Skip to main content
Log in

Generalized rawlsianism

  • Original Paper
  • Published:
Social Choice and Welfare Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This paper proposes and characterizes a family of social choice rules, including maximin and leximin, by considering only ordinal social choice in the sense that individual utilities are ordinally measurable and ordinally comparable. This family of rules, called generalized Rawlsianism, provides a unified approach for dealing with different informational constraints on ordinal interpersonal comparisons. Rank noncomparability, which states that individual utilities under the same social ranking should always be interpersonally noncomparable, is then proposed as a new basic invariance axiom. We show that a social welfare ordering with super domain is a generalized rank hierarchy if and only if it satisfies anonymity, nonnullity, full rank noncomparability, and the Pareto monotonicity principle; together with the Pigou–Dalton principle, generalized Rawlsianism can then be fully characterized. Our characterizations depend heavily on the result that a social welfare ordering with super domain is a generalized hierarchy if and only if it satisfies nonnullity, interpersonal noncomparability, and the Pareto monotonicity principle.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. In A Theory of Justice (1999, revised edition, p. 79), Rawls argued as follows:

    “The indifference principle tries to establish objective grounds for interpersonal comparisons \(\cdots \) as long as we can identify the least advantaged representative man, only ordinal judgements of wellbeing are required from then on \(\cdots \) It does not matter how much worse off this representative individual is than the others. The further difficulties of cardinal measurement do not arise since no other interpersonal comparisons are necessary.”

  2. In Theorem 1, if Pareto monotonicity is weakened into Pareto indifference, then inverse dictatorship is allowed. With similar arguments as in the proof of Theorem 1, it is easy to show that a social welfare function with full domain satisfies nonnullity and strong neutrality if and only if for some positive integer kin N, there is a injection \(\pi : \{1, 2, \ldots , k\} \cdots N\) such that \(\pi \)(1) is a strong (inverse) dictator; or \(\pi \)(1) is a weak (inverse) dictator, and \(\pi \)(2) is a strong (inverse) dictator whenever \(\pi \)(1) is indifferent; \(\cdots \); or \(\pi \)(1) is a weak (inverse) dictator, \(\pi \)(2) is a weak (inverse) dictator whenever \(\pi \)(1) is indifferent, \(\ldots \), \(\pi (k-1)\) is a weak (inverse) dictator whenever \(\pi \)(1), \(\ldots \), \(\pi (k-2)\) are indifferent, and \(\pi (k)\) is a strong (inverse) dictator whenever \(\pi (1), \ldots , \pi (k-1)\) are indifferent.

References

  • Aleskerov FT (1999) Arrovian aggregation models. Kluwer Academic Publishers, Boston

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Aleskerov FT, Vladimirov AV (1986) Hierarchical voting. Inf Sci 39:41–86

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Arrow KJ (1951, 1963) Social choice and individual values. Wiley, New York

  • Barberá S (1983) Pivotal voters: a new proof of Arrow’s theorem. Econ Lett 6:13–16

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barberá S, Sonnenschein H (1978) Preference aggregation with randomized social orderings. J Econ Theory 18:244–254

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Birkhoff G (1948) Lattice theory, vol XXV. American Mathematical Society Publications, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Blau JH (1972) A direct proof of the Arrow theorem. Econometrica 40:61–67

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Blau JH (1976) Neutrality, monotonicity and the right of veto: a comment. Econometrica 44:603

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Blackorby C, Donaldson D, Weymark JA (1990) A welfarist proof of Arrow’s theorem. Rech Econom de Louvain 56:259–286

    Google Scholar 

  • Bossert W, Weymark JA (2004) Utility in social choice. In: Barberà S, Hammond PJ, Seidl C (eds) Handbook of utility theory, vol 2. Springer, New York, pp 1099–1177

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Campbell DE, Kelly JS (2002) Impossibility theorems in the Arrovian framework. In: Arrow KJ, Sen AK, Suzumura K (eds) Handbook of social choice and welfare, vol 1. Elsevier, North Holland, pp 35–94

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Cato S (2010) Brief proofs of Arrovian impossibility theorems. Soc Choice Welf 35:267–284

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dardanoni V (2001) A pedagogical proof of Arrow’s impossibility theorem. Soc Choice Welf 18:107–112

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • D’Aspremont C (1985) Axioms for social welfare orderings. In: Hurwicz L, Schmeidler D, Sonnenschein H (eds) Social goals and social organization: essays in memory of Elisha Pazner. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 19–76

    Google Scholar 

  • D’Aspremont C, Gevers L (1977) Equity and the informational basis of collective choice. Rev Econ Stud 44:199–209

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • D’Aspremont C, Gevers L (2002) Social welfare functionals and interpersonal comparability. In: Arrow KJ, Sen AK, Suzumura K (eds) Handbook of social choice and welfare, vol 1. Elsevier, North Holland, pp 459–541

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Denicolò V (1996) An elementary proof of Arrow’s impossibility theorem. Jpn Econ Rev 47:432–435

