Abstract
This paper examines a signaling game with endogenous types in which the sender can influence the property of his private information. We propose an equilibrium selection criterion, called criterion D3, which builds on criterion D1 from signaling games without endogenous types (Cho and Kreps 1987 and Cho and Sobel 1990). We examine the selected equilibrium properties and compare them to the equilibria selected under the existing selection rules.
Similar content being viewed by others
Notes
I am grateful for a referee to suggest an alternative extension of criterion D1.
This type of extension is consistent with In and Wright (2018).
Strict dominance is more than what we need. If the added strategies are never best responses (Kohlberg and Mertens 1986), the same conclusion continues to hold. I am grateful to Hari Govindan for pointing out a subtle difference between the addition and deletion of strictly dominated strategies.
Just like the example on page 1017 in Kohlberg and Mertens (1986), our example is not generic. Whether we can construct a generic example of a signaling game with endogenous types remains unknown.
This property fails in the example examined in Sect. 2.
Note that we have defined the Riley outcome as a normal form concept, not as an extensive form concept.
The solution concept for \(\Gamma (\sigma _\pi )\) depends on the specific problem, including sequential equilibrium and D1 equilibrium.
References
Banks JS, Sobel J (1987) Equilibrium selection in signaling games. Econometrica 55(3):647–661
Burkart M, Lee S (2015) Signalling to dispersed shareholders and corporate control. Rev Econ Stud 82(3):922–962
Cho I-K, Kreps DM (1987) Signaling games and stable equilibria. Q J Econ 102(2):179–221
Cho I-K, Sobel J (1990) Strategic stability and uniqueness in signaling games. J Econ Theory 50:381–413
Ekmekci M, Kos N (2020) “Signaling Covertly Acquired Information,” Boston College
Grassi S, Ma C-TA (2016) Information acquisition, referral, and organization. RAND J Econ 47(4):935–960
Grossman SJ, Perry M (1986) Perfect sequential equilibrium. J Econ Theory 39(1):97–119
In Y, Wright J (2018) Signaling private choices. Rev Econ Stud 85(1):558–580
Kohlberg E, Mertens J-F (1986) On the strategic stability of equilibria. Econometrica 54(5):1003–1037
Kreps DM, Wilson R (1982) Sequential Equilibria. Econometrica 50:863–894
Rüdiger J, Vigier A (2020) Who acquires information in dealer markets? Am Econ Rev 110(4):1145–76
Rubinstein A (1985) A bargaining model with incomplete information about time preferences. Econometrica 53(5):1151–1172
Spence AM (1973) Job market signaling. Q J Econ 87(3):355–374
Author information
Authors and Affiliations
Corresponding author
Additional information
Publisher's Note
Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.
Financial support from the National Science Foundation and the Korea Research Foundation is gratefully acknowledged. I thank Hari Govindan and Joel Sobel for their helpful communication.
Appendix A. Proof of Proposition 3.4
Appendix A. Proof of Proposition 3.4
We only prove the “only if” part. Let \(\epsilon _n=(\epsilon _n(\pi ,m),\epsilon _n(a))\) be the profile of minimum probabilities for \((\pi ,m,a)\in \Pi \times {{\mathcal {M}}}\times A\). Let \(G^{\epsilon _n}\) be a perturbed game of G, where \(\epsilon _n\rightarrow 0\) is a profile of the minimum probabilities for each pure strategy in G. We need to construct a Nash equilibrium of \(G^{\epsilon _n}\) whose outcome is close to \([\sigma ,r]\).
-
(1)
By U4, \(\forall k\), \((\pi ,m)\) with \(\pi <{{\overline{\pi }}}\) is never a weak best response. We consider a game obtained by eliminating these “never weak best responses.” Given G, define \({{\overline{G}}}\) as the signaling game in which the set of endogenous types is \(\Pi =\{{{\overline{\pi }}}\}\) instead of \([0,{{\overline{\pi }}}]\). \({{\overline{G}}}\) is a monotonic signaling game where criterion D1 is generically equivalent to strategic stability (Cho and Sobel 1990).
