Abstract
We compare the voluntary contribution mechanism with any mechanism attaining Pareto-efficient allocations when each agent can choose whether he/she participates in the mechanism for the provision of a non-excludable public good. We find that, in our participation game, the voluntary contribution mechanism, because of its higher participation probability in the unique symmetric mixed strategy Nash equilibrium, may perform better than any Pareto-efficient mechanism in terms of the equilibrium expected provision level of the public good and the equilibrium expected payoff of each agent. Our results suggest that the voluntary contribution mechanism, which cannot realize Pareto-efficient allocations under compulsory participation, might be superior to any Pareto-efficient mechanism if we allow agents to voluntarily choose participation in the mechanism.



Similar content being viewed by others
Notes
The main drawback of the Groves-Ledyard mechanism is that it is not individually rational; that is, the equilibrium allocation determined by the mechanism does not necessarily satisfy the condition that it is at least as good as each agent’s initial endowment. Hurwicz (1979) and Walker (1981) subsequently succeeded in constructing a mechanism whose Nash equilibrium allocations are Lindahl allocations that satisfy both Pareto-efficiency and individual rationality. Since then, numerous mechanisms that satisfy additional desirable properties, such as individual feasibility and balancedness, have been proposed. See, for example, Groves and Ledyard (1987), Tian (1989; 1990), Kim (1993; 1996), de Trenqualye (1994), Dutta et al. (1995), Chen (2002), Suzuki (2009), Rouillon (2013), and Van Essen (2013).
Under the aforementioned mechanisms, agents choose strategies simultaneously. These are called mechanisms in normal form. On the contrary, under the PEMs for public goods proposed by Moore and Repullo (1988) and Varian (1994), agents select strategies sequentially. These are called mechanisms in extensive form.
As mentioned above, several studies have examined mechanisms whose Nash equilibrium allocations are Lindahl allocations that are Pareto-efficient. The VCM has also been theoretically investigated by several authors (e.g., Warr (1982; 1983), Bergstrom et al. (1986), Saijo and Tatamitani (1994), Kotchen (2006), and Saijo (2020)). Moreover, many studies have experimentally tested these mechanisms. See Chen (2008) and Croson (2008) for surveys on the experimental results for public goods provision mechanisms.
Hong and Lim (2016) provided analytical and experimental results that support Dixit and Olson’s (2000) simulation results. Koriyama (2009) compared the compulsory participation case with the voluntary participation case under the provision point mechanism and reported that, in some situations, the expected payoff in the latter case is higher than that in the former case. Heijnen (2009) also considered symmetric mixed strategy Nash equilibria in their participation games with a binary public good and then examined how the probability of breakdown (i.e., no one participates) varies with group size. Similarly, we examine how the probability of breakdown varies with group size in our participation game with a continuous public good (see Appendix D).
Let \(a,b\in \mathbb {R}\) be such that \(a\le b\). Then, we denote by [a, b] and ]a, b[ the closed interval from a to b and the open interval from a to b, respectively.
This normalization does not affect our analysis.
Given a non-empty set X, we denote by \(\#X\) the cardinality of X.
For simplicity, we confine our attention to mechanisms in normal form. This restriction does not affect the results.
Although Proposition 1 reveals nothing about the existence of a symmetric pure strategy Nash equilibrium, we can find a PEM that has a symmetric pure strategy Nash equilibrium in our symmetric Cobb-Douglas economies. Van Essen’s (2013) mechanism stated in Remark 1 is such an example. A symmetric pure strategy Nash equilibrium of this mechanism is given by \(m_{i}=(r_{i},s_{i})=((1-\alpha )\#T, (1-\alpha )\#T)\) for each \(i \in T\). The same thing holds for other Lindahl mechanisms. See, for example, Hurwicz (1979), Walker (1981), Tian (1989; 1990), de Trenqualye (1994), Chen (2002), Dutta et al. (1995), and Suzuki (2009). (Note however that these studies, with the exception of de Trenqualye (1994), consider the case of at least three agents and do not cover the two agents case.) Moreover, for the VCM, we can confirm that there is a unique symmetric pure strategy Nash equilibrium in our symmetric Cobb-Douglas economies, given by \(m_{i}=\frac{1-\alpha }{1+\alpha (\#T-1)}\) for each \(i \in T\).
For example, consider the three-agent case. Let \(\alpha = 0.7\). Then, there are three pure strategy Nash equilibria under which only one agent chooses P under both any PEM and the VCM. These pure strategy Nash equilibria are all asymmetric.
This mixed strategy is an evolutionarily stable strategy (Maynard Smith 1982). That is, the symmetric mixed strategy Nash equilibrium satisfies the strong stability property and hence, is worth analyzing.
Strictly speaking, in the case of \(\alpha = 0.2\), the expected payoff ratio is greater than 1 when there are at least 11 agents (\({{EP}}(0.2, 11) \approx 1.0010 > 1\)).
We thank an anonymous referee for suggesting the interpretations of these equations.
Note that
$$\begin{aligned} \lim _{\alpha \downarrow 0} \alpha ^{\alpha } = \lim _{\alpha \downarrow 0} \exp (\alpha \ln \alpha )= \exp \left( \lim _{\alpha \downarrow 0} \frac{\ln \alpha }{\frac{1}{\alpha }}\right) = \exp \left( \lim _{\alpha \downarrow 0} \frac{\frac{1}{\alpha }}{\frac{-1}{\alpha ^2}}\right) = \exp \left( \lim _{\alpha \downarrow 0} -\alpha \right) = \exp \left( 0 \right) = 1, \end{aligned}$$where the third equality follows from the l’Hôpital’s rule. Using this fact, we obtain \(\lim _{\alpha \downarrow 0} g^{{\tiny \text{V}}}_{\oplus }(\alpha ,k) =\lim _{\alpha \downarrow 0} \frac{\alpha ^{\alpha }(k+1)}{1+k\alpha } = \frac{\lim _{\alpha \downarrow 0} \alpha ^{\alpha }(k+1)}{\lim _{\alpha \downarrow 0} (1+k\alpha )} = k+1\). Moreover, we obtain \(\lim _{\alpha \downarrow 0}\frac{\alpha ^{\alpha }}{(1+k\alpha )^{2}} = 1\) and \(\lim _{\alpha \downarrow 0}\frac{\alpha ^\alpha \left( 1 + \ln \alpha \right) }{1+k\alpha } = -\infty\), and thus, \(\lim _{\alpha \downarrow 0} \frac{\partial g^{{\tiny \text{V}}}_{\oplus }(\alpha ,k)}{\partial \alpha } =\lim _{\alpha \downarrow 0} \left( -k(k+1) \cdot \frac{\alpha ^{\alpha }}{(1+k\alpha )^{2}} + (k+1) \cdot \frac{\alpha ^\alpha \left( 1 + \ln \alpha \right) }{1+k\alpha }\right) = -\infty .\)
By similar calculations, we can confirm that \(\lim _{\alpha \downarrow 0}\frac{\partial g^{{\tiny \text{V}}}_{\oplus }(\alpha , 1)}{\partial \alpha } = -\infty\), \(\lim _{\alpha \uparrow 1}\frac{\partial g^{{\tiny \text{V}}}_{\oplus }(\alpha , 1)}{\partial \alpha } = \frac{1}{2}\), \(\lim _{\alpha \downarrow 0}\frac{\partial g^{{\tiny \text{V}}}_{\ominus }(\alpha , 1)}{\partial \alpha }= 0\), and \(\lim _{\alpha \uparrow 1}\frac{\partial g^{{\tiny \text{V}}}_{\ominus }(\alpha , 1)}{\partial \alpha } = 0\). Thus, we obtain \(\lim _{\alpha \downarrow 0}\frac{\partial g^{{\tiny \text{V}}}(\alpha , 1)}{\partial \alpha } = \lim _{\alpha \downarrow 0}\left( \frac{\partial g^{{\tiny \text{V}}}_{\oplus }(\alpha , 1)}{\partial \alpha } - \frac{\partial g^{{\tiny \text{V}}}_{\ominus }(\alpha , 1)}{\partial \alpha } \right) = -\infty\) and \(\lim _{\alpha \uparrow 1}\frac{\partial g^{{\tiny \text{V}}}(\alpha , 1)}{\partial \alpha } = \lim _{\alpha \uparrow 1}\left( \frac{\partial g^{{\tiny \text{V}}}_{\oplus }(\alpha , 1)}{\partial \alpha } - \frac{\partial g^{{\tiny \text{V}}}_{\ominus }(\alpha , 1)}{\partial \alpha }\right) = \frac{1}{2}\).