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Denicolò V (2001) An elementary proof of Arrow’s impossibility theorem: correction. Jpn Econ Rev 52:134–135

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Feldman AM, Serrano R (2006) Welfare economics and social choice theory. Springer, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Fishburn PC (1970) Arrow’s impossibility theorem: concise proof and infinite voters. J Econ Theory 2:103–106

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fishburn PC (1975) Axioms for lexicographic preferences. Rev Econ Stud 42:415–419

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fleurbaey M, Mongin P (2005) The news of the death of welfare economics is greatly exaggerated. Soc Choice Welf 25:381–418

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Geanakoplos J (2005) Three brief proofs of Arrow’s impossibility theorem. Econ Theory 26:211–215

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gevers L (1979) On interpersonal comparability and social welfare orderings. Econometrica 47:75–89

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Guha AS (1972) Neutrality, monotonicity and the right of veto. Econometrica 40:821–826

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hammond PJ (1976) Equity, Arrow’s conditions, and Rawls’ difference principle. Econometrica 44:793–804

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hausner M, Wendel JG (1952) Ordered vector spaces. Proc Am Math Soc 3:977–982

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Krause U (1995) Essentially lexicographic aggregation. Soc Choice Welf 12:233–244

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Luce RD, Raiffa H (1957) Games and decisions. Wiley, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • McLennan A (1980) Randomized preference aggregation: additivity of power and strategy proofness. J Econ Theory 12:1–11

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ou-Yang K (2015) A complete characterization of hierarchy. Econ Lett 136:162–164

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ou-Yang K (2016) Rawls’s maximin rule and Arrow’s impossibility theorem. Econ Lett 145:114–116

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pouzet M (1998) A projection property and Arrow’s impossibility theorem. Discret Math 192:293–308

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rawls J (1971, 1999) A theory of justice. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

  • Reny PJ (2001) Arrow’s theorem and the Gibbard–Satterthwaite theorem: a unified approach. Econ Lett 70:99–105

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Roberts KWS (1980) Social choice theory: single-profile and multi-profile approaches. Rev Econ Stud 47:441–450

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rubinstein A, Fishburn PC (1986) Algebraic aggregation theory. J Econ Theory 38:63–77

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Saari DG (1994) Geometry of voting. Springer, Berlin

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sen AK (1970) Collective choice and social welfare. Holden-Day, San Francisco

    Google Scholar 

  • Sen AK (1977) On weight and measures: informational constraints in social welfare analysis. Econometrica 45:1539–1572

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sen AK (1986) Social choice theory. In: Arrow KJ, Intrilligator MD (eds) Handbook of mathematical economics, vol III. North-Holland, Amsterdam, pp 1073–1181

    Google Scholar 

  • Suzumura K (1988) Reduction of social choice problems: a simple proof of Arrow’s general possibility theorem. Hitotsubashi J Econ 19:219–221

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilson RB (1972) Social choice without the Pareto principle. J Econ Theory 5:14–20

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wilson RB (1975) On the theory of aggregation. J Econ Theory 10:89–99

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Yu NN (2012) A one-shot proof of Arrow’s impossibility theorem. Econ Theory 50:523–525

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I am very grateful for helpful suggestions received from the editors and the anonymous referees. Financial supports from the Science Foundation of Education Department of Shaanxi (2013JK139) and the Key Research Foundation of Humanities and Social Sciences of the Ministry of Education of China (16JJD790046) are gratefully acknowledged.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Kui Ou-Yang.

Appendix A: Proofs

Appendix A: Proofs

1.1 Proof of Theorem 1

Necessity is obvious, and we only prove sufficiency. Suppose that \(W:\mathcal {O} (X)^{N }\rightarrow \mathcal {O} (X)\) satisfies IIA, nonnullity, and the Pareto monotonicity principle. Note that the Pareto monotonicity principle implies the Pareto indifference principle, and thus by the strong neutrality theorem, strong neutrality must be satisfied. By Wilson’s independence theorem and the Pareto monotonicity principle, it must be weakly dictatorial. This dictator can be denoted by \(\pi \)(1).

Then consider a social welfare function \(W_{1}: \mathcal {O}(X)^{N\backslash \{\pi (1)\} }\rightarrow \mathcal {O}(X)\) for the society \(N \backslash \{ \pi (1)\}\) such that for all \({{\varvec{R}}} \in \mathcal {O}(X)^{N}\) and for all \(x, y \in X\), if \(x \sim _{R_{\pi \left( 1 \right) } } y\), then\( W_{1}({{\varvec{R}}}_{N\backslash \{\pi (1)\}})(x, y)=W(R_{\pi (1)}, {{\varvec{R}}}_{N\backslash \{\pi (1)\}})(x, y)=W({{\varvec{R}}})(x, y)\). It is easy to check that this social welfare function \(W_{1}\) is well defined and satisfies IIA and the Pareto monotonicity principle. If \(W_{1}\) is null, then \(\pi \)(1) must be a strong dictator in the society N. If \(W_{1}\) is nonnull, then again by Wilson’s theorem and the Pareto monotonicity principle, there must be a weak dictator in the society \(N \backslash \{\pi (1)\}\), which can be denoted by \(\pi \)(2).