-
(2)
We perturb each player’s payoffs in \({{\overline{G}}}\) according to \(\epsilon _n(\pi ,m)\). Define
$$\begin{aligned} {{\overline{u}}}_n(k,{{\overline{\pi }}},m,a)=\sum _{\pi<{{\overline{\pi }}}}\epsilon _n(\pi ,m) u(k,\pi ,m,a) +\left( 1-\sum _{\pi <{{\overline{\pi }}}}\epsilon _n(\pi ,m)\right) u(k,{{\overline{\pi }}},m,a) \end{aligned}$$and
$$\begin{aligned} {{\overline{v}}}_n(k,{{\overline{\pi }}},m,a)=\sum _{\pi<{{\overline{\pi }}}}\epsilon _n(\pi ,m) v(k,\pi ,m,a) +\left( 1-\sum _{\pi <{{\overline{\pi }}}}\epsilon _n(\pi ,m)\right) v(k,{{\overline{\pi }}},m,a). \end{aligned}$$\({{\overline{u}}}_n\) is the expected payoff of choosing \({{\overline{\pi }}}\) subject to the constraint that all other \(\pi <{{\overline{\pi }}}\) is used with minimum probabilities \(\{\epsilon _n(\pi ,m)\}\). Similarly, \({{\overline{v}}}_n\) is the receiver’s expected payoff when the receiver chooses \(a\in A\), while the sender chooses \(\pi <{{\overline{\pi }}}\) with the minimum probabilities. Define \({{\overline{G}}}_n\) as the signaling game obtained by replacing (u, v) by \(({{\overline{u}}}_n,{{\overline{v}}}_n)\). Note that \({{\overline{G}}}_n\) remains a monotonic signaling game.
-
(3)
Define \(\epsilon _n(m\mid k)=\sum _\pi \epsilon _n(\pi ,m\mid k)\) as the minimum probability to choose m in \({{\overline{G}}}_n\) by type k sender. Let \(\epsilon _n(m)=(\epsilon _n(m\mid k))_{k\in {{\mathcal {K}}}}\). Define \({{\overline{G}}}^{\epsilon _n(m),\epsilon _n(a)}_n\) as the perturbed game of \({{\overline{G}}}_n\) by forcing each player to use each action with minimum probabilities \(\{\epsilon _n(m),\epsilon _n(a)\}\).
Fix a sequential equilibrium outcome \([\sigma ,r]\) that survives criterion D3. We know that \([\sigma ,r]\) survives criterion D1 in \({{\overline{G}}}\). Since \({{\overline{G}}}\) is a monotonic signaling game, \([\sigma ,r]\) is a stable outcome generically. In a generic game, a D1 outcome changes continuously with respect to the payoffs of the game. For a small \((\epsilon _n(m),\epsilon _n(a))\), there exists a sequential equilibrium surviving D1 in \({{\overline{G}}}_n\), \((\sigma _n,r_n)\), so that
Since \({{\overline{G}}}_n\) is a monotonic signaling game, \([\sigma _n,r_n]\) is a stable outcome generically. Therefore, for any small \((\epsilon _n(m),\epsilon _n(a))\), there is a Nash equilibrium \(({{\overline{\sigma }}}_n,{{\overline{r}}}_n)\) in \({{\overline{G}}}_n\) so that
We now move from \({{\overline{G}}}_n\) to \(G^{\epsilon _n}\) by adding \((\pi ,m)\) with \(\pi <{{\overline{\pi }}}\) back to the sender’s feasible actions.
We claim that \([{{\overline{\sigma }}}_n,{{\overline{r}}}_n]\) induces Nash equilibrium outcome \(({{\tilde{\sigma }}}_n,{{\tilde{r}}}_n)\) in \(G^{\epsilon _n}\) so that
from which the conclusion of the proof follows.
By the construction of \({{\overline{G}}}_n\), the expected payoff of each player is equal to the equilibrium payoff from \([{{\overline{\sigma }}}_n,{{\overline{r}}}_n]\) in \(G^{\epsilon _n}\), if \(\forall \pi <{{\overline{\pi }}}\) is assigned with the minimum probability. By U4, \((\pi ,m)\) with \(\pi <{{\overline{\pi }}}\) is never a best response. Thus, it is optimal for the sender to use \(\pi <{{\overline{\pi }}}\) only with the minimum probability in any Nash equilibrium of \(G^{\epsilon _n}\). By V1, the receiver’s response remains close to the best response for the belief in \({{\overline{G}}}_n\). Define \({{\tilde{r}}}_n(m)={{\overline{r}}}_n(m)\) and a mixed strategy \({{\tilde{\sigma }}}_n(\cdot |k)\) as
By the construction of \({{\overline{G}}}_n\), \(({{\tilde{\sigma }}}_n,{{\tilde{r}}}_n)\) constitutes a Nash equilibrium in \(G^{\epsilon _n}\).
Rights and permissions
Springer Nature or its licensor (e.g. a society or other partner) holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.
About this article
Cite this article
Cho, IK. Signaling games with endogenous types. Int J Game Theory 52, 157–174 (2023). https://doi.org/10.1007/s00182-022-00813-4
Accepted:
Published:
Issue Date:
DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s00182-022-00813-4