Skip to main content
Log in

The “desire to conform” and dynamic search by a committee

  • Original Paper
  • Published:
International Journal of Game Theory Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

We consider dynamic search by a committee where members exhibit an innate desire to conform to the committee’s decision, in addition to their economic incentives. This gives rise to multiple equilibria. “Conformal” equilibria now exist, at least one in which every member votes to continue (stop) the search except on receiving private signals from a set of small but positive measure. A “regular” equilibrium also exists, close to the unique equilibrium that occurs when there is no desire to conform. These equilibria can be Pareto ranked, however, under a certain restriction on the prior distribution of candidates, the regular equilibrium is the Pareto superior equilibrium, provided the voting occurs under a simple or a super-majority rule. Nonetheless, in this equilibrium, the desire to conform causes the committee to increase the minimum acceptable standard of a candidate for the search to stop, and increases the expected search duration.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Subscribe and save

Springer+ Basic
$34.99 /Month
  • Get 10 units per month
  • Download Article/Chapter or eBook
  • 1 Unit = 1 Article or 1 Chapter
  • Cancel anytime
Subscribe now

Buy Now

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2
Fig. 3
Fig. 4

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. The “need to belong or conform” is more than just casual empiricism. Years on from the well-known Asch experiments from the 1950s, the “belongingness theory of motivation”, pioneered by Baumeister and Leary (1995), is a key area of basic research in Social Psychology with important clinical applications. It also has interdisciplinary influences that range from applied Management Science to Sociology. Although the human need to form interpersonal contacts is asserted at least since Freud, the most widely cited hierarchy of human needs is due to Abraham Maslow (See Maslow (1943) and Maslow (1968)). In this, “love and belongingness” needs rank in the middle of the hierarchy. Baumeister and Leary (1995) are the first to provide systematic empirical validation of this speculative ranking. See also Ryan and Deci (2000) and the references therein. Although Maslow’s original hierarchy has seen several revisions, it continues to be important in popular media and among management gurus. See for example “Abraham Maslow and the pyramid that beguiled business”BBC news magazine, William Kremer; Hammond, Claudia (31 August 2013) or the TED talk “Measuring what makes life worthwhile” by Chip Conley, hotelier and Airbnb head of hospitality. There is also some recent neurobiological evidence that vindicates the emotional need to belong. See for example Dunbar (2006), Eisenberger et al. (2003) and Eisenberger and Cole (2012).

  2. There is a considerable literature on strategic voting in committees. Some of the more prominent ones, all with common-value or correlated information structure, include.

  3. One may modify the model so that a member receives \(\alpha _a\) if her vote matches the committee’s decision and receives \(\alpha _r\) otherwise. The analysis to follow may be seen to be immune to such a modification provided \(\alpha _a > \alpha _r\) by setting \(\alpha := \alpha _a - \alpha _r\), i.e. \(\alpha\) is the net benefit of being accepted.

  4. As stated in Albrecht et al. (2010), in the single-agent search, the Markovian assumption is without loss of generality. However, search by committee is a game and non-stationary strategies can potentially be supported as equilibria. In the current context, since our results concern the introduction of multiplicity to even the set of interior Markov equilibria, consideration of non-stationary equilibrium is arguably unimportant.

  5. Given \(z\in [0,1]\), for any realization of values \({\textbf{x}} = (x_1, \ldots , x_n)\), define \(Y_z ({\textbf{x}}) = {\# \{ i \mid x_i \ge z \}}/{N}\). AAV show that \(\omega (z) = E [ Y_z ({\textbf{x}}) \mid Y_z ({\textbf{x}}) \ge \frac{M}{N} ]\), i.e., in a symmetric Markov strategy with MAT equal z, \(\omega (z)\) is the expected fraction of agents that vote for the search to stop is at least M/N.

  6. Unlike for the case of \(M<N\), when \(M=N\), the \(\lim _{z\rightarrow 0}x(\alpha ,z) = x_0(0)+\alpha\) for any \(\alpha >0\). \(\lim _{z\rightarrow 1}x(\alpha ,z)=\infty\) continues to hold.

