p})}{2})].\)

References

  • Allen B, Hellwig M (1986) Bertrand-edgeworth oligopoly in large markets. Rev Econ Stud 53(2):175–204

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Axell B (1977) Search market equilibrium. Scand J Econ 79(1):20–40

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bagwell K, Lee GM (2014) Number of firms and price competition. Research Collection School of Economics, Working Paper, 1–32. https://ink.library.smu.edu.sg/soe_research/1566

  • Bakshi S (2015) Three essays on imperfect information and market pricing. Ph.D. (Economics) Dissertation, University of Texas at Dallas

  • Benabou R, Gertner R (1993) Search with learning from prices: Does increased inflationary uncertainty lead to higher markups. Rev Econ Stud 60(1):69–93

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bester H (1988) Bargaining, search costs, and equilibrium price distributions. Rev Econ Stud 55(2):201–214

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Blume A (2003) Bertrand without fudge. Econ Lett 78(2):167–168

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Burdett K, Judd KL (1983) Equilibrium price dispersion. Econometrica 51(4):955–970

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carlson JA, McAfee RP (1983) Discrete equilibrium price dispersion. J Political Econ 91(3):480–493

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dana JD (1994) Learning in an equilibrium search model. Int Econ Rev 35(3):745–771

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • De los Santos B, Hortacsu A, Wildenbeest MR (2012) Testing models of consumer search using data on web browsing and purchasing behavior. Am Econ Rev 102(6):2955–2980

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Deneckere RJ, Kovenock D (1996) Bertrand-edgeworth duopoly with unit cost asymmetry. Econ Theory 8(1):1–25

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Diamond PA (1971) A model of price adjustment. J Econ Theory 3(1):156–168

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fishman A (1994) Asymmetric price competition with price inertia. RAND J Econ 25(4):608–618

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gale D (1988) Price setting and competition in a simple duopoly model. Q J Econ 103(4):729–739

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gu Y, Wenzel T (2017) Consumer confusion, obfuscation and price regulation. Scott J Political Econ 64(2):169–190

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Holt CA (1994) Oligopoly price competition with incomplete information: Convergence to mixed strategy equilibria. University of Virginia, Working paper/Discussion paper. https://goo.gl/MZjVqm

  • Kreps DM, Scheinkman JA (1983) Quantity precommitment and bertrand competition yield cournot outcomes. Bell J Econ 14(2):326–337

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moorthy S, Winter RA (2006) Price-matching guarantees. RAND J Econ 37(2):449–465

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Narasimhan C (1988) Competitive promotional strategies. J Bus 61(4):427–449

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nermuth M, Pasini G, Weidenholzer S (2013) The informational divide. Games Econ Behav 78(1):21–30

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Osborne MJ, Pitchik C (1986) Price competition in a capacity-constrained duopoly. J Econ Theory 38(2):238–260

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Png I, Hirshleifer D (1987) Price discrimination through offers to match price. J Bus 60(3):365–383

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Reinganum JF (1979) A simple model of equilibrium price dispersion. J Political Econ 87(4):851–858

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rosenthal RW (1980) A model in which an increase in the number of sellers leads to a higher price. Econometrica 48(1):1575–1579

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shelegia S (2012) Asymmetric marginal costs in search models. Econ Lett 116(3):551–553

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shelegia S, Wilson CM (2017) A generalized model of advertised sales. CEPR Discussion Paper 14113. Available at the author’s webpage: https://sites.google.com/site/sandroshelegia/research

  • Shilony Y (1977) Mixed pricing in oligopoly. J Econ Theory 14(1):373–388

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Spulber DF (1995) Bertrand competition when rivas’ costs are unknown. J Ind Econ 43(1):1–11

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stigler GJ (1961) The economics of information. J Political Econ 69(3):213–225

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Varian HR (1980) A model of sales. Am Econ Rev 70(4):651–659

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilde LL, Schwartz A (1979) Equilibrium comparison shopping. Rev Econ Stud 46(3):543–553

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Sneha Bakshi.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

This paper grew from my Ph.D. dissertation, Bakshi (2015), at University of Texas at Dallas. I am grateful to my advisor, Kevin Siqueira, and to Bernhard Ganglmair, for questions and discussions that helped sharpen the exposition of the model. Many thanks also to anonymous reviewers and an associate editor for their comments, suggestions, and questions that have helped improve this paper substantially; and to Gary Bolton, Jason Parker, Kanishka Kacker, participants of the brown bag seminars at University of Texas at Dallas; the Texas Theory Camp, 2013; The Midwest Economic Association Conference, 2014; the 25th Stony Brook International Conference on Game Theory; and the Delhi Economic Theory Workshop, 2019. All remaining errors are mine.