We thank an anonymous referee for suggesting the discussion of this section.
We observe that \(18 \cdot p^{{\tiny \text{V}}}(0.2, 18) \approx 3.619781\), \(19 \cdot p^{{\tiny \text{V}}}(0.2, 19) \approx 3.619798\), and \(20 \cdot p^{{\tiny \text{V}}}(0.2, 20) \approx 3.619796\).
References
Bag PK, Mondal D (2014) Group size paradox and public goods. Econ Lett 25:215–218
Bagnoli M, Lipman B (1988) Successful takeovers without exclusion. Rev Financ Stud 1:89–110
Bergstrom T, Blume L, Varian H (1986) On the private provision of public goods. J Public Econ 29:25–49
Chen Y (2002) A family of supermodular Nash mechanisms implementing Lindahl allocations. Econ Theory 19:773–790
Chen Y (2008) Incentive-compatible mechanisms for pure public goods: a survey of experimental research. In: Smith V, Plott C (eds) Handbook of Experimental Economics Results, vol 1. North Holland, Amsterdam, pp 625–643
Croson R (2008) Public goods experiments. In: Durlauf SN, Blume LE (eds) The New Palgrave Dictionary of Economics, 2nd edn. Palgrave Macmillan, Basingstoke
de Trenqualye P (1994) Nash implementation of Lindahl allocations. Soc Choice Welf 11:83–94
Dixit A, Olson M (2000) Does voluntary participation undermine the Coase theorem? J Public Econ 76:309–335
Dutta B, Sen A, Vohra R (1995) Nash implementation through elementary mechanisms in economic environments. Econ Des 1:173–204
Furusawa T, Konishi H (2011) Contributing or free-riding? Voluntary participation in a public good economy. Theor Econ 6:219–256
Groves T, Ledyard J (1977) Optimal allocation of public goods: a solution to the ‘free rider’ problem. Econometrica 45:783–809
Groves T, J. Ledyard (1987) Incentive compatibility since 1972. In: Groves T, Radner R, Reiter S (eds) Information, Incentives, and Economic Mechanisms: Essays in Honor of Leonid Hurwicz. University of Minnesota Press, Minneapolis, pp 48–111
Healy PJ (2010) Equilibrium participation in public goods allocations. Rev Econ Des 14:27–50
Heijnen P (2009) On the probability of breakdown in participation games. Social Choice Welf 32:493–511
Holmström B, Nalebuff B (1992) To the raider goes the surplus? A reexamination of the free-rider problem. J Econ Manag Strategy 1:37–62
Hong F, Karp L (2012) International environmental agreements with mixed strategies and investment. J Public Econ 96:685–697
Hong F, Lim W (2016) Voluntary participation in public goods provision with Coasian bargaining. J Econ Behav Organiz 126:102–119
Hurwicz L (1979) Outcome functions yielding Walrasian and Lindahl allocations at Nash equilibrium points. Rev Econ Stud 46:217–224
Kim T (1993) A stable Nash mechanism implementing Lindahl allocations for quasi-linear environments. J Math Econ 22:359–371
Kim T (1996) A stable Nash mechanism for quasi-additive public good environments. Jpn Econ Rev 47:144–156
Konishi H, Shinohara R (2014) Voluntary participation and the provision of public goods in large finite economies. J Public Econ Theory 16:173–195
Koriyama Y (2009) Freedom to not join: a voluntary participation game of a discrete public good. mimeo
Kotchen MJ (2006) Green markets and private provision of public goods. J Political Econ 114:816–834
Matsushima N, Shinohara R (2012) Private provision of public goods that are complement to private goods: application to open source software developments, ISER Discussion Paper No. 830, Osaka University
Maynard Smith J (1982) Evolution and the Theory of Games. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge
Moore J, Repullo R (1988) Subgame perfect implementation. Econometrica 56:1191–1220
Okada A (1993) The possibility of cooperation in an \(n\)-person prisoners’ dilemma with institutional arrangements. Public Choice 77:629–656
Olson M (1965) The Logic of Collective Action: Public Goods and the Theory of Groups. Harvard University Press, Cambridge
Palfrey T, Rosenthal H (1984) Participation and the provision of discrete public goods: a strategic analysis. J Public Econ 24:171–193
Rouillon S (2013) Anonymous implementation of the Lindahl correspondence: possibility and impossibility results. Social Choice Welf 40:1179–1203
Saijo T (2020) Global stability of voluntary contribution mechanism with heterogeneous preferences, SDES-2020-6, Kochi University of Technology
Saijo T, Tatamitani Y (1994) Characterizing neutrality in the voluntary contribution mechanism. Econ Des 1:119–140
Saijo T, Yamato T (1997) Fundamental difficulties in the provision of public goods: ‘A solution to the free-rider problem’ twenty years after, ISER discussion paper No. 445, Osaka University
Saijo T, Yamato T (1999) A voluntary participation game with a non-excludable public good. J Econ Theory 84:227–242
Saijo T, Yamato T (2010) Fundamental impossibility theorems on voluntary participation in the provision of non-excludable public goods. Rev Econ Des 14:51–73
Samuelson PA (1954) The pure theory of public expenditure. Rev Econ Stat 36:387–389
Shinohara R (2009) The possibility of efficient provision of a public good in voluntary participation games. Social Choice Welf 32:367–387
Shinohara R (2014) Participation and demand levels for a joint project. Social Choice Welf 43:925–952
Suzuki T (2009) Natural implementation in public goods economies. Social Choice Welf 33:647–664
Tian G (1989) Implementation of the Lindahl correspondence by a single-valued, feasible and continuous mechanism. Review of Economic Studies 56:613–621
Tian G (1990) Completely feasible and continuous implementation of the Lindahl correspondence with a message space of minimal dimension. J Econ Theory 51:443–452
Van Essen M (2013) A simple supermodular mechanism that implements Lindahl allocations. J Public Econ Theory 15:363–377
Varian HR (1994) A solution to the problem of externalities when agents are well-informed. Am Econ Rev 84:1278–1293
Walker M (1981) A simple incentive compatible scheme for attaining Lindahl allocations. Econometrica 49:65–71
Warr PG (1982) Pareto optimal redistribution and private charity. J Public Econ 19:131–138
Warr PG (1983) The private provision of a public good is independent of the distribution of income. Econ Lett 13:207–211
Author information
Authors and Affiliations
Corresponding author
Additional information
Publisher's Note
Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.