References

  • Albrecht J, Anderson A, Vroman S (2010) Search by committee. J Econ Theory 145(4):1386–1407

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Austen-Smith D, Banks JS (1996) Information aggregation, rationality, and the condorcet jury theorem. Am Polit Sci Rev 90(1):34–45

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baumeister RF, Leary MR (1995) The need to belong: desire for interpersonal attachments as a fundamental human motivation. Psychol Bull 117(3):497–529

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bernheim DB (1994) A theory of conformity. J Polit Econ 102(5):841–77

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bikhchandani S, Hirshleifer D, Welch I (1998) Learning from the behavior of others: conformity, fads, and informational cascades. J Econ Perspect 12(3):151–170

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Callander S (2007) Bandwagons and momentum in sequential voting. Rev Econ Stud 74(3):653–684

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Callander S (2008) Majority rule when voters like to win. Games Econ Behav 64(2):393–420

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chan J, Lizzeri A, Suen W, Yariv L (2018) Deliberating collective decisions. Rev Econ Stud 85(2):929–963. https://doi.org/10.1093/restud/rdx028

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Compte O, Jehiel P (2010) Bargaining and majority rules: a collective search perspective. J Polit Econ 118(2):189–221

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dunbar R (2006) We believe. New Sci 2536(4):30–33

    Google Scholar 

  • Eisenberger NI, Cole SW (2012) Social neuroscience and health: neurophysiological mechanisms linking social ties with physical health. Nat Neurosci 15:669–674. https://doi.org/10.1038/nn.3086

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Eisenberger NI, Lieberman MD, Williams KD (2003) Does rejection hurt? An fmri study of social exclusion. Science 302(5643):290–292

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Feddersen T, Pesendorfer W (1998) Convicting the innocent: the inferiority of unanimous jury verdicts under strategic voting. Am Polit Sci Rev 92(1):23–35

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Glazer J, Rubinstein A (1998) Motives and implementation: on the design of mechanisms to elicit opinions. J Econ Theory 79(2):157–173

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hinich M (1982) Voting as an act of contribution. Public Choice 36:135–138

    Google Scholar 

  • Levy G (2007) Decision making in committees: transparency, reputation and voting rules. Am Econ Rev 97(1):150–168

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lindbeck A (1997) Incentives and social norms in household behavior. Am Econ Rev 87(2):370–77

    Google Scholar 

  • Maslow AH (1943) A theory of human motivation. Psychol Rev 50:370–396

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maslow AH (1968) Toward a psychology of being. Van Nostrand, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Moldovanu B, Shi X (2013) Specialization and partisanship in committee search. Theor Econ 8(3):751–774

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ottaviani M, Sorensen P (2001) Information aggregation in debate: who should speak first? J Public Econ 81(3):393–421

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Persico N (2004) Committee design with endogenous information. Rev Econ Stud 71(1):165–191

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ryan RM, Deci EL (2000) Self-determination theory and the facilitation of intrinsic motivation, social development, and well-being. Am Psychol 55(1):68

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Jorge Rojas-Vallejos.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Appendix

Appendix

In the following, IVT stands for the “Intermediate Value Theorem”.

Proof

(Lemma 3) We know from AAV that \(x_0\) is continuous. It is easy to see that \(\psi\) is non-negative. It is also bounded, since its denominator takes values in \((1 - \delta , 1)\) and the numerator takes values in [0, 1]. It is clearly continuous. Next, observe that the numerator of \(\varphi (z)\) converges to \(- 1\) and 1 as z converges to 0 and 1 respectively. Using the fact that \(\lim _{z \rightarrow 0} p (z, k, n) = \lim _{z \rightarrow 1} p (z, k, n) = 0\), provided \(k \ne n\), we readily conclude that \(\lim _{z \rightarrow 0} \varphi (z) = - \infty\) and \(\lim _{z \rightarrow 1} \varphi (z) = \infty\). Since \(x (z, \alpha )\) is linear in \(\alpha\), and is the sum of continuous functions, the various assertions in the proposition for the case where \(M\ne N\) now follow readily. \(\square\)