Electronic supplementary material

Below is the link to the electronic supplementary material.

Supplementary material 1 (xlsx 68 KB)

Appendices

Appendix 1: Proof of the Theorem

Proof

(a) Let \(f \le \hat{f}\); therefore, \(\underline{p}_2\in [p_1^m, p_2^m]\). Seller 2 undercuts its rival only if \(p_1>\underline{p}_2\) (by definition); its best response to all lower prices is \(p_2^m\). Seller 1’s best response to \(p_2 \ge \underline{p}_2\) is \(p_1^m\). The unique equilibrium therefore is \((p_1^*=p_1^m, p_2^*=p_2^m)\). \(\square \)

Proof

(b) Let \(f \in (\hat{f}, 1)\).

Step 1: There can be no pure strategy equilibrium.Footnote 8

Proof

\(p_1 \ngtr \underline{p}_2\) in pure strategy equilibrium, by definition 1. But, \(\forall p_1 \le \underline{p}_2\), seller 2’s best response is \(p_2^m\), to which seller 1’s best response is \(p_1^m\) which exceeds \(\underline{p}_2\) because \(f \in (\hat{f}, 1) \Leftrightarrow \underline{p}_2 \in (c_2, p_1^m)\). \(\square \)

Let \(G_1(p)\) and \(G_2(p)\) be the respective (cumulative) probability distribution functions in mixed strategy equilibrium, with supports \(S_1\) and \(S_2\); and let \(P_i(p)\) denote any positive probability on price p by seller i, if p has a point mass of probability.

Step 2: \(\underline{p}_2\) is the lower bound of \(S_i, \; i=\{1,2\}\); and \(\forall p \in S_1 \cap S_2\), the probability of a tie is zero.

Proof

If there is no common lower bound (\(p^l\)), then one seller can profitably increase its lowest price. If \(p^l>\underline{p}_2\), then seller 2 can profitably undercut because \(\underline{p}_2>c_2\) from \(f<1\); and \(p^l<\underline{p}_2\) is (by definition 1) dominated by \(p_2^m\) for seller 2. Therefore, \(p^l=\underline{p}_2\). Moreover, \(\underline{p}_1<\underline{p}_2\) from (2), and therefore from any tie with positive probability in \(S_1 \cap S_2\) seller 1 is better off deviating probabilistically to a marginally lower price. \(\square \)

For all prices in \(S_i\), seller i’s expected profit is as followsFootnote 9:

$$\begin{aligned} \pi _i(p; G_j(p))= & {} [1-G_j(p)]\frac{(1+f)}{2} \pi _i^m(p)+[G_j(p)-P_j(p)] \frac{(1-f)}{2} \pi _i^m(p) + P_j(p)\frac{1}{2} \pi _i^m(p) \nonumber \\&\implies \pi _i(p; G_j(p)) = \pi _i^m(p)\left[ \frac{1}{2} + f\left( \frac{1}{2} - G_j(p) + \frac{P_j(p)}{2}\right) \right] , \; \forall \; p \in S_i . \end{aligned}$$
(7)

Step 3: \(p_2^m \in S_2\), with \(G_2(p_2^m)=1\); \(G_1(p_2^m)=1\); and \(G_1(\underline{p}_2)=P_1(\underline{p}_2)=P_1(p_2^m)=0\).

Proof

From Step 2, \(\underline{p}_2 \in S_1\); and because \(f<1\), seller 2’s best response to \(p_1 = \underline{p}_2\) is \(p_2^m\). Also from Step 2, \(\underline{p}_2 \in S_2\). But from Definition 1, for seller 2 the maximum profit from \(\underline{p}_2\) equals the minimum profit from \(p_2^m\); i.e. \(\frac{(1+f)}{2} \pi _2^m(\underline{p}_2) = \frac{(1-f)}{2} \pi _2^m(p_2^m)>0\), where its positive sign follows from \(f<1\). Therefore, \(p_2^m \in S_2\),Footnote 10 and the expected profits for seller 2 from \(\underline{p}_2\) and \(p_2^m\) should be equal. Using (7) and the above then

$$\begin{aligned} f\left( -G_1(\underline{p}_2)+\frac{P_1(\underline{p}_2)}{2}\right) =0, \end{aligned}$$
(8)

and

$$\begin{aligned} \frac{1}{2}-G_1(p_2^m)+\frac{P_1(p_2^m)}{2} = -\frac{1}{2}. \end{aligned}$$
(9)

From Step 2, we have \(G_1(\underline{p}_2)=P_1(\underline{p}_2)\); but then (8) implies \(G_1(\underline{p}_2)=P_1(\underline{p}_2)=0\). Moreover (9) implies \(1 = G_1(p_2^m) - \frac{P_1(p_2^m)}{2}\). But \(G_1(p_2^m) \le 1\) and \(P_1(p_2^m) \ge 0\) as probability measures; therefore it must be that \(P_1(p_2^m)=0\), and \(G_1(p_2^m)=1\). But this in turn implies that prices \(\{p:p>p_2^m\}\) are dominated by \(p_2^m\) for seller 2; therefore \(G_2(p_2^m)=1\). \(\square \)

Step 4: \(S_1=[\underline{p}_2, \bar{p}] = S_1 \cap S_2\).