We are grateful to the associate editor and two anonymous referees whose comments helped us to improve this paper. We also thank Tatsuyoshi Saijo for his suggestions. This work was supported by JSPS KAKENHI Grant Numbers JP22730165, JP22330061, JP25380244, JP15H03328, JP16K03567, JP19K01541, and JP20K01555.
Supplementary Information
Below is the link to the electronic supplementary material.
Appendices
A. Appendix: Proof of Theorem 1
Let
where
Here, \(h^{{\text{PE}}}(p,\alpha ,n)\) and \(g^{{\text{PE}}}(\alpha ,k)\) measure the expected incentive to participate under any PEM when there are n agents and the incentive to participate under any PEM given the participation of k agents, respectively.Footnote 13
1.1 A.1 Outline of the proof
In this subsection, we provide the outline of the proof. We first establish the following preliminary result (Lemma 1): \(g^{{\text{PE}}}\) is strictly decreasing in the number k of participants. This indicates that the incentive to participate declines as the number of participants increases.
To prove statement (i), by using Lemma 1, we first show that \(h^{{\text{PE}}}\) is strictly decreasing in p. That is, the expected incentive to participate decreases as the probability of other agents choosing P increases. Moreover, note that \(h^{{\text{PE}}}(0,\alpha ,n) > 0\), that is, an agent has a positive incentive to participate when the probability of other agents choosing P is zero. By using these facts and the continuity of \(h^{{\text{PE}}}\) with respect to p, we can show the existence and uniqueness of a symmetric mixed strategy Nash equilibrium.
To prove statement (ii), suppose \(p^{{\text{PE}}}(\alpha , n+1) <1\), which implies that there is \(\hat{p} \in \ ]0,1[\) with \(h^{{\text{PE}}}(\hat{p}, \alpha ,n+1) = 0\). From Lemma 1 and with some calculations, we first show \(h^{{\text{PE}}}(\hat{p},\alpha ,n) > 0\) (i.e., \(U_{\textsf{P}}^{{\text{PE}}}(\hat{p},\alpha ,n) > U_{\textsf{NP}}^{{\text{PE}}}(\hat{p},\alpha , n)\)). By the strict decreasingness and continuity of \(h^{{\text{PE}}}\) with respect to p, this fact yields that the equilibrium participation probability in the case of n agents is larger than that in the case of \(n+1\) agents; that is, \(p^{{\text{PE}}}(\alpha , n+1) < p^{{\text{PE}}}(\alpha , n)\).
1.2 A.2 Preliminary result
Lemma 1
For each \(\alpha \in \ ]0, 1[\), \(\frac{\partial g^{{\tiny \text{PE}}}(\alpha , k)}{\partial k}< 0\).
Proof
By differentiating \(g^{{\text{PE}}}\) with respect to k, we obtain
Since \(\alpha \in \ ]0,1[\), we obtain \(\left( \frac{\alpha }{k+1} \right) ^{\alpha } < \left( \frac{1}{k} \right) ^{\alpha }\), which implies \(\frac{\partial g^{{\tiny \text{PE}}}(\alpha , k)}{\partial k}< 0\). \(\square\)
1.3 A.3 Proof of statement (i)
We start showing that \(h^{{\text{PE}}}\) is strictly decreasing in p. Differentiation of \(h^{{\text{PE}}}\) with respect to p yields
The derivation of (1) requires some calculations and is thus relegated to Online Appendix E. It then follows from Lemma 1 that \(g^{{\text{PE}}}(\alpha , k+1) - g^{{\text{PE}}}(\alpha , k) < 0\). This implies \(\frac{\partial h^{{\tiny \text{PE}}}(p,\alpha ,n)}{\partial p} < 0\). Now we have either
-
(a)
for each \(p \in \ ]0, 1[\), \(h^{{\text{PE}}}(p,\alpha ,n) \ne 0\) or
-
(b)
there is \(\bar{p} \in \ ]0,1[\) such that \(h^{{\text{PE}}}(\bar{p}, \alpha ,n) = 0\).
Suppose (a) holds. Note that \(h^{{\text{PE}}}(0,\alpha ,n) =\binom{n-1}{0}g^{{\text{PE}}}(\alpha , 0) = \alpha ^{\alpha } > 0\). By using this fact and the continuity of \(h^{{\text{PE}}}\) with respect to p, we obtain that for each \(p \in [0, 1[\), \(h^{{\text{PE}}}(p, \alpha ,n) > 0\) and \(h^{{\text{PE}}}(1, \alpha ,n) \ge 0\). This implies \(p^{{\text{PE}}}(\alpha , n) = 1\).
Suppose (b) holds. Then, \(\bar{p}\) is a symmetric mixed strategy Nash equilibrium. Since \(h^{{\text{PE}}}(0,\alpha ,n) > 0\) and \(h^{{\text{PE}}}\) is continuous and strictly decreasing in p, we see that such \(\bar{p}\) uniquely exists.
Hence, in each case, we have the desired result. \(\square\)
1.4 A.4 Proof of statement (ii)
Suppose that \(p^{{\text{PE}}}(\alpha , n+1) <1\). This implies that there is \(\hat{p} \in \ ]0,1[\) such that \(h^{{\text{PE}}}(\hat{p}, \alpha ,n+1) = 0\).
The proof is in two steps.Step 1: \({{\varvec{h}}}^{{\textbf{PE}}}(\varvec{\hat{p}}, {\varvec{\alpha }},{{\varvec{n}}}){\textbf{ > 0}}\). Let \(k^{*} > 0\) be such that \(g^{{\text{PE}}}(\alpha , k^{*}) < 0\) and \(g^{{\text{PE}}}(\alpha , k^{*}-1) \ge 0\). Then, Lemma 1, together with \(h^{{\text{PE}}}(\hat{p}, \alpha , n+1) = 0\), implies that such \(k^{*}\) exists and the following conditions hold:
- GE1.:
-
For each \(k \in \{0, \dots , k^{*}-2\}\), \(g^{{\text{PE}}}(\alpha , k) > 0\);
- GE2.:
-
\(g^{{\text{PE}}}(\alpha , k^{*}-1) \ge 0\);
- GE3.:
-
For each \(k \in \{k^{*}, \dots , n\}\), \(g^{{\text{PE}}}(\alpha , k) < 0\).
Then, \(h^{{\text{PE}}}(\hat{p}, \alpha , n+1) = 0\) is equivalent to
This equality can be rearranged to give
Multiplying both sides of the above by \(\frac{1}{n(1-\hat{p})}\),
There are two cases.