Proof

(Proposition 1.) We first prove Part 2. Choose \(\varepsilon > 0\) sufficiently small so that \(2 \varepsilon< y^{*} < 1 - 2 \varepsilon\). Define,

$$\begin{aligned} \delta= & {} \inf \{ | x_0 (z) - z |: z \in [\varepsilon , y^{*} - \varepsilon ] \cup [y^{*} + \varepsilon , 1 - \varepsilon ] \}. \end{aligned}$$

\(\delta > 0\), since we know from Proposition 0 that \(y^{*}\) is the unique fixed point of \(x_0 (\cdot )\). Next, observe that \(x (z, \alpha )\) converges pointwise to \(x_0 (z)\) for all z in the compact interval \([\varepsilon , 1 - \varepsilon ]\). From Lemma 1, we know that \(x (z, \alpha )\) is jointly continuous in both its arguments for \((z, \alpha ) \in (0, 1) \times [0, \infty )\). Hence, we can find \(\alpha _{\varepsilon } > 0\) such that,

$$\begin{aligned} | x (z, \alpha ) - x_0 (z) | < \delta / 2 \forall z \in [\varepsilon , 1 - \varepsilon ] {\text { and }} \forall \alpha \in (0, \alpha _{\varepsilon }). \end{aligned}$$
(16)

From Proposition 0, \(x_0 (z) > z\) for \(z \in [\varepsilon , y^{*} - \varepsilon ]\) which gives,

$$\begin{aligned} x (z, \alpha ) - z > x_0 (z) - z - \delta / 2 \ge \delta / 2 \forall z \in [\varepsilon , y^{*} - \varepsilon ] \end{aligned}$$

and that \(x_0 (z) < z\) for \(z \in [y^{*} + \varepsilon , \varepsilon ]\), which gives,

$$\begin{aligned} x (z, \alpha ) - z < x_0 (z) - z + \delta / 2 \, \le - \delta / 2 \forall z \in [y^{*} + \varepsilon , 1 - \varepsilon ] \end{aligned}$$

Therefore, fixed points of \(x (\cdot , \alpha )\), if they exist, can occur only in the regions \([0, \varepsilon )\), \((y^{*} - \varepsilon , y^{*} + \varepsilon )\) or \((1 - \varepsilon , 1]\). This proves Part 2.

Next, we turn to Part 1. From Lemma 3, we know that \(\lim _{z \rightarrow 0} \, x (z, \alpha ) = - \infty\) and \(\lim _{z \rightarrow 1} \, x (z, \alpha ) = \infty\). This, together with the foregoing conclusions concerning \(x (z, \alpha )\) allow us to conclude the following regarding the graph of \(x (z, \alpha )\): it begins from below the 45 degree line when z is close to zero, is above it in the region \([\varepsilon , y^{*} - \varepsilon ]\), is below it in the region \([y^{*} + \varepsilon , 1 - \varepsilon ]\) and again above it for z close enough to 1. Appealing to the continuity of \(x (\cdot , \alpha )\) and applying the IVT, it follows that \(x (\cdot , \alpha )\) intersects the 45 degree line at least once in each of the regions \((0, \varepsilon )\), \((y^{*} - \varepsilon , y^{*} + \varepsilon )\) and \((\varepsilon , 1 - \varepsilon )\), and only on those regions. Each of these points of intersection in the respective regions constitute the acceptance thresholds for a left conformal equilibrium, a regular equilibrium or a right conformal equilibrium. This completes the proof of Part 1. \(\square\)