Proof

\(\underline{p}_2 \in S_1 \cap S_2\) (from Step 2), and \(P_1(\underline{p}_2)=0\) (from Step 3) together give \(\exists \;p \in (\underline{p}_2,p_2^m) \; s.t. \; [\underline{p}_2, p] \subseteq S_1\). Call the largest such price \(\bar{p}\).

Suppose \(\exists \; p \in [\underline{p}_2, \bar{p}]\), but \(p \notin S_2\) which implies \(P_2(p)=0\).

If \(p<p_1^m\), take the smallest price in \(S_2\) greater than p, which exists because \(G_2(p)<1, \; \forall p<p_2^m\) from Step 3 and because \(p_1^m<p_2^m\); call this \(p'\). Then there exists \(p''\) such that \(p_1^m>p''\); \(p'>p'' > p\); \(p''\notin S_2\); and \(G_2(p)=G_2(p'')\). If, however, \(p>p_1^m\), then take the largest price in \(S_2\) that is smaller than p and call that \(p'\); then there exists \(p''\), such that \(p_1^m<p''\); \(p'<p'' < p\); \(p''\notin S_2\); and \(G_2(p)=G_2(p'')\). In either case, \(p''\) dominates p for seller 1, from (7), contradicting \(p \in S_1\). Thus, if \(p \ne p_1^m\) and \(p \in [\underline{p}_2, \bar{p}]\), then \(p \in S_2\).

And if \(p_1^m \in [\underline{p}_2, \bar{p}]\) but \(p_1^m \notin S_2\), then take the largest price in \(S_2\) that is smaller than \(p_1^m\) and call it \(p'\). Because \(\underline{p}_2<p_1^m\) from \(f>\hat{f}\), continuity of \([\underline{p}_2, \bar{p}]\) implies that \(\exists p''\) such that \(p'<p'' < p_1^m\) and \(p'' \in [\underline{p}_2, \bar{p}]\) but \(p'' \notin S_2\). This contradicts: if \(p \ne p_1^m\) and \(p \in [\underline{p}_2, \bar{p}]\), then \(p \in S_2\). Therefore, \([\underline{p}_2, \bar{p}] \subseteq S_1 \cap S_2\).

Lastly, to establish \([\underline{p}_2, \bar{p}]=S_1\). Suppose not; then \(\exists \; p>\bar{p}\) such that \(p\in S_1\) but \((\bar{p},p) \notin S_1\). There are two possible cases for \(\bar{p}\), and in each a contradiction is established as follows, implying \([\underline{p}_2, \bar{p}]=S_1\).

First consider \(\bar{p} \ge p_1^m\). Because \(p>\bar{p}\) implies \(G_2(p) \ge G_2(\bar{p}) \ge G_2(p_1^m)\); from (7), \(p\in S_1\) only if \(P_2(p)>0\), because otherwise seller 1 could profitably replace p with \(p_1^m\). But if \(P_2(p)>0\), then from (7) seller 1 profits by deviating from p to a marginally lower price, call it \(\hat{p}\), because \(G_2(\hat{p}) \le G_2(p) - P_2(p)\) and \(\pi _1^m(\hat{p}) > \pi _1^m(p)\), contradicting \((\bar{p},p) \notin S_1\).

Consider the other possibility: \(\bar{p}<p_1^m\). Because \((\bar{p},p) \notin S_1\), for any two prices, \(p_a,p_b \in (\bar{p},p)\), we have \(P_1(p_a)=P_1(p_b)=0\), and \(G_1(p_a)=G_1(p_b)=G_1(\bar{p})\). Therefore if \(p_a<p_b\), then from (7), \(\pi _2(p_b; G_1(p_b))>\pi _2(p_a;G_1(p_a))\). From any price in \((\bar{p},p)\) then, seller 2 has a profitable price hike; i.e. \((\bar{p},p) \notin S_2\). But then it must be that \(P_2(\bar{p})>0\), because otherwise from \(\bar{p}<p_1^m\) and (7) seller 1 prefers a price marginally higher than \(\bar{p}\) to \(\bar{p}\) itself, contradicting \((\bar{p},p) \notin S_1\). But \(P_2(\bar{p})>0\) implies \(P_1(\bar{p})=0\), from Step 2; and \(P_1(\bar{p})=0\) and \(G_1(\bar{p})=G_1(p_a), \; \forall p_a \in (\bar{p},p)\) together imply a profitable deviation for seller 2 from \(\bar{p}\) to a marginally higher price in \((\bar{p}, p)\); i.e. \(\bar{p} \notin S_2\), contradicting \([\underline{p}_2, \bar{p}] \subseteq S_1 \cap S_2\) proven above. \(\square \)

Step 5: \(\bar{p}=p_1^m\); and therefore, \((p_1^m, p_2^m) \notin S_2\), and \(P_2(p_2^m)>0\).