-
Case 1: \({{\varvec{k}}}^{*} {\varvec{\ne }} {{\varvec{n}}}\). Note that if (\(n>\)) \(j> k^{*} > \ell\), then \(\frac{1}{n-j}> \frac{1}{n-k^{*}} > \frac{1}{n-\ell }\). Using this fact and (2), we obtain
$$\begin{aligned}&\sum _{k = 0}^{k^{*}-1}\frac{1}{n-k^{*}}\left( {\begin{array}{c}n-1\\ k\end{array}}\right) \hat{p}^{k}(1-\hat{p})^{n-1-k}g^{{\text{PE}}}(\alpha , k) \\&\quad > - \sum _{k = k^{*}}^{n-1}\frac{1}{n-k^*}\left( {\begin{array}{c}n-1\\ k\end{array}}\right) \hat{p}^{k}(1-\hat{p})^{n-1-k}g^{{\text{PE}}}(\alpha , k) - \frac{1}{n-k^{*}} \cdot \frac{\hat{p}^{n}g^{{\text{PE}}}(\alpha , n)}{n(1-\hat{p})}. \end{aligned}$$Multiplying both sides of the above by \(n-k^*\),
$$\begin{aligned}&\sum _{k = 0}^{k^{*}-1}\left( {\begin{array}{c}n-1\\ k\end{array}}\right) \hat{p}^{k}(1-\hat{p})^{n-1-k}g^{{\text{PE}}}(\alpha , k)\\&\quad > - \sum _{k = k^{*}}^{n-1}\left( {\begin{array}{c}n-1\\ k\end{array}}\right) \hat{p}^{k}(1-\hat{p})^{n-1-k}g^{{\text{PE}}}(\alpha , k) - \frac{\hat{p}^{n}g^{{\text{PE}}}(\alpha , n)}{n(1-\hat{p})}, \end{aligned}$$which implies that
$$\begin{aligned} \sum _{k = 0}^{n-1}\left( {\begin{array}{c}n-1\\ k\end{array}}\right) \hat{p}^{k}(1-\hat{p})^{n-1-k}g^{{\text{PE}}}(\alpha , k) > - \frac{\hat{p}^{n}g^{{\text{PE}}}(\alpha , n)}{n(1-\hat{p})}. \end{aligned}$$(3)Since the left-hand side of (3) is equal to \(h^{{\text{PE}}}(\hat{p}, \alpha , n)\), (3) becomes
$$\begin{aligned} h^{{\text{PE}}}(\hat{p}, \alpha , n)> - \frac{\hat{p}^{n}g^{{\text{PE}}}(\alpha , n)}{n(1-\hat{p})} > 0, \end{aligned}$$where the second inequality follows from GE3. This gives the desired conclusion.
-
Case 2: \({{\varvec{k}}}^{*}{\textbf{= }} {{\varvec{n}}}\). Note that if \(n-1 > k\), then \(1 > \frac{1}{n-k}\). Thus,
$$\begin{aligned} \sum _{k = 0}^{n-1}\left( {\begin{array}{c}n-1\\ k\end{array}}\right) \hat{p}^{k}(1-\hat{p})^{n-1-k}g^{{\text{PE}}}(\alpha , k) > \sum _{k = 0}^{n-1}\frac{1}{n-k}\left( {\begin{array}{c}n-1\\ k\end{array}}\right) \hat{p}^{k}(1-\hat{p})^{n-1-k}g^{{\text{PE}}}(\alpha , k). \end{aligned}$$(4)Note that the left-hand side of (4) is equal to \(h^{{\text{PE}}}(\hat{p}, \alpha , n)\). Also, by (2), the right-hand side of (4) is equal to \(- \frac{\hat{p}^{n}g^{{\tiny \text{PE}}}(\alpha , n)}{n(1-\hat{p})}\). Hence, (4) becomes
$$\begin{aligned} h^{{\text{PE}}}(\hat{p}, \alpha , n)>- \frac{\hat{p}^{n}g^{{\text{PE}}}(\alpha , n)}{n(1-\hat{p})} >0, \end{aligned}$$where the second inequality follows from GE3. This gives the desired conclusion.
Step 2: Conclusion. Now we have either
-
(a)
for each \(p \in \ ]0, 1[\), \(h^{{\text{PE}}}(p, \alpha , n) \ne 0\) or
-
(b)
there is \(\bar{p} \in \ ]0, 1[\) such that \(h^{{\text{PE}}}(\bar{p}, \alpha , n) = 0\).
Suppose (a) holds. Since \(h^{{\text{PE}}}\) is continuous and strictly increasing in p, \(h^{{\text{PE}}}(\hat{p}, \alpha , n) > 0\) (Step 1) implies that for each \(p \in [0,1[\), \(h^{{\text{PE}}}(p, \alpha , n) > 0\) and \(h^{{\text{PE}}}(1, \alpha , n) \ge 0\). Hence, \(p^{{\text{PE}}}(\alpha , n)=1 > p^{{\text{PE}}}(\alpha , n+1)\).
Suppose (b) holds. Then, by the continuity and strict decreasingness of \(h^{{\text{PE}}}\) with respect to p, \(h^{{\text{PE}}}(\hat{p}, \alpha , n) > 0\) (Step 1) implies that \(\bar{p} > \hat{p}\), that is, \(p^{{\text{PE}}}(\alpha , n) > p^{{\text{PE}}}(\alpha , n+1)\). \(\square\)
B. Appendix: Proof of Theorem 2
Let
where
Here, \(h^{{\text{V}}}(p,\alpha ,n)\) and \(g^{{\text{V}}}(\alpha ,k)\) measure the expected incentive to participate under the VCM when there are n agents and the incentive to participate under the VCM given the participation of k agents, respectively.
1.1 B.1 Outline of the proof
In this subsection, we provide the outline of the proof. As in the proof of Theorem 1, we first establish preliminary results on the form of \(g^{{\text{V}}}\). However, in contrast to function \(g^{{\text{PE}}}\), function \(g^{{\text{V}}}\) is not decreasing in k and has a somewhat complicated form (Fig. 4a illustrates the form of \(g^{{\text{V}}}(0.5,k)\)). Due to this fact, we cannot prove Theorem 2 by applying exactly the same proof techniques as in Theorem 1. Thus, we provide three useful lemmas regarding the form of \(g^{{\text{V}}}\).
The first lemma (Lemma 2) states that for each \(\alpha \in \ ]0,1[\), \(g^{{\text{V}}}(\alpha , 0)\) is positive. That is, an agent has an incentive to participate if no one participates in the VCM. The second lemma (Lemma 3) states that for each \(k \ge 1\), the graph of the function \(g^{{\text{V}}}(\ \cdot \ , k)\) intersects the horizontal axis only once at some value \(\bar{\alpha } \in \ ]0,1[\). Moreover, the derivative of \(g^{{\text{V}}}(\ \cdot \ , k)\) evaluated at \(\bar{\alpha }\) is negative. That is, there is a threshold \(\bar{\alpha }\) such that, given the participation of k agents, an agent has an incentive to not participate if the value of the public good relative to the private good exceeds the threshold \(\bar{\alpha }\); otherwise, the agent has an incentive to participate. The third lemma (Lemma 4) states that for each \(\alpha \in \ ]0,1[\) and each \(k \ge 0\), \(g^{{\text{V}}}(\alpha , k+1)=0\) implies \(g^{{\text{V}}} (\alpha , k)>0\). That is, if participation and non-participation are indifferent for an agent when there are \(k+1\) participants, then the agent has an incentive to participate when there are k participants. Figure 4b illustrates these lemmas.
To prove statement (i), we focus on the case where \(h^{{\text{V}}}(\bar{p},\alpha ,n) = 0\) for some \(\bar{p} \in \ ]0,1[\), that is, a non-degenerate mixed strategy Nash equilibrium exists; otherwise, by the continuity of \(h^{{\text{V}}}\) with respect to p and the fact that \(h^{{\text{V}}}(0,\alpha ,n) > 0\), we can easily derive the existence and uniqueness result. Then, it suffices to show that \(\frac{\partial h^{{\tiny \text{V}}}(\bar{p}, \alpha , n)}{\partial p} < 0\), that is, the derivative of \(h^{{\text{V}}}\) with respect to p, evaluated at that equilibrium, is negative. This is because, considering that \(h^{{\text{V}}}\) is continuous in p and \(h^{{\text{V}}}(0,\alpha , n) > 0\), this immediately implies that \(\bar{p}\) is the unique symmetric mixed strategy Nash equilibrium.
