Skip to main content
Log in

The allocation of marginal surplus for cooperative games with transferable utility

  • Original Paper
  • Published:
International Journal of Game Theory Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Marginal contribution is a significant index to measure every player’s ability to cooperate in cooperative games. Several solutions for cooperative games are defined in terms of marginal contribution, including the Shapley value and the Solidarity value. In this paper, we introduce marginal surplus as an alternative index to describe the contribution level of every player. We define a new solution for cooperative games, namely the average-surplus value, which is determined by an underlying procedure of sharing marginal surplus. Then we characterize the average-surplus value by introducing the A-null surplus player property and the revised balanced contributions property. We also propose the AS-potential function to implement the average-surplus value. Finally, we provide a non-cooperative game, the outcome of which coincides with the average-surplus value in subgame perfect equilibria.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. The condition of superadditivity states that players can collectively achieve a higher worth than in separated coalitions, that is, two coalitions can jointly do at least as good as they do separately. It is a natural assumption conforming to economic regulations since players usually reach a cooperative agreement and form a coalition with the aim of obtaining more benefits. But the remarkable thing is that all of the conclusions in this paper except Sect. 6 are tenable if they are restricted on the class of all TU-games.

  2. A potential function for a strategic form game is a function mapping strategy profiles into real numbers such that, when a player deviates, the change in the player’s payoff equals the change in the potential function. Generally, a cooperation-formation (strategic form) game can be constituted by a TU-game and a given solution of TU-games. Monderer and Shapley (1996) presented a characterization for the Shapley value in terms of a non-cooperative potential function. Similarly, it is also feasible to implement the average-surplus value by the non-cooperative potential approach.

  3. The neutral dummy property: if for all \(i\in N\) such that \(v(S\cup \{i\})=v(S)+v(i)\) for all \(S\subseteq N\backslash \{i\}\), then \(\varphi _i(N,v)=\frac{1}{2}v(i)+\frac{1}{2}(v(i)+\frac{v(N)-\sum _{j\in N}v(j)}{n})\) for all \(\langle N,v \rangle \in {\mathcal {G}}^N\).

References

  • Albizuri MJ, Echarri JM, Zarzuelo JM (2015) A non-cooperative mechanism for the Shapley value of airport problems. Annals of Operations Research 235(1):1–11

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carreras F, Giménez JM (2011) Power and potential maps induced by any semivalue: some algebraic properties and computation by multilinear extensions. Eur J Oper Res 211(1):148–159

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Casajus A, Huettner F (2014) On a class of the Solidarity values. Eur J Oper Res 236(2):583–591

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dragan I (1996) New mathematical properties of the Banzhaf value. Eur J Oper Res 95(2):451–463

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hamiache G (2001) Associated consistency and the Shapley value. Int J Game Theory 30(2):279–289

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hart S, Mas-Colell A (1989) Potential, value, and consistency. Econometrica 57(3):589–614

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Joosten R (1996) Dynamics, equilibria and values. Dissertation, Universiteit Maastricht

  • Ju Y, Wettstein D (2009) Implementing cooperative solution concepts: a generalized bidding approach. Econ Theory 39(2):307–330

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ju Y, Borm P, Ruys P (2007) The consensus value: a new solution concept for cooperative games. Soc Choice Welf 28(4):685–703

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ju Y, Chun Y, van den Brink R (2014) Auctioning and selling positions: a non-cooperative approach to queueing conflicts. J Econ Theory 153:33–45

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kamijoab Y (2012) Whose deletion does not affect your payoff? The difference between the Shapley value, the egalitarian value, the Solidarity value, and the Banzhaf value. Eur J Oper Res 216(3):638–646

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Malawski M (2013) Procedural values for cooperative games. Int J Game Theory 42(1):305–324

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Monderer D, Shapley LS (1996) Potential games. Games Econ Behav 14(1):124–143