Proof

Because \(S_1=[\underline{p}_2,\bar{p}]\) from Step 4, \((\bar{p},p_2^m) \notin S_2\) because these prices are dominated by \(p_2^m\) for seller 2. Also using Step 2, let seller i be the only seller listing \(\bar{p}\) with positive probability in equilibrium; in case neither lists it with positive probability, let seller i be a randomly chosen seller. Therefore, if \(\bar{p}<p_1^m\), then \(G_j(\bar{p})=G_j(p_1^m)\) and \(P_j(\bar{p})=P_j(p_1^m)=0\), which implies using (7) that seller i has a profitable deviation from \(\bar{p}\) to \(p_1^m\).

If, however, \(\bar{p}>p_1^m\), then because \(G_2(\bar{p}) - P_2(\bar{p}) > G_2(p_1^m)\) and \(\pi _1^m(\bar{p}) < \pi _1^m(p_1^m)\), we have \(\pi _1^m(p_1^m) [\frac{1}{2} + f(\frac{1}{2} - G_2(p_1^m) + \frac{P_2(p_1^m)}{2})] > \pi _1^m(\bar{p}) [\frac{1}{2} + f(\frac{1}{2} - G_2(\bar{p}) + \frac{P_2(\bar{p})}{2})]\).Footnote 11 Using (7), therefore \(\pi _1(\bar{p}; G_2(\bar{p})) < \pi _1(p_1^m; G_2(p_1^m))\); which in turn implies \(\bar{p} \notin S_i\), a contradiction to Step 4.

Therefore, \(\bar{p}=p_1^m\). It is straightforward then that \((p_1^m, p_2^m) \notin S_2\) because these prices are dominated by \(p_2^m\); and because from Step 3, we have \(p_2^m \in S_2\), it must be that \(P_2(p_2^m)>0\). \(\square \)

All prices in \(S_2\) must give the same expected profit; therefore from Steps 3, 4, and 5, we have

$$\begin{aligned} \pi _2(p;G_1(p))=\frac{(1-f)}{2} \pi _2^m(p_2^m), \quad \forall p\in S_2. \end{aligned}$$
(10)

Step 6: \(P_i(p)=0, \; \forall p\in [\underline{p}_2, p_1^m), \quad \forall i=1,2\).

Proof

From (7), \([\frac{1}{2}+f(\frac{1}{2}-G_j(p)+\frac{P_j(p)}{2})]\) should be a continuous function of p throughout the support \([\underline{p}_2, p_1^m]\), because \(\pi _i^m(p), \forall i\) is continuous and each price in \(S_i\) gives equal expected profit. Therefore, any atoms in the support must lie on the end points of \([\underline{p}_2, p_1^m]\). From Step 3, we already know that \(P_1(\underline{p}_2)=0\). If \(P_2(\underline{p}_2)>0\), then seller 1 can profitably marginally undercut \(\underline{p}_2\), contradicting Step 2. \(\square \)

Step 7: \(S_1=[\underline{p}_2, p_1^m]\), with \(G_1(p)= {\left\{ \begin{array}{ll} \frac{1+f}{2f}-\frac{(1-f)\pi _2^m(p_2^m)}{2f\pi _2^m(p)}, \forall p \in [\underline{p}_2, p_1^m) \\ 1, \; if \; p=p_1^m \end{array}\right. }\), and \(P_1(p_1^m)=\frac{(1-f)}{f} [\frac{\pi _2^m(p_2^m)-\pi _2^m(p_1^m)}{\pi _2^m(p_1^m)}]\); and \(S_2=[\underline{p}_2,p_1^m] \cup \{p_2^m\}\), with \(G_2(p)= {\left\{ \begin{array}{ll} \frac{(1+f)}{2f}[1- \frac{\pi _1^m(\underline{p}_2)}{\pi _1^m(p)}], \forall p \in [\underline{p}_2, p_1^m] \\ 1, \; if \; p=p_2^m \end{array}\right. }\), and \(P_2(p_2^m)=[\frac{(1+f)\pi _1^m(\underline{p}_2)-(1-f)\pi _1^m(p_1^m)}{2f\pi _1^m(p_1^m)}]\).