Proof

(Lemma 2) Part 1. \(\delta \mu > y^{*}\) is given. Set \(\beta = (\delta \mu - y^{*}) / 2 \delta\). Note that \(V_0 (0) - V_0 (y^{*}) = (\mu - y^{*} / \delta ) = 2 \beta > 0\) and \(V_0 (0) - V_0 (1) = \mu> 2 \beta > 0\). Since \(V_0 (z)\) is uniformly continuous in z in the compact interval [0, 1], there exists \({\hat{\varepsilon }} > 0\) such that

$$\begin{aligned} V_0 (z) - V_0 (z')> & {} \beta \qquad \forall z \in (0, {\hat{\varepsilon }}) \text {and } z' \in (y^{*} - {\hat{\varepsilon }}, y^{*} + {\hat{\varepsilon }}). \\ V_0 (z) - V_0 (z')> & {} \beta \qquad \forall z \in (0, {\hat{\varepsilon }}) \text {and } z' \in (1 - {\hat{\varepsilon }}, 1). \end{aligned}$$

Set \({\hat{\alpha }} = \beta (1 - \delta ) / 2\). Then, \(\forall z \in (0, {\hat{\varepsilon }}) \text {and } z' \in (y^{*} - {\hat{\varepsilon }}, y^{*} + {\hat{\varepsilon }}) \cup (1 - {\hat{\varepsilon }}, 1)\)

$$\begin{aligned} V (z, \alpha ) - V (z', \alpha )= & {} V_0 (z) - V_0 (z') + \alpha (\psi (z) - \psi (z')) \\{} & {} > \beta + \alpha (\psi (z) - \psi (z')) > 0 \end{aligned}$$

where the last inequality is due to the fact that \(\psi (\cdot )\) is non-negative and bounded above by \(1 / (1 - \delta )\) on [0, 1]. Therefore, for all \(\alpha \in (0, {\hat{\alpha }})\),

$$\begin{aligned} V (z, \alpha ) - V (z', \alpha )= & {} V_0 (z) - V_0 (z') + \alpha (\psi (z) - \psi (z'))\\{} & {} \quad > 0 \qquad \forall z \in (0, {\hat{\varepsilon }}) \text {and } z' \in (y^{*} - {\hat{\varepsilon }}, y^{*} + {\hat{\varepsilon }}) \cup (1 - {\hat{\varepsilon }}, 1). \end{aligned}$$

Now, select \(\varepsilon < {\hat{\varepsilon }}\), let \(\alpha _{\varepsilon }\) be as in Proposition 1 and set \(\alpha ^{*} = \min \{ {\hat{\alpha }}, \alpha _{\varepsilon } \}\). By Proposition 1 then, for all \(\alpha \in (0, \alpha ^{*})\), only \(\varepsilon\)-left, \(\varepsilon\)-right conformal equilibria and \(\varepsilon\)-regular equilibria exist, and from the above, the Pareto Superior equilibrium must be the \(\varepsilon\)-left conformal equilibrium.

Part 2. \(y^{*} > \delta \mu\) is given. Set \(\beta = (y^{*} - \delta \mu ) / 2 \delta\). Observe that \(V_0 (y^{*}) - V_0 (0) = (y^{*} / \delta - \mu ) = 2 \beta > 0\) and \(V_0 (y^{*}) - V_0 (1) = y^{*} / \delta> 2 \beta > 0\). An anlogous argument to the one provided above for Part 1 can be used to complete the proof. \(\square\)

Proof

(Lemma 3) Recall that \(\lim _{z\rightarrow 0}\varphi (z)=-\infty\) and \(\lim _{z\rightarrow 1}\varphi (z)=\infty\). \(\varphi (z)\) is also continuous in z. The proof of the lemma, including the existence of a unique \({\bar{y}}\) defined in (15) is complete upon verifying that \(\varphi (z)\) is increasing.

$$\begin{aligned} \frac{p (z, k, N - 1)}{p (z, M - 1, N - 1)}= & {} \frac{\left( {\begin{array}{c}N - 1\\ k\end{array}}\right) }{\left( {\begin{array}{c}N - 1\\ M - 1\end{array}}\right) } \frac{F (z)^{N - 1 - k} (1 - F (z))^k}{F (z)^{N - M} (1 - F (z))^{M - 1}} \\= & {} \frac{\left( {\begin{array}{c}N - 1\\ k\end{array}}\right) }{\left( {\begin{array}{c}N - 1\\ M - 1\end{array}}\right) } \left( \frac{F (z)}{1 - F (z)} \right) ^{(M - 1) - k} \\= & {} \lambda (k)\theta (z)^{M-1-k}, \end{aligned}$$