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Myerson RB (1980) Conference structures and fair allocation rules. Int J Game Theory 9(3):169–182

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nowak AS, Radzik T (1994) A solidarity value for n-person transferable utility games. Int J Game Theory 23(1):43–48

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pérez-Castrillo D, Wettstein D (2001) Bidding for the surplus: a non-cooperative approach to the Shapley value. J Econ Theory 100(2):274–294

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Qin CZ (1996) Endogenous formation of cooperation structures. J Econ Theory 69:218–226

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shapley LS (1953) A value for n-person games. In: Kuhn HW, Tucker AW (eds) Contributions to the theory of games II. Princeton University Press, pp 307–317

  • van den Brink R (2007) Null or nullifying players: the difference between the Shapley value and equal division solutions. J Econ Theory 136(1):767–775

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • van den Brink R, Funaki Y (2015) Implementation and axiomatization of discounted Shapley values. Soc Choice Welf 45:329–344

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • van den Brink R, Funaki Y, Ju Y (2013) Reconciling marginalism with egalitarianism: consistency, monotonicity, and implementation of egalitarian Shapley values. Soc Choice Welf 40:693–714

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • van den Brink R, Dietz C, van der Laan G, Xu G (2017) Comparable characterizations of four solutions for permission tree games. Econ Theory 63(4):1–21

    Google Scholar 

  • Wang W, Sun H, van den Brink R, Xu G (2019) The family of ideal values for cooperative games. J Optim Theory Appl 180:1065–1086

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Xu G, Driessen TSH, Sun H (2008) Matrix analysis for associated consistency in cooperative game theory. Linear Algebra Appl 428(7):1571–1586

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Xu G, Dai H, Hou D, Sun H (2016) A-potential function and a non-cooperative foundation for the Solidarity value. Oper Res Lett 44(1):86–91

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

The authors would like to thank Réne van den Brink, an associate editor and three reviewers for their suggestions and comments for the improvement of this paper. This work is supported by the National Natural Science Foundation of China (Grant Nos. 72071159, 71871180 and 71671140) and China Scholarship Council (Grant Nos. 202006290157).

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Genjiu Xu.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Appendix

Appendix

Proof of Theorem 3

It is sufficient to prove that \(A{\tilde{P}}\) satisfies efficiency, symmetry, additivity and the A-null surplus player property.

  • Efficiency: By Eq. (5.1) and Eq.(5.6), we have

    $$\begin{aligned} \sum _{i\in N}A_i{\tilde{P}}(N,v)&= \sum _{i\in N}\left[ D_i{\tilde{P}}(N,v)+v(i)+\frac{1}{n}(v(N\backslash i)-\sum _{j\in N\backslash i}v(j))\right] \\&= v(N)-\frac{1}{n}\sum _{i\in N}(v(N\backslash i)+v(i))+\sum _{i\in N}v(i)\\&\qquad +\frac{1}{n}\sum _{i\in N}(v(N\backslash i)-\sum _{j\in N\backslash i}v(j))\\&= v(N). \end{aligned}$$
  • Additivity: It is easy to check that the AS-potential function \({\tilde{P}}\) satisfies additivity by Eq. (5.5) , that is, \({\tilde{P}}(N,v+w)={\tilde{P}}(N,v)+{\tilde{P}}(N,w)\) for all \(\langle N,v\rangle , \langle N,w\rangle \in {\mathcal {G}}^N\). Thus, \(D{\tilde{P}}(N,v)\) and \(A{\tilde{P}}(N,v)\) also satisfy additivity by Eqs. (5.2) and (5.6).