To prove statement (ii), suppose \(p^{{\text{V}}}(\alpha , n+1) <1\), which implies that there is \(\hat{p} \in \ ]0,1[\) with \(h^{{\text{V}}}(\hat{p},\alpha ,n+1) = 0\). As in the proof of Theorem 1(ii), we first show that \(h^{{\text{V}}}(\hat{p}, \alpha ,n) > 0\) by invoking Lemmas 2–4 and after that we prove that this implies \(p^{{\text{V}}}(\alpha , n+1) < p^{{\text{V}}}(\alpha , n)\).
1.2 B.2 Preliminary results
Lemma 2
For each \(\alpha \in \ ]0,1[\), \(g^{{\text{V}}}(\alpha , 0) > 0\).
Proof
Let \(\alpha \in \ ]0,1[\). Then, \(g^{{\text{V}}}(\alpha , 0) = \alpha ^{\alpha } > 0\). \(\square\)
Lemma 3
For each \(k \ge 1\), there is a unique value \(\bar{\alpha } \in \ ]0,1[\) such that \(g^{{\text{V}}}(\bar{\alpha }, k) = 0\). Moreover, \(\frac{\partial g^{{\tiny \text{V}}}(\bar{\alpha }, k)}{\partial \alpha } < 0\).
Proof
Let
Note that \(g^{{\text{V}}}(\alpha , k) = g^{{\text{V}}}_{\oplus }(\alpha ,k) - g^{{\text{V}}}_{\ominus }(\alpha ,k)\). Then, we obtain
The derivations of these equations are delegated to Online Appendix F.
There are two cases.
-
Case 1: \({{\varvec{k}}} {\varvec{\ge }} {{\varvec{2}}}\). Then, it is easily checked that (i) \(\lim _{\alpha \downarrow 0} g^{{\text{V}}}_{\ominus } (\alpha , k) =k > 1\), (ii) \(\lim _{\alpha \uparrow 1} g^{{\text{V}}}_{\oplus } (\alpha , k)= \lim _{\alpha \uparrow 1} g^{{\text{V}}}_{\ominus } (\alpha , k)=1\), (iii) \(\lim _{\alpha \uparrow 1}\frac{\partial g^{{\tiny \text{V}}}_{\oplus }(\alpha , k) }{\partial \alpha }= - \frac{k}{1+k} + 1> 0\), (iv) \(\lim _{\alpha \downarrow 0}\frac{\partial g^{{\tiny \text{V}}}_{\ominus }(\alpha , k) }{\partial \alpha } = -k(\ln k + k-1)< 0\), (v) \(\lim _{\alpha \uparrow 1}\frac{\partial g^{{\tiny \text{V}}}_{\ominus }(\alpha , k)}{\partial \alpha } = 0\), (vi) \(\frac{\partial ^2 g^{{\tiny \text{V}}}_{\oplus }(\alpha , k) }{\partial \alpha ^2} > 0\), and (vii) \(\frac{\partial ^2 g^{{\tiny \text{V}}}_{\ominus }(\alpha , k) }{\partial \alpha ^2} > 0\). Moreover, by using the l’Hôpital’s rule, we obtain that \(\lim _{\alpha \downarrow 0}g^{{\text{V}}}_{\oplus }(\alpha ,k) = k + 1\) (\(> k = \lim _{\alpha \downarrow 0} g^{{\text{V}}}_{\ominus }(\alpha ,k)\)) and \(\lim _{\alpha \downarrow 0}\frac{\partial g^{{\tiny \text{V}}}_{\oplus }(\alpha , k) }{\partial \alpha } = -\infty < 0\).Footnote 14 Since both \(g_{\oplus }^{{\text{V}}}\) and \(g_{\ominus }^{{\text{V}}}\) are continuous in \(\alpha\), these facts imply that there is a unique value \(\bar{\alpha } \in \ ]0,1[\) such that \(g^{{\text{V}}}_{\oplus }(\bar{\alpha },k) = g^{{\text{V}}}_{\ominus }(\bar{\alpha },k)\), that is, \(g^{{\text{V}}}(\bar{\alpha },k) = 0\).
-
Case 2: \({{\varvec{k}}} = {{\varvec{1}}}\). Then \(\lim _{\alpha \downarrow 0}\frac{\partial g^{{\tiny \text{V}}}(\alpha , 1)}{\partial \alpha } = -\infty < 0\) and \(\lim _{\alpha \uparrow 1}\frac{\partial g^{{\tiny \text{V}}}(\alpha , 1)}{\partial \alpha }= \frac{1}{2}> 0\).Footnote 15 Moreover, we obtain \(\frac{\partial ^2 g^{{\tiny \text{V}}}(\alpha , 1)}{\partial \alpha ^2}> 0\). Since \(\lim _{\alpha \downarrow 0}g^{{\text{V}}}(\alpha , k) = 1 > 0\), \(\lim _{\alpha \uparrow 1}g^{{\text{V}}}(\alpha , k) = 0\), and \(g^{{\text{V}}}\) is continuous in \(\alpha\), these imply that there is a unique value \(\bar{\alpha } \in \ ]0,1[\) with \(g^{{\text{V}}}(\bar{\alpha }, k) = 0\).
Moreover, \(g^{{\text{V}}}(\bar{\alpha }, k) = 0\) implies \(\frac{\partial g^{{\tiny \text{V}}}(\bar{\alpha }, k) }{\partial \alpha }< 0\) because \(\lim _{\alpha \downarrow 0} g^{{\text{V}}}(\alpha ,k) > 0\) and \(g^{{\text{V}}}\) is continuous in \(\alpha\). \(\square\)
Lemma 4
For each \(\alpha \in \ ]0,1[\) and each \(k \ge 0\), if \(g^{{\text{V}}}(\alpha , k+1)=0\), then \(g^{{\text{V}}} (\alpha , k)>0.\)
Proof
Let \(\alpha \in \ ]0,1[\) and \(k \ge 0\) be such that \(g^{{\text{V}}}(\alpha , k+1)=0\). Then,
that is,
By using (5), \(g^{{\text{V}}}(\alpha , k)\) can be rewritten as
Let \(a \equiv \frac{1}{\alpha }\), \(b \equiv \frac{k+1}{1 + k \alpha }\), and \(c \equiv \frac{k}{1 + (k-1) \alpha }\). Note that \(a> b > c\) and
Let \(f \colon \mathbb {R}_{+} \rightarrow \mathbb {R}_{+}\) be a function defined by \(f(x) = x^{1-\alpha }\). Then, by (6),
Since f is strictly concave,
By (7), this can be rewritten as
which implies that
Since \(a-b > 0\) and \(\frac{\alpha }{1+(k-1)\alpha } > \frac{\alpha }{1+k\alpha }\),
which implies
By (8) and (9), we obtain \(g^{{\text{V}}}(\alpha , k) > 0\). \(\square\)
1.3 B.3 Proof of statement (i)
Note that \(h^{{\text{V}}}(0,\alpha ,n) = \binom{n-1}{0}g^{{\text{V}}}(\alpha , 0) = \alpha ^{\alpha } > 0\). Then, we have either
-
(a)
for each \(p \in \ ]0,1[\), \(h^{{\text{V}}}(p,\alpha ,n) \ne 0\) or
-
(b)
there is \(\bar{p} \in \ ]0,1[\) such that \(h^{{\text{V}}}(\bar{p},\alpha ,n) = 0\).