Proof

Steps 2, 3, 4, and 5 define \(S_1\) and \(S_2\). Using (7) to expand the left hand side (LHS) of (10), we have:

$$\begin{aligned} \pi _2^m(p)\left[ \frac{1}{2} + f\left( \frac{1}{2} - G_1(p) + \frac{P_1(p)}{2}\right) \right] =\frac{(1-f)}{2} \pi _2^m(p_2^m); \end{aligned}$$
(11)

and substituting \(p=p_1^m\) and \(G_1(p_1^m)=1\) (from Steps 4 and 5), gives \(P_1(p_1^m)=\frac{(1-f)}{f} [\frac{\pi _2^m(p_2^m)-\pi _2^m(p_1^m)}{\pi _2^m(p_1^m)}]>0\).

But then Step 2 implies \(P_2(p_1^m)=0\), in equilibrium. Using Step 6 then, \(P_2(p)=0, \forall p\in S_1\). Therefore, substituting \(p=\underline{p}_2\) in (7), we have for seller 1 for all prices in \(S_1\):

$$\begin{aligned} \pi _1^m(\underline{p}_2)\frac{(1+f)}{2} = \pi _1^m(p)\left[ \frac{1}{2} + f\left( \frac{1}{2} - G_2(p) \right) \right] . \end{aligned}$$
(12)

Therefore, \(G_2(p)=\frac{(1+f)}{2f}[1- \frac{\pi _1^m(\underline{p}_2)}{\pi _1^m(p)}], \forall p \in [\underline{p}_2, p_1^m]\). Substituting \(p=p_1^m\) gives:

$$\begin{aligned} P_2(p_2^m)= 1-G_2(p_1^m) = \frac{(1+f)\pi _1^m(\underline{p}_2)-(1-f)\pi _1^m(p_1^m)}{2f\pi _1^m(p_1^m)} >0. \end{aligned}$$

From Steps 4, 5 and 6, there are no more point masses. And from (11) we have \(G_1(p)=\frac{1+f}{2f}-\frac{(1-f)\pi _2^m(p_2^m)}{2f\pi _2^m(p)}, \forall p \in [\underline{p}_2, p_1^m)\). Expected profits are therefore, \(\pi _1=\frac{(1+f)}{2} \pi _1^m(\underline{p}_2)\), and \(\pi _2=\frac{(1-f)}{2} \pi _2^m(p_2^m)=\frac{(1+f)}{2} \pi _2^m(\underline{p}_2)\), from (7), (12), and (10). \(\square \)

Proof

(c) Let \(f=1\). This is equivalent to \(\underline{p}_2=c_2\). Therefore, seller 2’s best response for any \(p_1>c_2\) is to undercut. This reduces the game to an asymmetric Bertrand game that has mixed strategy equilibria as found by Blume (2003), with seller 1 selling to the entire market alone at \(p_1^*=c_2\), and seller 2 using a mixed strategy on the support \([c_2, c_2+\gamma ]\) with \(P_2(c_2)=0\). \(\square \)

Appendix 2: Proofs for Section 4


Lemma 1.

Proof

(i) \(\frac{\partial P_1(p_1^m)}{\partial c_1} = \frac{(1-f)}{f} [\frac{- \pi _2^m(p_2^m) \pi _2^{m'}(p_1^m) \frac{dp_1^m}{dc_1}}{(\pi _2^m(p_1^m))^2}]<0\). And using (5) and simplifying, \(\frac{\partial P_2(p_2^m)}{\partial c_1} = \frac{-(1+f)q(\underline{p}_2) q(p_1^m) (p_1^m - \underline{p}_2)}{2f \{\pi _1^m(p_1^m)\}^2} <0\).

(ii) Using (5), and simplifying, \(\frac{\partial P_1(p_1^m)}{\partial c_2} = \frac{(1-f) q(p_1^m) q(p_2^m) [p_2^m-p_1^m]}{f[\pi _2^m(p_1^m)]^2} >0\). And \(\frac{\partial P_2(p_2^m)}{\partial c_2}=\frac{(1+f)}{2f \pi _1^m(p_1^m)} \frac{\partial \underline{p}_2}{\partial c_2} \pi _1^{m'}(\underline{p}_2) >0\), using (2) and the fact that equilibria of type (b) result when \(f\in (\hat{f},1)\) which is equivalent to \(\underline{p}_2\in (c_2,p_1^m)\), implying \(\pi _1^{m'}(\underline{p}_2)>0\). \(\square \)


Lemma 2.