  • Symmetry: Let i and j be symmetric players. Firstly, we prove that \({\tilde{P}}(S\backslash i, v|_{S\backslash i})={\tilde{P}}(S\backslash j, v|_{S\backslash j})\) for all \(S\subseteq N, S\ni i,j\) by induction. It is obvious that \({\tilde{P}}(i, v|_i)=0={\tilde{P}}(j, v|_j)\) for \(S=\{i,j\}\). Suppose that the conclusion holds for \(2\le |S|< n\). Then, for \(|S|=n\), we have

    $$\begin{aligned}&{\tilde{P}}(N\backslash i, v|_{N\backslash i})-{\tilde{P}}(N\backslash j, v|_{N\backslash j}) \\&\quad = \frac{1}{n-1}\left[ \sum _{k\in N\backslash i}{\tilde{P}}(N \backslash \{i,k\}, v|_{N \backslash \{i,k\}})+v(N\backslash i) -\frac{1}{n-1}\sum _{k\in N\backslash i}(v(N \backslash \{i,k\})+v(k))\right] \\&\qquad -\frac{1}{n-1}\left[ \sum _{k\in N\backslash j}{\tilde{P}}(N \backslash \{j,k\}, v|_{N \backslash \{j,k\}})+v(N\backslash j) -\frac{1}{n-1}\sum _{k\in N\backslash j}(v(N \backslash \{j,k\})+v(k))\right] \\&\quad = \frac{1}{n-1}\left[ \sum _{k\in N\backslash i}{\tilde{P}}(N \backslash \{i,k\}, v|_{N \backslash \{i,k\}}) - \sum _{k\in N\backslash j}{\tilde{P}}(N \backslash \{j,k\}, v|_{N \backslash \{j,k\}})\right] \\&\quad = 0. \end{aligned}$$

    Since \(v(N\backslash i)=v(N\backslash j)\) and \(v(i)=v(j)\), then symmetry of \(A{\tilde{P}}\) is verified as follows,

    $$\begin{aligned} A_i{\tilde{P}}(N,v)-A_j{\tilde{P}}(N,v)&= D_i{\tilde{P}}(N,v)+v(i)+\frac{1}{n}(v(N\backslash i)-\sum _{k\in N\backslash i}v(k))\\&\quad -\left[ D_j{\tilde{P}}(N,v)+v(j)+\frac{1}{n}(v(N\backslash j)-\sum _{k\in N\backslash j}v(k))\right] \\&= {\tilde{P}}(N\backslash i, v|_{N\backslash i})-{\tilde{P}}(N\backslash j, v|_{N\backslash j})\\&= 0. \end{aligned}$$
  • The A-null surplus player property: Let i be an A-null surplus player in \(\langle N,v\rangle \), then \(v(S)-\frac{1}{s}\sum _{j\in S}(v(S\backslash j)+v(j))=0\) for all \(S\subseteq N\) and \(S\ni i\). Obviously, i is also an A-null surplus player in all subgames \(\langle S, v|_S\rangle \). Next, we prove that \(A_i{\tilde{P}}(S,v|_S)=v(i)\) for all \(\langle S, v|_S\rangle \) by induction, in particular, \(A_i{\tilde{P}}(N,v)=v(i)\). It is trivial that \(A_i{\tilde{P}}(i,v|_i)=v(i)\) with \(S=\{i\}\). Suppose that \(A_i{\tilde{P}}(S,v|_S)=v(i)\) for all subgames with \(|S|\le n-1\), that is, for all \(j\in N\backslash i\),

    $$\begin{aligned} D_i{\tilde{P}}(N\backslash j,v|_{N\backslash j})+v(i)+\frac{1}{n-1} (v(N\backslash \{i,j\})-\sum _{k\in N\backslash \{i,j\}}v(k))=v(i). \end{aligned}$$