Similarly, for each \(k \in \) {1, \(\ldots , n\)-2}, we can define a social welfare function \(W_{k}: \mathcal {O}(X)^{N\backslash \{\pi (1), \ldots , \pi (k)\} }\rightarrow \mathcal {O}(X)\) for the society \(N \backslash \) { \(\pi \)(1), \(\ldots \), \(\pi (k)\}\) such that for all R \(\in \mathcal {O}(X)^{N}\) and for all \(x, y \in X\), if \(x \sim _{R_{\pi \left( 1 \right) } } y, \ldots , x \sim _{R_{\pi \left( k \right) } } y\), then \(W_{k}({{\varvec{R}}}_{N\backslash \{\pi (1), \ldots , \pi (k)\}})(x, y)=W({{\varvec{R}}}_{\{\pi (1), \ldots , \pi (k)\}}\), \({{\varvec{R}}}_{N\backslash \{\pi (1), \ldots , \pi (k)\}})(x, y)=W({{\varvec{R}}})(x, y)\). It is easy to check that this social welfare function \(W_{k}\) is well defined and satisfies IIA and the Pareto monotonicity principle. If \(W_{k}\) is null, then \(\pi (k)\) must be a strong dictator in the society \(N \backslash \{ \pi (1), \ldots , \pi (k-1)\}\). If \(W_{k}\) is nonnull, then again by Wilson’s theorem and the Pareto monotonicity principle, there must be a weak dictator in the society \(N \backslash \{ \pi (1), \ldots , \pi (k)\}\), which can be denoted by \(\pi (k+1)\).

Finally, if \(k=n \)- 2, then \(\pi (n-1)\) is a weak dictator in the society \(N \backslash \{ \pi (1), \ldots \), \(\pi (n-2)\}\), and let \(\pi \)(n) be the single member in \(N \backslash \{ \pi (1), \ldots , \pi (n-1)\}\). For all R \(\in \mathcal {O}(X)^{N}\) and for all \(x, y \in X\), if \(x \sim _{R_{\pi \left( 1 \right) } } y, \ldots , x \sim _{R_{\pi \left( {n-1} \right) } } y\), and \(x \succ _{R_{\pi \left( n \right) } } y\), then by the Pareto monotonicity principle there are only two cases: (1) \(x \sim _{W(R)} y\); (2) \(x \succ _{W(R)} y\). In the first case, \(\pi \)(n-1) must be a strong dictator in \(N \backslash \) { \(\pi \)(1), \(\ldots \), \(\pi \)(n-2)}; in the second case, \(\pi \)(n) must be a strong dictator in \(N \backslash \) { \(\pi \)(1), \(\ldots \), \(\pi \)(\(n-1\))}. \(\square \)

1.2 Proof of Theorem 2

We only prove sufficiency. Suppose that \( \succsim _{E}\) has a super domain E and satisfies anonymity, nullity, full rank noncomparability, and the Pareto monotonicity principle. Without loss of any generality, suppose \(E_{0} = \{{{\varvec{u}}} \in \mathbb {R}^{N} | u_{1} \le u_{2} \le \cdots \le u_{n}\)} \(\subseteq E\). Then by Corollary 1, \( \succsim _{E}\) must be a generalized hierarchy in \(E_{0}\), and let \(\pi \): {1, 2, \(\ldots , k\)} \(\rightarrow N\) denote the hierarchical injection. For any u, v in E, there must be some r, s in \(E_{0}\) such that \(\forall i \in N, u_{(i)}=r_{i}\) and \(v_{(i)}=s_{i}\). By anonymity, \({{\varvec{u}}} \sim _{E} {{\varvec{r}}}\) and \({{\varvec{v}}} \sim _{E}\, {{\varvec{s}}}\), and hence \({{\varvec{u}}} \succsim _{E} {{\varvec{v}}}\) if and only if r \( \succsim _{E}\) s. By the generalized hierarchy in \(E_{0}, {{\varvec{r}}} \succ _{E}\; {{\varvec{s}}}\) if and only if there is some \(i \in \) {1, 2, \(\ldots , k\)}, \(r_{\pi (i)} > s_{\pi (i)}\), and for all \(j < i, r_{\pi (j)}=s_{\pi (j)}\), which means that u \(\succ _{E}\) v if and only if there is some \(i \in \{1, 2, \ldots , k\}, u_{(\pi (i))} > v_{(\pi (i))}\), and for all \(j < i, u_{(\pi (j))}=v_{(\pi (j))}\). Therefore, let \(K = \{ \pi (1),\pi (2),\ldots ,\pi (k)\}\), and then \( \succsim _{E}\) must be a generalized rank hierarchy. \(\square \)

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Ou-Yang, K. Generalized rawlsianism. Soc Choice Welf 50, 265–279 (2018). https://doi.org/10.1007/s00355-017-1083-3

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s00355-017-1083-3

Navigation