Proof

From the theorem, we have \(G_1(p)= \frac{1+f}{2f}-\frac{(1-f)\pi _2^m(p_2^m)}{2f\pi _2^m(p)}\), and \(G_2(p)= \frac{(1+f)}{2f}[1- \frac{\pi _1^m(\underline{p}_2)}{\pi _1^m(p)}]\). Therefore, using (5), \(\frac{\partial G_1(p|c_2)}{\partial c_2}= -\frac{(1-f)}{2f} \frac{q(p)q(p_2^m)(p_2^m-p)}{(\pi _2^m (p))^2}< 0, \; \forall p \in (\underline{p}_2 (c_2^h), p_1^m)\). Secondly, (2) gives \(\underline{p}_2 (c_2^h)>\underline{p}_2 (c_2^l)\), and therefore \(G_1(p|c_2^h) =0 \le G_1(p|c_2^l), \forall p\in [\underline{p}_2 (c_2^l),\underline{p}_2 (c_2^h)]\). Thirdly, \(G_1(p_1^m|c_2^h) = 1 = G_1(p_1^m|c_2^l)\). Together, this proves, in equilibrium, \(p_1 |c_2^h \; \textit{FOSD} \; p_1 |c_2^l\).

Also, \(\frac{\partial G_2(p|c_2)}{\partial c_2} = -\frac{(1+f)}{2f \pi _1^m(p)} \frac{\partial \underline{p}_2}{\partial c_2} \pi _1^{m'}(\underline{p}_2) <0, \; \forall p \in (\underline{p}_2 (c_2^h), p_1^m]\). Also, as above, \(\underline{p}_2 (c_2^h)>\underline{p}_2 (c_2^l)\), and therefore \(G_2(p|c_2^h) =0 \le G_2(p|c_2^l), \forall p\in [\underline{p}_2 (c_2^l),\underline{p}_2 (c_2^h)]\). And lastly, because \(p_2^m(c_2^h)>p_2^m(c_2^l),\) therefore \(G_2(p_2^m(c_2^l)|c_2^h) < 1 =G_2(p_2^m(c_2^l)|c_2^l)\), while \(G_2(p_2^m(c_2^h)|c_2^h)= G_2(p_2^m(c_2^h)|c_2^l) = 1\). Together this proves, in equilibrium, \(p_2 |c_2^h \; \textit{FOSD} \; p_2 |c_2^l\). \(\square \)


Lemma 3.

Proof

Notice that neither \(\underline{p}_2\) nor \(G_1(p |c_1), \forall p\in [\underline{p}_2, p_1^m)\) are functions of \(c_1\); however, \(\frac{\partial p_1^m}{\partial c_1} > 0\). Therefore, \(G_1(p |c_1^l)= G_1(p |c_1^h), \forall p\in [\underline{p}_2, p_1^m(c_1^l))\), but \(\forall p \in [p_1^m(c_1^l), p_1^m(c_1^h)), \; G_1(p |c_1^l) =1 > G_1(p |c_1^h)\); and \(G_1(p_1^m(c_1^h) |c_1^l)= G_1(p_1^m(c_1^h) |c_1^h) = 1\). Therefore, in equilibrium, \(p_1 |c_1^h \; \textit{FOSD} \; p_1 |c_1^l\).

And using (5), we have

$$\begin{aligned} \frac{\partial G_2(p |c_1)}{\partial c_1} = \frac{-(1+f)}{2f} \frac{q(p)q(\underline{p}_2) \{\underline{p}_2-p\}}{\{\pi _1^m(p)\}^2} ={\left\{ \begin{array}{ll} 0, \textit{if} \; p=\underline{p}_2, \\ >0, \; \forall p\in (\underline{p}_2, p_1^m(c_1)] \end{array}\right. }. \end{aligned}$$
(13)

That is, \(G_2(p |c_1^h) \ge G_2(p |c_1^l), \; \forall p\in [\underline{p}_2, p_1^m(c_1^l))\). Also because \(p_1^m(c_1^l)< p_1^m(c_1^h)< p_2^m\), Lemma 1 implies that \(G_2(p_1^m(c_1^h)|c_1^l) = 1-P_2(p_2^m|c_1^l) < G_2(p_1^m(c_1^h)|c_1^h) = 1-P_2(p_2^m|c_1^h)\).