    Thus, by Eq. (5.4), we have

    $$\begin{aligned}&nA_i{\tilde{P}}(N,v)\\&\quad = n{\tilde{P}}(N,v)-n{\tilde{P}}(N\backslash i, v|_{N\backslash i})+nv(i)+ v(N\backslash i)-\sum _{j\in N\backslash i}v(j) \\&\quad = \left[ \sum _{j\in N}{\tilde{P}}(N\backslash j, v|_{N\backslash j}) +v(N)-\frac{1}{n}\sum _{j\in N}(v(N\backslash j)+v(j))\right] \\&\qquad - \left[ \sum _{j\in N\backslash i}{\tilde{P}}(N\backslash \{i,j\}, v|_{N\backslash \{i,j\}}) +v(N\backslash i)-\frac{1}{n-1}\sum _{j\in N\backslash i} (v(N\backslash \{i,j\})+v(j))\right] \\&\qquad -{\tilde{P}}(N\backslash i, v|_{N\backslash i})+nv(i)+ v(N\backslash i)-\sum _{j\in N\backslash i}v(j)\\&\quad = \sum _{j\in N\backslash i}D_i{\tilde{P}}(N\backslash j,v|_{N\backslash j})+ \frac{1}{n-1}\sum _{j\in N\backslash i}v(N\backslash \{i,j\}) +nv(i)-\frac{n-2}{n-1}\sum _{j\in N\backslash i}v(j) \\&\quad = \sum _{j\in N\backslash i}\left[ D_i{\tilde{P}}(N\backslash j,v|_{N\backslash j})+v(i)+\frac{1}{n-1} (v(N\backslash \{i,j\})-\sum _{k\in N\backslash \{i,j\}}v(k))\right] +v(i)\\&\quad = nv(i). \end{aligned}$$

\(\square \)

Proof of Theorem 4

The theorem is proved by induction on the number k of players. Obviously, the result holds for \(k=1\), since \(AS_i(\{i\},v)=v(i)\) for every one-person TU-game \(\langle \{i\},v\rangle \). Suppose that the result holds for all \(k<n\), then we show that it also holds for \(k=n\).

Let \(N=\{1,2,\ldots ,n\}\). We now show that the average-surplus value is indeed a SPE outcome by considering the following strategies.

  • At stage 1, each player, \(i\in N\), makes bids \(b_j^i = AS_j(N,v)- AS_j(N\backslash i,v|_{N\backslash i})-\frac{1}{n}(v(N)-v(N\backslash i)-v(i))\) for every player \(j\in N\backslash i\).

  • At stage 2, The proposer \(\alpha \) makes offers \(x_j^{\alpha }= AS_j(N\backslash \alpha ,v|_{N\backslash \alpha })+\frac{1}{n}(v(N)-v(N\backslash \alpha )-v(\alpha ))\) to every player \(j\in N\backslash \alpha \).

  • At stage 3, each player \(j\in N\backslash \alpha \) will accept the offer if \(x_j^{\alpha }\ge AS_j(N\backslash \alpha ,v|_{N\backslash \alpha })+\frac{1}{n}(v(N)-v(N\backslash \alpha )-v(\alpha ))\), otherwise the offer is rejected.

It is obvious that the outcome of the strategies is the average-surplus value. We will verify that the strategies constitute a SPE. At stage 3, each player \(j\in N\backslash \alpha \) can obtain \(AS_j(N\backslash \alpha ,v|_{N\backslash \alpha })+\frac{1}{n}(v(N)-v(N\backslash \alpha )-v(\alpha ))\) by the induction hypothesis, and the proposer \(\alpha \) just receives \(v(\alpha )-\sum _{j\in N\backslash \alpha } \frac{1}{n}(v(N)-v(N\backslash \alpha )-v(\alpha ))\) in the case of rejection. Thus, the strategies are best responses at stage 3 and stage 2 as long as \(v(N)-v(N\backslash \alpha )\ge v(\alpha ) \) for all superadditive TU-games, since

$$\begin{aligned}&v(N)-\sum _{j\in N\backslash \alpha }\left[ AS_j(N\backslash \alpha ,v|_{N\backslash \alpha }) +\frac{1}{n}(v(N)-v(N\backslash \alpha )-v(\alpha ))\right] \\&\quad \ge v(\alpha )-\sum _{j\in N\backslash \alpha } \frac{1}{n}(v(N)-v(N\backslash \alpha ) -v(\alpha )) \\&\qquad \Leftrightarrow \ \ v(N)-v(N\backslash \alpha )\ge v(\alpha ). \end{aligned}$$