where we have set \(\lambda (k) = {\left( {\begin{array}{c}N - 1\\ k\end{array}}\right) }/{\left( {\begin{array}{c}N - 1\\ M - 1\end{array}}\right) }\) and \(\theta (z) = {F (z)}/{1 - F (z)}\). Next, note that \(\varphi (z)\) is a polynomial in \(\theta (z)\) with \(\lambda (k)\)’s as coefficients:

$$\begin{aligned} \varphi (z)= & {} \frac{P (z, M, N - 1) - Q (z, M - 1, N - 1)}{p (z, M - 1, N - 1)} \\= & {} \sum _{j = 0}^{M - 1} \frac{p (z, j, N - 1)}{p (z, M - 1, N - 1)} - \sum _{j = M - 1}^{N - 1} \frac{p (z, j, N - 1)}{p (z, M - 1, N - 1)} \\= & {} \sum _{j = 0}^{M - 1} \lambda (j) \theta (z)^{M - 1 - j} + \sum _{j = M - 1}^{N - 1} (-\lambda (j)) \theta (z)^{M - 1 - j} \\= & {} \sum _{j = 0}^{M - 2} \lambda (j) \theta (z)^{M - 1 - j} + \sum _{j = M }^{N - 1} (-\lambda (j)) \theta (z)^{M - 1 - j} \end{aligned}$$

Clearly \(\theta (z)^{M-1-j}\) is increasing in z when \(j< M-1\) but is decreasing when \(j> M-1\), since \(\theta (z)\) is itself increasing in z. Given \(\lambda (j)>0\) for all \(j=0,\ldots ,N-1\), it is now clear that \(\varphi (z)\) is also increasing in z. \(\square\)

Proof

(Proposition 2) Part 1. Let \(\alpha ^{*}\) be as in Lemma 2. The \(\varepsilon\)-left equilibrium is Pareto superior with a MAT \(y_{\alpha } \in (0, \varepsilon )\) and hence \(y_{\alpha } < y^{*}\) for all \(\alpha \in (0, \alpha ^{*})\). So the expected search duration decreases.

We recall that establish (17) and the Claim prior to (15). Recall \(\psi (y) \ge 0\) for all \(y\in [0,1]\), and from Lemma 3 that \(\varphi (y)\) is increasing in y. Hence,

$$\begin{aligned} y> {\bar{y}} \Rightarrow&\varphi (y) + \psi (y) > 0 \end{aligned}$$
(17)

Again let \(\alpha ^{*}\) be as in Lemma 2 so that MAT of Pareto superior equilibrium \(y_{\alpha } \in (y^{*} - \varepsilon , y^{*} + \varepsilon )\). As \({\bar{y}} < y^{*}\), we may assume that \(\varepsilon\) (or equivalently \(\alpha ^{*}\)) was chosen to be small enough so that \({\bar{y}} < y_\alpha\). Therefore, from (17) above, \(\varphi (y_{\alpha }) + \psi (y_{\alpha }) > 0\). Moreover, since \(y_{\alpha }\) is an equilibrium MAT of \({\mathcal {G}} (\alpha , M, N)\), we have \(0 = x (y_{\alpha }, \alpha ) - y_{\alpha } = (x_0 (y_{\alpha }) - y_{\alpha }) + \alpha (\varphi (y_{\alpha }) + \psi (y_{\alpha }))\), we must have \(x_0 (y_{\alpha }) < y_{\alpha }\), which in turn, by Part 2, Lemma 1, implies \(y_{\alpha } > y^{*}\). Hence the expected search duration increases. \(\square\)