Lastly, \(\forall p \in [p_1^m(c_1^l), p_1^m(c_1^h)), \; G_2(p |c_1^l) = G_2(p_1^m(c_1^l) |c_1^l) = \frac{(1+f)}{2f} [1-\frac{q(\underline{p}_2)(\underline{p}_2 - c_1^l)}{q(p_1^m(c_1^l))(p_1^m(c_1^l) -c_1^l)}]\), and \(G_2(p |c_1^h) = \frac{(1+f)}{2f}[1- \frac{q(\underline{p}_2)(\underline{p}_2-c_1^h)}{q(p)(p-c_1^h)}]\). The condition \( [1-\frac{q(\underline{p}_2)(\underline{p}_2 - c_1^l)}{q(p_1^m(c_1^l))(p_1^m(c_1^l) -c_1^l)}] \le [1- \frac{q(\underline{p}_2)(\underline{p}_2-c_1^h)}{q(p)(p-c_1^h)}],\) can be simplified to \(q(p)(p-c_1^h) \ge \frac{(\underline{p}_2-c_1^h) q(p_1^m(c_1^l))(p_1^m(c_1^l) -c_1^l)}{(\underline{p}_2 - c_1^l)}.\) The LHS increases in p within the given range of prices whereas the RHS doesn’t change; therefore, this condition would be satisfied iff it is satisfied at the lower limit, i.e. at \(p_1^m(c_1^l)\). Therefore, \(G_2(p |c_1^l) \le G_2(p |c_1^h), \; \forall p \in [p_1^m(c_1^l), p_1^m(c_1^h))\) iff

$$\begin{aligned} q(p_1^m(c_1^l))(p_1^m(c_1^l)-c_1^h) \ge \frac{(\underline{p}_2-c_1^h) q(p_1^m(c_1^l))(p_1^m(c_1^l) -c_1^l)}{(\underline{p}_2 - c_1^l)}. \end{aligned}$$

Simplifying and reducing, we get \(\underline{p}_2 \le p_1^m(c_1^l)\). But this is automatically satisfied when equilibrium is of type (b); in other words \(f > \hat{f}(c_1^l)\) gives \(\underline{p}_2 < p_1^m(c_1^l)\). Therefore in equilibrium, \(p_2 |c_1^l \; \textit{FOSD} \; p_2 |c_1^h\). \(\square \)


Proposition 1.

Proof

A higher \(c_2\) raises \(p_2^m\) from (1), raises \(\underline{p}_2\) from (2), and raises \(\hat{f}\) from (6). Let \(c_2\) increase from \(c_2^l\) to \(c_2^h\); from (6) and the theorem, one of the following captures the shifting equilibrium due such a change.

  1. (i)

    \(f \le \hat{f}(c_2^l)<\hat{f}(c_2^h)<1\): equilibrium prices change from \(p_1^m; p_2^m (c_2^l)\) to \(p_1^m; p_2^m (c_2^h)\), and because \(p_2^m (c_2^h)>p_2^m (c_2^l)\), market price at \(c_2^h\) first order stochastically dominates that at \(c_2^l\) making buyers worse off. Expected profit changes only for the inefficient seller, from \(\frac{(1-f)}{2} \pi _2^m(p_2^m(c_2^l))\) to \(\frac{(1-f)}{2} \pi _2^m(p_2^m(c_2^h))\), which is a decrease from (5). Aggregating therefore, market welfare decreases.

  2. (ii)

    \(\hat{f}(c_2^l)<f \le \hat{f}(c_2^h)<1\): seller 1’s equilibrium price increases from a mixed strategy with support \(S_1=[\underline{p}_2 (c_2^l),p_1^m]\) to a pure strategy at price \(p_1^m\), thus improving its expected profit from \(\frac{(1+f)}{2} \pi _1^m(\underline{p}_2 (c_2^l))\) to \(\frac{(1+f)}{2} \pi _1^m(p_1^m)\). Seller 2’s price increases from a mixed strategy with support \(S_2=[\underline{p}_2 (c_2^l),p_1^m] \bigcup \{p_2^m (c_2^l)\}\) to a pure strategy at price \(p_2^m (c_2^h)\), i.e. its expected profit changes from \(\frac{(1-f)}{2} \pi _2^m(p_2^m(c_2^l))\) to \(\frac{(1-f)}{2} \pi _2^m(p_2^m(c_2^h))\), which is a decrease from (5). Market price at \(c_2^h\) first order stochastically dominates that at \(c_2^l\) because both sellers’ prices increase, making buyers worse off.

  3. (iii)

    \(\hat{f}(c_2^l)<\hat{f}(c_2^h)<f<1\): both sellers continue to use mixed strategy pricing, and from lemma 2, equilibrium market price at \(c_2^h\) first order stochastically dominates that at \(c_2^l\) making buyers worse off. Expected profit for seller 1 improves from \(\frac{(1+f)}{2} \pi _1^m(\underline{p}_2 (c_2^l))\) to \(\frac{(1+f)}{2} \pi _1^m(\underline{p}_2 (c_2^h))\); and expected profit for seller 2 decreases from \(\frac{(1-f)}{2} \pi _2^m(p_2^m(c_2^l))\) to \(\frac{(1-f)}{2} \pi _2^m(p_2^m(c_2^h))\) from (5).