At stage 1, by the revised balanced contributions property, for all \(i\in N\), we have

$$\begin{aligned} B^i&= \sum _{j\in N\backslash i}(b_j^i-b_i^j) \\&= \sum _{j\in N\backslash i}[AS_j(N,v)-AS_j(N\backslash i,v|_{N\backslash i}) -\frac{1}{n}(v(N)-v(N\backslash i)-v(i))\\&\quad -(AS_i(N,v)-AS_i(N\backslash j,v|_{N\backslash j}) -\frac{1}{n}(v(N)-v(N\backslash j)-v(j)))]\\&= 0. \end{aligned}$$

Therefore, if a player, \(i\in N\), increases his total bid \(\sum _{j\in N\backslash i} b_j^i\), he will become the proposer, but his payoff will decrease. If a player, \(i\in N\), decreases his total bid \(\sum _{j\in N\backslash i} b_j^i\), then his payoff is invariable since other player will be chosen as the proposer. Thus, the strategy is a best response at stage 1. Hence, the above strategies constitute a SPE.

We now prove that any SPE yields the average-surplus value by a series of claims.

Claim (a):

In any SPE, at stage 3, every player \(j\in N\backslash \alpha \) will accept the offer if \(x_j^\alpha > AS_j(N\backslash \alpha ,v|_{N\backslash \alpha })+\frac{1}{n}(v(N)-v(N\backslash \alpha )-v(\alpha ))\). The offer is rejected if there exists at least one player \(j \in N\backslash \alpha \) such that \(x_j^\alpha < AS_j(N\backslash \alpha ,v|_{N\backslash \alpha })+\frac{1}{n}(v(N)-v(N\backslash \alpha )-v(\alpha ))\).

Note that in the case of rejection at stage 3, the payoff of each player, \(j\in N\backslash \alpha \), is \(AS_j (N\backslash \alpha , v|_{N\backslash \alpha })+\frac{1}{n}(v(N)-v(N\backslash \alpha )-v(\alpha ))\) by the induction hypothesis. Thus, a player, \(j\in N\backslash \alpha \), will accept the offer if \(x_j^\alpha > AS_j (N\backslash \alpha , v|_{N\backslash \alpha })+\frac{1}{n}(v(N)-v(N\backslash \alpha )-v(\alpha ))\) since he can improve his payoff, and he will reject the offer if \(x_j^\alpha < AS_j (N\backslash \alpha , v|_{N\backslash \alpha })+\frac{1}{n}(v(N)-v(N\backslash \alpha )-v(\alpha ))\). Therefore, claim (a) is proved by using the same argument for all \(j\in N\backslash \alpha \).

Claim (b):

If \(v(N)> v(N\backslash \alpha ) +v(\alpha )\), the SPE strategies starting from stage 2 are as follows. At stage 2, the proposer \(\alpha \) offers \(x_j^\alpha =AS_j(N\backslash \alpha ,v|_{N\backslash \alpha })+\frac{1}{n}(v(N)-v(N\backslash \alpha )-v(\alpha ))\) to each player \(j\in N\backslash \alpha \); at stage 3, each player, \(j\in N \backslash \alpha \), rejects any offer \(x_j^\alpha < AS_j(N\backslash \alpha ,v|_{N\backslash \alpha })+\frac{1}{n}(v(N)-v(N\backslash \alpha )-v(\alpha ))\) and accepts the offer otherwise. If \(v(N)= v(N\backslash \alpha ) +v(\alpha )\), there exist SPE strategies besides the previous SPE strategies. At stage 2, the proposer \(\alpha \) offers \(x_j^\alpha \le AS_j(N\backslash \alpha ,v|_{N\backslash \alpha })+\frac{1}{n}(v(N)-v(N\backslash \alpha )-v(\alpha ))\) to each player \(j\in N\backslash \alpha \); at stage 3, each player, \(j\in N \backslash \alpha \), rejects any offer \(x_j^\alpha \le AS_j(N\backslash \alpha ,v|_{N\backslash \alpha })+\frac{1}{n}(v(N)-v(N\backslash \alpha )-v(\alpha ))\) and accepts the offer otherwise.