Suppose (a) holds. Then, since \(h^{{\text{V}}}\) is continuous in p and \(h^{{\text{V}}}(0,\alpha ,n) > 0\), we obtain that for each \(p \in [0, 1[\), \(h^{{\text{V}}}(p, \alpha , n) > 0\) and \(h^{{\text{V}}}(1, \alpha , n) \ge 0\). This implies \(p^{{\text{V}}}(\alpha , n) = 1\).
Suppose (b) holds. Then, \(\bar{p}\) is a symmetric mixed strategy Nash equilibrium. In order to show the uniqueness, it is sufficient to show \(\frac{\partial h^{{\tiny \text{V}}}(\bar{p},\alpha ,n)}{\partial p} < 0\). This is because this fact, together with the facts that \(h^{{\text{V}}}(0,\alpha ,n) >0\) and \(h^{{\text{V}}}\) is continuous in p, implies that for each \(p \in [0, \bar{p}[\), \(h^{{\text{V}}}(p,\alpha ,n) > 0\) and for each \(p \in \ ]\bar{p},1 ]\), \(h^{{\text{V}}}(p,\alpha ,n) < 0\) and hence, \(\bar{p}\) is the unique symmetric mixed strategy Nash equilibrium.
By differentiating \(h^{{\text{V}}}\) with respect to p and evaluating this at \(\bar{p}\), we obtain the following:Footnote 16
After some manipulation (see Online Appendix F), (10) can be rewritten as follows:
By (11), the proof is done if we can show \(h^{{\text{V}}}(\bar{p},\alpha , n-1) > 0\). Thus, we now show \(h^{{\text{V}}}(\bar{p},\alpha ,n-1) > 0\). Since \(\lim _{\alpha \downarrow 0}g^{{\text{V}}}(\alpha ,k) > 0\) and \(g^{{\text{V}}}\) is continuous in \(\alpha\), by Lemmas 3 and 4, \(g^{{\text{V}}}(\alpha ,k) < 0\) implies \(g^{{\text{V}}}(\alpha , k+1) < 0\). This, together with \(h^{{\text{V}}}(\bar{p},\alpha ,n) = 0\) and Lemma 2, implies that there exists \(k^{*} > 0\) such that
- GV1.:
-
\(g^{{\text{V}}} (\alpha , 0) > 0\);
- GV2.:
-
For each \(k \in \{1, \dots , k^{*}-1\}\), \(g^{{\text{V}}} (\alpha , k) \ge 0\);
- GV3.:
-
For each \(k \in \{k^{*}, \dots , n-1\}\), \(g^{{\text{V}}} (\alpha , k) < 0\).
Then, \(h^{{\text{V}}}(\bar{p}, \alpha , n) = 0\) is equivalent to
Then, by applying similar arguments as those employed in the proof of statement (ii) of Theorem 1, we obtain \(h^{{\text{V}}}(\bar{p},\alpha ,n-1) > 0\). \(\square\)
1.4 B.4 Proof of statement (ii)
Suppose that \(p^{{\text{V}}}(\alpha , n+1) <1\). This implies that there is \(\hat{p} \in \ ]0,1[\) with \(h^{{\text{V}}}(\hat{p}, \alpha , n+1) = 0\). We now show \(h^{{\text{V}}}(\hat{p}, \alpha , n) > 0\). To do this, let \(k^{*} > 0\) be such that \(g^{{\text{V}}}(\alpha , k^{*}) < 0\) and \(g^{{\text{V}}}(\alpha , k^{*}-1) \ge 0\). Since \(h^{{\text{V}}}(\hat{p},\alpha , n+1) = 0\), Lemmas 2–4 ensure that such \(k^{*}\) exists and GV1–GV2 above and the following slightly modified version of GV3 hold: for each \(k \in \{k^{*}, \dots , n\}\), \(g^{{\text{V}}}(\alpha , k) < 0\). Then, using similar arguments as those employed in the proof of statement (ii) of Theorem 1, we can prove \(h^{{\text{V}}}(\hat{p}, \alpha , n) > 0\).
Now we have either
-
(a)
for each \(p \in \ ]0,1[\), \(h^{{\text{V}}}(p,\alpha , n) \ne 0\) or
-
(b)
there is \(\bar{p} \in \ ]0,1[\) such that \(h^{{\text{V}}}(\bar{p},\alpha ,n) = 0\).
Suppose (a) holds. Since \(h^{{\text{V}}}(0,\alpha ,n) >0\) and \(h^{{\text{V}}}\) is continuous in p, we obtain that for each \(p \in [0,1[\), \(h^{{\text{V}}}(p, \alpha , n) > 0\) and \(h^{{\text{V}}}(1, \alpha , n) \ge 0\). This implies that \(p^{{\text{V}}}(\alpha , n) = 1> p^{{\text{V}}}(\alpha , n+1)\).
Suppose (b) holds. Recall that as shown in the proof of statement (i) of Theorem 2, \(\frac{\partial h^{{\tiny \text{V}}}(\bar{p}, \alpha , n)}{\partial p}< 0\). Considering that \(h^{{\text{V}}}(0,\alpha , n) >0\) and \(h^{{\text{V}}}\) is continuous in p, this implies that for each \(p \in [0, \bar{p}[\), \(h^{{\text{V}}}(p, \alpha , n) > 0\) and for each \(p \in \ ]\bar{p}, 1]\), \(h^{{\text{V}}}(p, \alpha , n) < 0\). Hence, \(h^{{\text{V}}}(\hat{p}, \alpha , n) > 0\) implies \(\bar{p} > \hat{p}\), that is, \(p^{{\text{V}}}(\alpha , n) > p^{{\text{V}}}(\alpha , n+1)\). \(\square\)
C. Appendix: Omitted proofs in Section 5
1.1 C.1 Proof of Theorem 3
The proof is in three steps.
-
Step 1: For each \({\varvec{\alpha }} {\varvec{\in }}\ ]{{\varvec{0}}}, {{\varvec{1}}}[\), \(\frac{{\varvec{\partial }} {{\varvec{h}}}^{{\tiny{\textbf{V}}}}({{\varvec{p}}},{\varvec{\alpha }}, {{\varvec{2}}})}{ {\varvec{\partial }} {{\varvec{p}}}} < {{\varvec{0}}}\). Note that
$$\begin{aligned} \frac{\partial h^{{\text{V}}}(p,\alpha , 2)}{ \partial p} = g^{{\text{V}}}(\alpha , 1) - g^{{\text{V}}}(\alpha , 0) = \frac{2\alpha ^{\alpha }}{1+\alpha } -1 - \alpha ^{\alpha } = \frac{(\alpha ^{\alpha } - 1)-\alpha (1+\alpha ^{\alpha })}{1+\alpha }. \end{aligned}$$Since \(\alpha \in \ ]0,1 [\), we obtain \(\alpha ^{\alpha } -1 <0\), which implies \(\frac{\partial h^{{\tiny \text{V}}}(p,\alpha ,2)}{ \partial p} < 0\).