  4. (iv)

    \(\hat{f}(c_2^l)<\hat{f}(c_2^h)<f=1\): the only price at which sales occur (\(p_1 = c_2\)) increases from \(c_2^l\) to \(c_2^h\), leading to a first order stochastically dominating market price, lowering buyer surplus and raising seller 1’s profit; while seller 2 remains indifferent earning zero profit.

\(\square \)


Proposition 2.

Proof

A higher \(c_1\) raises \(p_1^m\), but leaves \(\underline{p}_2\) unchanged (from definition 1), and lowers \(\hat{f}\) (from (6)); therefore, its impact on prices is not straightforward. Let \(c_1\) increase from \(c_1^l\) to \(c_1^h\); from (6) and the theorem, one of the following captures the shift in equilibrium.

  1. (i)

    \(f \le \hat{f}(c_1^h)<\hat{f}(c_1^l)<1\): equilibrium prices change from \(p_1^m (c_1^l); p_2^m\) to \(p_1^m (c_1^h); p_2^m\); i.e. \(p_1|c_1^h\) first order stochastically dominates \(p_1|c_1^l\), while \(p_2\) doesn’t change, making buyers worse off. Expected profit changes only for the efficient seller, from \(\frac{(1+f)}{2} \pi _1^m(p_1^m(c_1^l))\) to \(\frac{(1+f)}{2} \pi _1^m(p_1^m(c_1^h))\), which is a decrease from (5). Aggregating therefore, market welfare decreases.

  2. (ii)

    \(\hat{f}(c_1^h)<f \le \hat{f}(c_1^l)<1\): seller 1’s price changes from a pure strategy at \(p_1^m (c_1^l)\) to a mixed strategy with support \(S_1=[\underline{p}_2 ,p_1^m(c_1^h)]\); because \(\hat{f}(c_1^h)<f \le \hat{f}(c_1^l)\) is equivalent to \(p_1^m(c_1^l) \le \underline{p}_2 < p_1^m(c_1^h)\), this implies \(p_1|c_1^h\) first order stochastically dominates \(p_1|c_1^l\). Seller 2’s price decreases from a pure strategy at \(p_2^m\) to a mixed strategy with support \(S_2=[\underline{p}_2 ,p_1^m(c_1^h)] \bigcup \{p_2^m\}\), i.e. \(p_2|c_1^l\) first order stochastically dominates \(p_2|c_1^h\). Seller 2’s expected profit does not change despite the equilibrium moving to mixed strategies and remains at \(\frac{(1-f)}{2} \pi _2^m(p_2^m)\), while that of seller 1 changes from \(\frac{(1+f)}{2} \pi _1^m(p_1^m (c_1^l))\) to \(\frac{(1+f)}{2} \pi _1^m(\underline{p}_2|c_1^h)\). Because \(\hat{f}(c_1^h)<f \) is equivalent to \(\underline{p}_2 < p_1^m(c_1^h)\), we have \(\pi _1^m(\underline{p}_2|c_1^h) < \pi _1^m(p_1^m(c_1^h))\); but from (5) we have \(\pi _1^m(p_1^m(c_1^h)) < \pi _1^m(p_1^m(c_1^l))\). Therefore \(\pi _1^m(\underline{p}_2|c_1^h) < \pi _1^m(p_1^m(c_1^l))\), or that seller 1’s expected profit falls.

  3. (iii)

    \(\hat{f}(c_1^h)<\hat{f}(c_1^l)<f<1\): both sellers continue to use mixed strategies in equilibrium. From lemma 3, \(p_1|c_1^h\) first order stochastically dominates \(p_1|c_1^l\), but \(p_2|c_1^l\) first order stochastically dominates \(p_2|c_1^h\). Expected profit for seller 2 does not change because neither \(c_2\) nor \(p_2^m\) changes, but expected profit for seller 1 falls despite no change in \(\underline{p}_2\), from \(\frac{(1+f)}{2} \pi _1^m(\underline{p}_2|c_1^l)\) to \(\frac{(1+f)}{2} \pi _1^m(\underline{p}_2|c_1^h)\) because its cost has risen.

  4. (iv)

    \(\hat{f}(c_1^h)<\hat{f}(c_1^l)<f=1\): the only price at which sales occur (\(p_1 = c_2\)) does not change and therefore neither does buyer surplus nor the profit of seller 2; however seller 1’s profit falls from \(\pi _1^m(c_2|c_1^l)\) to \(\pi _1^m(c_2|c_1^h)\). Aggregating therefore, market welfare decreases.

\(\square \)

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Bakshi, S. Limits of price competition: cost asymmetry and imperfect information. Int J Game Theory 49, 913–932 (2020). https://doi.org/10.1007/s00182-020-00717-1

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s00182-020-00717-1

Keywords

JEL Classification

Navigation