We verify that the previous strategies constitute a SPE. Suppose that \(v(N)> v(N\backslash \alpha ) +v(\alpha )\). In that case, the offer made by the proposer \(\alpha \) is rejected and then the proposer \(\alpha \) obtains \(v(\alpha )-\sum _{j\in N\backslash \alpha }\frac{1}{n}(v(N)-v(N\backslash \alpha )-v(\alpha ))\), which cannot be part of a SPE, since the proposer \(\alpha \) can improve his payoff by offering \(AS_j(N\backslash \alpha ,v|_{N\backslash \alpha }) +\frac{1}{n}(v(N)-v(N\backslash \alpha )-v(\alpha ))+\varepsilon / (n-1)\) to each player \(j\in N\backslash \alpha \) with \(0<\varepsilon < v(N)- v(N\backslash \alpha ) -v(\alpha )\) so that the offer is accepted by claim (a). Therefore, it implies that \(x_j^\alpha \ge AS_j(N\backslash \alpha ,v|_{N\backslash \alpha })+\frac{1}{n}(v(N)-v(N\backslash \alpha )-v(\alpha ))\) for all \(j\in N\backslash \alpha \) in any SPE. However, an offer with \(x_j^\alpha > AS_j(N\backslash \alpha ,v|_{N\backslash \alpha })+\frac{1}{n}(v(N)-v(N\backslash \alpha )-v(\alpha ))\) for some \(j\in N\backslash \alpha \) cannot be part of a SPE. The reason is that the proposer \(\alpha \) can improve his payoff by offering \(AS_j(N\backslash \alpha ,v|_{N\backslash \alpha }) +\frac{1}{n}(v(N)-v(N\backslash \alpha )-v(\alpha ))+\varepsilon / (n-1)\) to each player \(j\in N\backslash \alpha \) with \(\varepsilon < x_j^\alpha - AS_j(N\backslash \alpha ,v|_{N\backslash \alpha })-\frac{1}{n}(v(N)-v(N\backslash \alpha )-v(\alpha ))\) and \(\varepsilon > 0\). Hence, \(x_j^\alpha =AS_j(N\backslash \alpha ,v|_{N\backslash \alpha })+\frac{1}{n}(v(N)-v(N\backslash \alpha )-v(\alpha ))\) for all \(j\in N\backslash \alpha \), and acceptation of the offer implies that each player \(j\in N \backslash \alpha \) accepts any offer \(x_j^\alpha \ge AS_j(N\backslash \alpha ,v|_{N\backslash \alpha })+\frac{1}{n}(v(N)-v(N\backslash \alpha )-v(\alpha ))\).

If \(v(N) = v(N\backslash \alpha ) +v(\alpha )\), the proposer \(\alpha \) offers at least \(AS_j(N\backslash \alpha ,v|_{N\backslash \alpha })+\frac{1}{n}(v(N)-v(N\backslash \alpha )-v(\alpha ))\) to each player \(j\in N\backslash \alpha \) so that the offer can be accepted by the same argument in the previous case. The proposer gets \(v(\alpha )-\sum _{j\in N\backslash \alpha }\frac{1}{n}(v(N)-v(N\backslash \alpha )-v(\alpha ))\) in the case of rejection, which is identity to the payoff in the case of acceptation. Therefore, any offer that leads to a rejection also is a SPE.

