
Notes
Risse [11] and Sanver’s informative 2004 Oberwolfach talk describe Brams and Sanver’s claim that the Approval Voting outcomes of any profile must include all possible positional and many other procedures’ outcomes, maybe even the Condorcet loser, where each outcome in this large set of possibilities can be sincere even if undesired! When I proved this fact in 1988 (Saari and Van Newenhizen [26], see Saari [14, 18] for easy ways to construct all possible AV outcomes for a profile) to demonstrate AV’s chaotic indeterminacy, Brams, Fishburn and Merrill [2] disputed my argument, so I welcome this belated agreement. But while each AV outcome can be sincere (or strategic), it is easy to show that the voters need not like the outcome—with AV, they can elect what they do not want. So Risse’s acceptance of this AV multiple outcome property as “a friendly amendment to my argument for the multiplicity thesis” contributes to my worry about the lack of substance attached to his use of “reasonable”.
“Tiny” here involves a one in 17,001 data change, or even a one in 17,000,001 change.
As an example, let k voters prefer ABC, k prefer BAC and k+1 prefer CAB. Even though C is bottom ranked by \(\frac{{2k}}{{3k + 1}} = \frac{2}{3} - \frac{2}{{9k + 3}}\) of the voters, she is the plurality winner.
Because a candidate’s Borda tally can be found by adding the pairwise tallies she receives against everyone else, the Borda count can be used with cyclic preferences and it cancels them leaving a tie. Sieberg and I [25] used this point to analyze engineering decisions where cyclic data do arise.
References
Arrow K (1951) (2nd ed 1963), Social choice and individual values. Wiley, New York
Brams S, Fishburn P, Merrill S (1988) The responsiveness of approval voting: comments on Saari and Van Newenhizen. Public Choice 59:121–131
Fishburn P (1981) Inverted orders for monotone scoring rules. Discrete Appl Math 3:27–36
Gibbard A (1973) Manipulation of voting schemes: a general result. Econometrica 41:587–601
Kemeny J (1959) Mathematics without numbers. Daedalus 88:571–591
Merlin V, Saari DG (2000) Changes that cause changes. Soc Choice Welf 17:691–705
Nurmi H (1999) Voting paradoxes and how to deal with them. Springer
Nurmi H (2002) Voting procedures under uncertainty. Springer, Berlin Heidelberg New York
Ratliff T (2004) Presentation at a Oberwolfach, Germany, conference
Risse M (2001) Arrow’s theorem, indeterminacy, and multiplicity reconsidered. Ethics 111:706–734
Risse M (2004) Why the Count de Borda cannot beat the Marquis de Condorcet, Social Choice and Welfare, this issue
Saari DG (1989) A dictionary for voting paradoxes. J Econ Theory 48:443–475
Saari DG (1990) Susceptibility to manipulation. Public Choice 64:21–41
Saari DG (1994) Geometry of voting. Springer, Berlin Heidelberg New York
Saari DG (1995) A chaotic exploration of aggregation paradoxes. SIAM Rev 37:37–52
Saari DG (1999) Explaining all three-alternative voting outcomes. J Econ Theory 87:313–355
Saari DG (2000) Mathematical structure of voting paradoxes. Econom Theory 15:1–101
Saari DG (2001) Chaotic elections! A mathematician looks at voting, American Mathematical Society, Providence, R.I.
Saari DG (2001) Decisions and elections: explaining the unexpected, Cambridge University Press, New York
Saari DG (2002) Adopting a plurality vote perspective. Math Oper Res 27:45–64
Saari DG (2003) Capturing the ‘will of the people.’ Ethics 113:333–334
Saari DG (2003) Disturbing aspects of voting theory. Econ Theory 22:529–556
Saari DG, Merlin V (2000) A geometric examination of Kemeny’s rule. Soc Choice Welf 17:403–438
Saari DG, Sieberg K (2001) The sum of the parts can violate the whole. Am Polit Sci Rev 95:415–430
Saari DG, Sieberg K (2004) Are part wise comparisons reliable? Res Eng Des 15:62–71
Saari DG, Van Newenhizen J (1988) Is approval voting an “unmitigated evil?” Public Choice 59:133–147
Satterthwaite M (1975) Strategy proofness and Arrow’s conditions. J Econ Theory 10:187–217
Sen A (1970) Collective choice and social welfare. Holden Day, San Francisco
Author information
Authors and Affiliations
Corresponding author
Additional information
This research was supported by an NSF DMI grant. While this paper addresses Risse’s [11] paper, it is based on my 3/10/04 presentation at a 2004 Oberwolfach meeting on the design of electoral systems. My thanks to the organizers M. Balinski, S. Brams, and F. Pukelsheim
Rights and permissions
About this article
Cite this article
Saari, D.G. Which is better: the Condorcet or Borda winner?. Soc Choice Welfare 26, 107–129 (2006). https://doi.org/10.1007/s00355-005-0046-2
Received:
Accepted:
Published:
Issue Date:
DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s00355-005-0046-2