-
Step 2: For each \({\varvec{\alpha }} {\varvec{\in }}\ ]{{\varvec{0}}}, {{\varvec{1}}}[\), \({{\varvec{1}}} + {\varvec{\alpha }} > {{\varvec{2}}}^{{\varvec{\alpha }}}\). Let \(\varphi (\alpha ) \equiv 1 + \alpha\) and \(\psi (\alpha ) \equiv 2^{\alpha }\). Note that \(\lim _{\alpha \downarrow 0} \varphi (\alpha )= \lim _{\alpha \downarrow 0} \psi (\alpha )= 1\) and \(\lim _{\alpha \uparrow 1} \varphi (\alpha )= \lim _{\alpha \uparrow 1} \psi (\alpha )= 2\). Then, \(\varphi '(\alpha ) = 1 > 0\), \(\varphi ''(\alpha ) = 0\), \(\psi '(\alpha ) = 2^{\alpha } \ln 2 >0\), and \(\psi ''(\alpha ) = 2^{\alpha } \left( \ln 2\right) ^2>0\). Since both \(\varphi\) and \(\psi\) are continuous, for each \(\alpha \in \ ]0, 1[\), \(\varphi (\alpha ) > \psi (\alpha )\), that is, \(1 + \alpha > 2^{\alpha }\).
-
Step 3: Conclusion. Let \(\alpha \in \ ]0, 1[\). As we have shown in the proof of statement (i) of Theorem 1, \(\frac{\partial h^{{\tiny \text{PE}}}(p,\alpha ,2)}{\partial p} < 0\). Moreover, by Step 1, \(\frac{\partial h^{{\tiny \text{V}}}(p,\alpha ,2)}{ \partial p}< 0\). Thus, \(h^{{\text{PE}}}(p, \alpha , 2)- h^{{\text{V}}}(p, \alpha , 2) > 0\) implies that if \(p^{{\text{V}}}(\alpha , 2) = 1\), then \(p^{{\text{PE}}}(\alpha , 2) = 1\) (i.e., \(\textit{PP}(\alpha ,2) = 1\)); otherwise, \(p^{{\text{PE}}}(\alpha , 2) > p^{{\text{V}}}(\alpha , 2)\) (i.e., \(\textit{PP}(\alpha ,2) < 1\)). We now show that \(h^{{\text{PE}}}(p, \alpha , 2)- h^{{\text{V}}}(p, \alpha , 2) > 0\). Then,
$$\begin{aligned} h^{{\text{PE}}}(p, \alpha , 2)- h^{{\text{V}}}(p, \alpha , 2)&= (1-p)[g^{{\text{PE}}}(\alpha , 0) - g^{{\text{V}}}(\alpha , 0)] +p[g^{{\text{PE}}}(\alpha , 1) - g^{{\text{V}}}(\alpha , 1)]\\&=(1-p)(\alpha ^{\alpha }-\alpha ^{\alpha })+p\left[ \frac{2\alpha ^{\alpha }}{2^{\alpha }} - 1 - \left( \frac{2\alpha ^{\alpha }}{1+\alpha } - 1\right) \right] \\&= p 2\alpha ^{\alpha } \left[ \frac{(1+\alpha ) - 2^{\alpha }}{2^{\alpha }(1+\alpha )} \right] \\&>0, \end{aligned}$$
where the last inequality follows from \((1+\alpha ) - 2^{\alpha } > 0\) (Step 2). Hence, \(\textit{PP}(\alpha ,2) \le 1\). Moreover, we can find \(\bar{\alpha } \in \ ]0, 1[\) with \(\textit{PP}(\bar{\alpha },2) < 1\) (e.g., \(\textit{PP}(0.5,2) < 1\)). \(\square\)
1.2 C.2 Proof of Theorem 4
Pick any \(\alpha \in \ ]0,1[\). Let \(y^{{\text{PE}}}_{2}(\alpha )\) (respectively, \(y^{{\text{PE}}}_{1}(\alpha )\)) be the Nash equilibrium provision level of a public good under any PEM when there are two participants (respectively, one participant). The notation \(y^{{\text{V}}}_{2}(\alpha )\) and \(y^{{\text{V}}}_{1}(\alpha )\) are similarly defined. Let \(\bar{p} \equiv p^{{\text{PE}}}(\alpha , 2)\) and \(\tilde{p} \equiv p^{{\text{V}}}(\alpha , 2)\). Note that by Proposition 1, \(y^{{\text{PE}}}_{2}(\alpha ) = 2(1-\alpha )> \frac{2(1-\alpha )}{1+\alpha } = y^{{\text{V}}}_{2}(\alpha )\) and \(y^{{\text{PE}}}_{1}(\alpha ) =(1-\alpha )= y^{{\text{V}}}_{1}(\alpha )\). Then,
Since \(\bar{p} \ge \tilde{p}\) (Theorem 3) and \(2(1-\alpha )> \frac{2(1-\alpha )}{1+\alpha }\), we obtain
This implies \(\textit{PL}(\alpha ,2) < 1\). \(\square\)
1.3 C.3 Proof of Theorem 5
The proof is in three steps.
-
Step 1: For each \({\varvec{\alpha }} {\varvec{\in }}\ ]{{\varvec{0}}}, {{\varvec{1}}}[\), \({{\varvec{2}}}^{{{\varvec{1}}}-{\varvec{\alpha }}} > \frac{{{\varvec{2}}}}{{{\varvec{1}}}+{\varvec{\alpha }}}\). Let \(\zeta (\alpha ) \equiv 2^{1-\alpha }\) and \(\xi (\alpha ) \equiv \frac{2}{1+\alpha }\). Note that \(\lim _{\alpha \downarrow 0} \zeta (\alpha )= \lim _{\alpha \downarrow 0} \xi (\alpha )= 2\) and \(\lim _{\alpha \uparrow 1} \zeta (\alpha )= \lim _{\alpha \uparrow 1} \xi (\alpha )= 1\). Then, \(\zeta '(\alpha ) = -2^{1-\alpha }\ln 2 < 0\), \(\zeta ''(\alpha ) = 2^{1-\alpha }(\ln 2)^2 > 0\), \(\xi '(\alpha ) = -\frac{2}{(1+\alpha )^2} < 0\), and \(\xi ''(\alpha ) = \frac{4}{(1+\alpha )^3} >0\). Moreover, \(\lim _{\alpha \downarrow 0} \zeta '(\alpha )=-2\ln 2 > -2 = \lim _{\alpha \downarrow 0} \xi '(\alpha )\) and \(\lim _{\alpha \uparrow 1} \zeta '(\alpha )=-\ln 2 < -0.5 = \lim _{\alpha \uparrow 1} \xi '(\alpha )\). Since both \(\zeta\) and \(\xi\) are continuous, we obtain that for each \(\alpha \in \ ]0, 1[\), \(\zeta (\alpha ) > \xi (\alpha )\), that is, \(2^{1-\alpha } > \frac{2}{1+\alpha }\).