Claim (c):

In any SPE, the net bid \(B^i=0\) for all \(i\in N\).

Let \(\Lambda =\{i\in N|B^i=\max _{j\in N}B^j\}\). If \(\Lambda = N\), the net bid \(B^i=0\) for all \(i\in N\) due to \(\sum _{i\in N}B^i=0\). Otherwise, for all \(j\in \Lambda \), he can improve his expected payoff by slightly changing his bids without altering the set \(\Lambda \). Let \(j\notin \Lambda \) and \(i\in \Lambda \). Player i changes his strategy by making bids \(b^{'i}_k=b_k^i+\delta \) for all \(k\in \Lambda \backslash i\), \(b_j^{'i}=b^i_j-|\Lambda |\delta \), and \(b^{'i}_l=b^i_l\) for all \(l\notin \Lambda \) and \(l\ne j\). Then the net bids are \(B^{'k}=B^k-\delta \) for all \(k\in \Lambda \); \(B^{'j}=B^j+|\Lambda |\delta \); \(B^{'l}=B^l\) for all \(l\notin \Lambda \) and \(l\ne j\). Because \(B^l<B^i\) for all \(l\notin \Lambda \), there must exist \(\delta >0\) such that \(B^j+|\Lambda |\delta <B^i-\delta \) and \(B^{'l}<B^{'i}=B^{'k}\) for all \(k\in \Lambda \). Therefore, \(\Lambda \) remains unchanged, but player i’s expected payoff increases.

Claim (d):

In any SPE, the payoff of every player is invariable whoever is chosen as the proposer.

The net bids of all players are the same by claim (c). Then every player would not strictly prefer to be the proposer. Otherwise, he has to enhance his bids, which will result in a decrease of his payoff. On the other hand, if a player prefers that the proposer is one of the other players, he needs to decrease his bids, which makes no difference to his payoff.

Claim (e):

In any SPE, the final payoff of every player coincides with the average-surplus value.

Firstly, if a player, \(i\in N\), is the proposer, his final payoff is \(y_i^i=v(N)-v(N\backslash i)- \sum _{j\in N\backslash i}(b_j^i+\frac{1}{n}(v(N)-v(N\backslash i)-v(i)))\). Then, if a player, \(j\in N\backslash i\), is the proposer, player i’s final payoff is \(y_i^j=AS_i(N\backslash j, v|_{N\backslash j})+\frac{1}{n}(v(N)-v(N\backslash j)-v(j))+b_i^j\). Therefore, the sum of player i’s payoff over all possible choices is as follows,

$$\begin{aligned} \sum _{j\in N}y_i^j&= v(N)-v(N\backslash i)- \sum _{j\in N\backslash i}\left( b_j^i+\frac{1}{n}(v(N)-v(N\backslash i)-v(i))\right) \\&\quad +\sum _{j\in N \backslash i}(AS_i(N\backslash j, v|_{N\backslash j}) +\frac{1}{n}(v(N)-v(N\backslash j)-v(j))+b_i^j) \\&= v(N)-\frac{1}{n}\sum _{j\in N}(v(N\backslash j)+v(j))+v(i) +\sum _{j\in N\backslash i}AS_i(N\backslash j, v|_{N\backslash j})\\&= nAS_i(N,v), \end{aligned}$$

where the last equality holds by Corollary 2. By claim (d), we have \(y_i^j=y_i^k\) for all \(j,k\in N\), and then we conclude that \(y_i^j=AS_i(N,v)\) for all \(j \in N\). Hence, the final payoff of every player coincides with the average-surplus value. \(\square \)

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Li, W., Xu, G., Zou, R. et al. The allocation of marginal surplus for cooperative games with transferable utility. Int J Game Theory 51, 353–377 (2022). https://doi.org/10.1007/s00182-021-00795-9

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s00182-021-00795-9

Keywords

Navigation