Proof

(Corollary 1) By assumption the plurality rule is a super-majority rule, i.e. \(M-2 \ge N-1-M\). Noting that \(\theta (\nu )=1\) and \(\lambda (j) = \lambda (N-1-j)\), we have

$$\begin{aligned} \varphi (\nu )= & {} \sum _{j = 0}^{M - 2} \lambda (j) - \sum _{j = M }^{N - 1} \lambda (j) \nonumber \\= & {} \sum _{j = 0}^{M - 2} \lambda (j) - \sum _{j = 0 }^{N - 1-M} \lambda (N-1-j) \; \; = \; \sum _{j = N-M}^{M - 2} \lambda (j) \; \ge 0 \end{aligned}$$
(18)

This gives \(\nu \ge {\bar{y}}\) the Claim preceding (15). Now apply Part 2, Proposition 2\(\square\)

Proof

Lemma 4. Let \(y_1 < y^{*}\). By Proposition 0, part 2, \(x_0 (y_1) > y_1\). From eq (14),

$$\begin{aligned} \alpha _1 (\varphi (y_1) + \psi (y_1))= & {} x (y_1, \alpha _1) - x_0 (y_1) \\= & {} y_1 - x_0 (y_1), \qquad \text { since }y_1\text { is a MAT of }{\mathcal {G}} (\alpha _1, M, N) \\< & {} 0. \end{aligned}$$

Hence \(x (y_1, \alpha _2) > x (y_1, \alpha _1) = y_1\). Since \(\lim _{y \rightarrow 0} x (y, \alpha _2) = - \infty\), there exists \(y' < y_1\) such that \(x (y', \alpha _2) < y'\). By IVT, we can find a \(y_2 < y_1\) such that \(x (y_2, \alpha _2) = y_2\). A similar argument proves the case where \(y_1 > y^{*}\)\(\square\) \(\square\)

Proof

(Proposition 3) Since Q(zMN) is continuously decreasing in z with \(\lim _{z \rightarrow 0} Q (z, M, N) = 1\) and \(\lim _{z \rightarrow 0} Q (1 - z, M, N) = 0\), there exists \({\hat{\varepsilon }} > 0\) and \({\hat{q}} > 0\) such that

$$\begin{aligned} Q ({\hat{\varepsilon }}, M, N)> \, {\hat{q}} \, > Q (1 - {\hat{\varepsilon }}, M', N) \quad \forall M, M'\ne 0. \end{aligned}$$

By Proposition 1, there exists \(\alpha _{{\hat{\varepsilon }}} (M)\) sufficiently small such that both \({\hat{\varepsilon }}\)-left and \({\hat{\varepsilon }}\)-right exist in \({\mathcal {G}} (\alpha , M, N)\) for all \(\alpha \in (0, \alpha _{{\hat{\varepsilon }}} (M))\). Set \(\alpha ^{*} = \min _M \alpha _{{\hat{\varepsilon }}} (M)\) and appeal to Lemma 4 above to conclude that for all \(\alpha \in (0, \alpha ^{*})\), an \({\hat{\varepsilon }}\)-left conformal equilibrium and an \({\hat{\varepsilon }}\)-right conformal equilibruim exist for all \(M\ne 0\).

Choose any \(\alpha \in (0, \alpha ^{*})\). Pick an \({\hat{\varepsilon }}\)-left conformal equilibrium MAT, say y, of \({\mathcal {G}} (\alpha , M, N)\). Then, \(Q (y, M, N) \ge Q ({\hat{\varepsilon }}, M, N)\) and hence \(\sigma (y, M, N) < 1 / {\hat{q}}\). Likewise, for an \({\hat{\varepsilon }}\)-right conformal equilibrium MAT, say \(y'\), of \({\mathcal {G}} (\alpha , M', N)\), \(Q (y', M', N) \ge Q (1 - {\hat{\varepsilon }}, M', N)\) and hence \(\sigma (y', M', N) > 1 / {\hat{q}}\), which means M does not search-dominate \(M'\). As \(M, M'\) are chosen arbitrarily, this completes the proof.\(\square\)

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor (e.g. a society or other partner) holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Agastya, M., Rojas-Vallejos, J. The “desire to conform” and dynamic search by a committee. Int J Game Theory 52, 737–756 (2023). https://doi.org/10.1007/s00182-023-00838-3

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s00182-023-00838-3

Keywords

JEL classification