-
Step 2: For each \({\varvec{\alpha }} {\varvec{\in }}\ ]{{\varvec{0}}}, {{\varvec{1}}}[\), \({{\varvec{U}}}_{\textsf{P}}^{{\textbf{PE}}}(\bar{{{\varvec{p}}}},{\varvec{\alpha }} ,{{\varvec{2}}}) - {{\varvec{U}}}_{\textsf{P}}^{{\textbf{V}}}(\tilde{{{\varvec{p}}}},{\varvec{\alpha }}, {{\varvec{2}}}) > {{\varvec{0}}}\). Pick any \(\alpha \in \ ]0,1[\). Let \(\bar{p} \equiv p^{{\text{PE}}}(\alpha , 2)\) and \(\tilde{p} \equiv p^{{\text{V}}}(\alpha , 2)\). Note that
$$\begin{aligned} U_{\textsf{P}}^{{\text{PE}}}(\bar{p},\alpha ,2)&= (1-\alpha )^{1-\alpha }\alpha ^{\alpha }\left[ (1-\bar{p}) + \bar{p} \cdot 2^{1-\alpha } \right] ;\\ U_{\textsf{P}}^{{\text{V}}}(\tilde{p},\alpha ,2)&= (1-\alpha )^{1-\alpha }\alpha ^{\alpha }\left[ (1-\tilde{p}) + \tilde{p} \cdot \frac{2}{1+\alpha } \right] . \end{aligned}$$
It then follows that
where the first inequality follows from \(2^{1-\alpha } > \frac{2}{1+\alpha }\) (Step 1) and the second inequality follows from \(\bar{p} \ge \tilde{p}\) (Theorem 3).
-
Step 3: Conclusion. By Step 2 and the fact that \(U_{\textsf{P}}^{{\text{PE}}}(\bar{p},\alpha ,2) = U_{\textsf{NP}}^{{\text{PE}}}(\bar{p},\alpha ,2)\) and \(U_{\textsf{P}}^{{\text{PE}}}(\tilde{p},\alpha ,2) = U_{\textsf{NP}}^{{\text{PE}}}(\tilde{p},\alpha ,2)\), we obtain \(U^{{\text{PE}}}(\alpha , 2) - U^{{\text{V}}}(\alpha , 2) > 0\). This implies \(\textit{EP}(\alpha ,2) < 1\). \(\square\)
D. Appendix: Expected participation level and probability of breakdown
In this section, we first consider the expected participation level under any PEM, \(n \cdot p^{{\text{PE}}}(\alpha , n)\), and under the VCM, \(n \cdot p^{{\text{V}}}(\alpha , n)\).Footnote 17 It is not clear whether the expected participation level increases or decreases with the number of agents, n, because one factor (the number of agents) increases while another (participation probability) decreases. Table 4 presents the expected participation level under both any PEM and the VCM when \(\alpha\) varies from 0.1 to 0.9 and n from 2 to 500. We then observe the following:
-
PEM: If \(\alpha = 0.5\), then \(n \cdot p^{{\text{PE}}}(\alpha , n)\) monotonically decreases as n increases. If \(\alpha = 0.9\), then \(n \cdot p^{{\text{PE}}}(\alpha , n)\) monotonically increases as n increases. For the other cases, \(n \cdot p^{{\text{PE}}}(\alpha , n)\) is non-monotonic in n. Specifically:
-
\({\varvec{\alpha }} = {\varvec{0.1}}\): In this case, \(p^{{\text{PE}}}(0.1 ,n) = 1\) if \(n \le 4\); otherwise, \(p^{{\text{PE}}}(0.1 ,n) < 1\). Thus, \(n \cdot p^{{\text{PE}}}(0.1, n)\) monotonically increases until \(n = 4\). When n increases from 4 to 5, \(n \cdot p^{{\text{PE}}}(0.1, n)\) also increases while \(p^{{\text{PE}}}(0.1 ,n)\) decreases. However, \(n \cdot p^{{\text{PE}}}(0.1, n)\) monotonically decreases over \(n =5\) as n increases.
-
\({\varvec{\alpha }} = {\varvec{0.2}}\): In this case, \(p^{{\text{PE}}}(0.2 ,n) = 1\) if \(n \le 3\); otherwise, \(p^{{\text{PE}}}(0.2, n) < 1\). Thus, \(n \cdot p^{{\text{PE}}}(0.2, n)\) monotonically increases until \(n = 3\). However, it monotonically decreases over \(n =3\) as n increases.
-
\(\varvec{\alpha } \varvec{\in } \{\varvec{0.3, 0.4, 0.6, 0.7, 0.8}\}\): In this case, \(p^{{\text{PE}}}(\alpha , n)\) monotonically decreases as n increases. If \(\alpha \in \{0.3, 0.4, 0.6, 0.7\}\) (resp. \(\alpha = 0.8\)), \(n \cdot p^{{\text{PE}}}(\alpha , n)\) increases in n until \(n=3\) (resp. \(n = 6\)) and then decreases.
-
-
VCM: If \(\alpha \in \{0.3, \dots , 0.9\}\), \(n \cdot p^{{\text{V}}}(\alpha , n)\) monotonically increases as n increases. If \(\alpha \in \{0.1,0,2\}\), \(n \cdot p^{{\text{V}}}(\alpha , n)\) is non-monotonic in n. Specifically:
-
\({\varvec{\alpha }} = {{\varvec{0.1}}}\): In this case, \(p^{{\text{V}}}(0.1 ,n) = 1\) if \(n \le 6\); otherwise, \(p^{{\text{V}}}(0.1 ,n) < 1\). Thus, \(n \cdot p^{{\text{V}}}(0.1, n)\) monotonically increases until \(n = 6\). When n increases from 6 to 7, \(n \cdot p^{{\text{V}}}(0.1, n)\) also increases until \(n =7\) while \(p^{{\text{V}}}(0.1 ,n)\) decreases. However, \(n \cdot p^{{\text{V}}}(0.1, n)\) monotonically decreases over \(n =7\) as n increases.
-
\({\varvec{\alpha }} = {{\varvec{0.2}}}\): In this case, \(p^{{\text{V}}}(0.2, n) = 1\) if \(n \le 3\); otherwise, \(p^{{\text{V}}}(0.2, n) < 1\). Thus, \(n \cdot p^{{\text{V}}}(0.2, n)\) monotonically increases until \(n = 3\). Interestingly, it also increases until \(n = 19\) while \(p^{{\text{V}}}(0.2 ,n)\) decreases. However, \(n \cdot p^{{\text{V}}}(0.2, n)\) monotonically decreases over \(n =19\) as n increases.Footnote 18
-
These observations tell us how the expected participation level varies in group size depending on the value of preference parameter \(\alpha\) under both any PEM and the VCM.
Next, we consider the probability of breakdown under any PEM, \(\left( 1 - p^{{\text{PE}}}(\alpha , n)\right)^n\), and under the VCM, \(\left( 1 - p^{{\text{V}}}(\alpha , n)\right)^n\). Table 5 presents the probability of breakdown under both any PEM and the VCM when \(\alpha\) varies from 0.1 to 0.9 and n from 2 to 500. This table indicates that under both mechanisms, the probability of breakdown monotonically increases as the number of agents increases.
It is, however, hard to obtain analytical results on both the expected participation level and the probability of breakdown. This is because the expected utility functions take complicated forms in our model, and thus, we cannot derive the explicit forms of \(p^{{\text{PE}}}(\alpha , n)\) and \(p^{{\text{V}}}(\alpha , n)\).Footnote 19
Rights and permissions
Springer Nature or its licensor (e.g. a society or other partner) holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.
About this article
Cite this article
Wakayama, T., Yamato, T. Comparison of the voluntary contribution and Pareto-efficient mechanisms under voluntary participation. Int J Game Theory 52, 517–553 (2023). https://doi.org/10.1007/s00182-022-00828-x
Accepted:
Published:
Issue Date:
DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s00182-022-00828-x
Keywords
- Voluntary participation
- Non-excludable public goods
- Voluntary contribution mechanism
- Pareto-efficient mechanism
- Mixed strategies