Skip to main content
Log in

The Electoral College, battleground states, and rule-utilitarian voting

  • Original Paper
  • Published:
Social Choice and Welfare Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

We extend the Feddersen and Sandroni (Am Econ Rev 96(4):1271–1282, 2006) voter turnout model to include partisan districts, a battleground district, and an Electoral College. We find that expected voter turnout by a single party is highest in the battleground district, followed by the party’s majority district, which in turn is followed by the party’s minority district. Total turnout is higher in the battleground district than in the partisan districts, but the gap decreases as the level of disagreement in the partisan districts increases. Lastly, turnout in the battleground district decreases as the partisan districts become more competitive.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Subscribe and save

Springer+ Basic
$34.99 /Month
  • Get 10 units per month
  • Download Article/Chapter or eBook
  • 1 Unit = 1 Article or 1 Chapter
  • Cancel anytime
Subscribe now

Buy Now

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2
Fig. 3

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Coate et al. (2008) use the same data and find that the pivotal voter model predicts closer elections than observed.

  2. Faravelli et al. (2015) model a large election in which paternalistic voters care about the margin of victory. Their model also predicts positive turnout in large elections.

  3. Ali and Lin (2013) also extend the work of Feddersen and Sandroni (2006) by considering a model in which some citizens vote because they are ethical, whereas others vote because of social pressure. Additionally, their model allows for candidates to strategically pick their policy platforms. Valasek (2012) extends the model to allow for the policy positions of candidates to be endogenous to voter turnout and for the number of parties to be more than two.

  4. Since there are infinitely many voters, this is equivalent to assuming that the fraction of voters with voting costs below \(c\le \bar{c}\) is \(\frac{c}{\bar{c}}\).

  5. This feature of the model seems to contradict the common belief among citizens that voter turnout is too low. However, group-rule utilitarians may prefer more low-cost individuals to turn out so that a small number of high-cost individuals can abstain. Ghosal and Lockwood (2009) present a model with an optimal level of turnout.

  6. As the Propositions will show, the binding cutoff rules for an interior equilibrium are for the cutoff rules in the battleground and minorities districts to be less than one. Since both cutoffs are increasing in w and decreasing in k it follows that the importance of the election cannot be too high and the level of disagreement cannot be too low.

References

  • Ali SN, Lin C (2013) Why people vote: ethical motives and social incentives. Am Econ J Microecon 5(2):73–98

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Blais A, Achen CH (2010) Taking civic duty seriously: political theory and voter turnout (unpublished manuscript)

  • Cebula RJ (2001) The electoral college and voter participation: evidence on two hypotheses. Atl Econ J 29(3):304–310

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cebula RJ, Meads H (2008) The electoral college system, political party dominance, and voter turnout, with evidence from the 2004 presidential election. Atl Econ J 36:53–64

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Coate S, Conlin M (2004) A group rule-utilitarian approach to voter turnout: theory and evidence. Am Econ Rev 94(5):1476–1504

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Coate S, Conlin M, Moro A (2008) The performance of pivotal-voter models in small-scale elections: evidence from Texas liquor referenda. J Public Econ 92(3):582–596

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Downs A (1957) An economic theory of political action in a democracy. J Political Econ 65(2):135–150

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Faravelli M, Man P, Walsh R (2015) Mandate and paternalism: a theory of large elections. Games Econ Behav 93:1–23

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Feddersen T, Sandroni A (2006) A theory of participation in elections. Am Econ Rev 96(4):1271–1282

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Federal Election Commission, United States (2001) 2000 Official Presidential General Election Results. www.fec.gov/pubrec/2000presgeresults.htm

  • Gelman A, Silver N, Edlin A (2012) What is the probability your vote will make a difference? Econ Inq 50(2):321–326

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ghosal S, Lockwood B (2009) Costly voting when both information and preferences differ: is turnout too high or too low? Soc Choice Welf 33(1):25–50

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Levine DK, Palfrey TR (2007) The paradox of voter participation? A laboratory study. Am Political Sci Rev 101(01):143–158

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lipsitz K (2009) The consequences of battleground and “spectator” state residency for political participation. Political Behav 31(2):187–209

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McDonald MP (2004) Up, up and away! Voter participation in the 2004 presidential election. In: The forum, vol 2

  • Riker WH, Ordeshook PC (1968) A theory of the calculus of voting. Am Political Sci Rev 62(01):25–42

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Valasek JM (2012) Get out the vote: how encouraging voting changes political outcomes. Econ Politics 24(3):346–373

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Martin Saavedra.

Additional information

We are grateful for feedback from Sourav Bhattacharya, Randall Walsh, two anonymous referees, and the Associate Editor. Sohail Kamdar and Emma Marshall provided excellent research assistance. All errors are our own.

Appendices

Appendix A: Solving for the symmetric equilibrium

1.1 Interior solution

We restrict our search to symmetric equilibria in which \(\sigma _1^{1*}=\sigma _2^{2*} =\alpha \), \(\sigma _1^{2*}=\sigma _2^{1*} =\beta \), and \(\sigma _1^{3*}=\sigma _2^{3*}=\gamma \). The CDF for the ratio of two independent standard uniform random variables is

$$\begin{aligned} F(z) = \left\{ \begin{array}{ll} \frac{z}{2} &{} \text {if }z \le 1;\\ 1-\frac{1}{2z} &{} \text {if }z >1.\end{array} \right. \end{aligned}$$

The payoff functions that each party seeks to maximize are \(R_1(\sigma ) = wp(\sigma )-\phi (\sigma )\) and \(R_2(\sigma ) = w(1-p(\sigma ))-\phi (\sigma )\). We can write \(p(\sigma )=p_1p_2 + p_1(1-p_2)p_3+(1-p_1)p_2p_3\), where \(p_1= F\left( \frac{(1-k)\sigma _1^1}{k \sigma _2^1} \right) \), \(p_2 = F\left( \frac{k\sigma _1^2}{(1-k) \sigma _2^2} \right) \), and \(p_3 = F\left( \frac{\sigma _1^3}{\sigma _2^3} \right) \). With respect to the partisan district cutoff rules (\(\sigma _1^1\), \(\sigma _1^2\), \(\sigma _2^1\) and \(\sigma _2^2\)), \(p_3\) is constant and is \(\frac{1}{2}\) in a symmetric equilibrium. This allows the simplification \(p(\sigma )=\frac{1}{2}(p_1+p_2)\) when evaluating the FOCs in the partisan districts. Taking the first order conditions and evaluating at \(\sigma _1^1=\sigma _2^2=\alpha \) and \(\sigma _1^2=\sigma _2^2=\beta \) gives us that

$$\begin{aligned} \frac{\partial {R_1}}{\partial {\sigma _1^1}} = \frac{\partial {R_2}}{\partial {\sigma _2^2}} = \frac{w}{2}\frac{1-k}{k}\frac{1}{\beta }f\Bigg (\frac{1-k}{k}\frac{\alpha }{\beta }\Bigg ) -\frac{1}{2}(1-k)\alpha \end{aligned}$$

and

$$\begin{aligned} \frac{\partial {R_1}}{\partial {\sigma _1^2}} = \frac{\partial {R_2}}{\partial {\sigma _2^1}} = \frac{w}{2}\frac{k}{1-k}\frac{1}{\alpha }f\Bigg (\frac{k}{1-k}\frac{\beta }{\alpha }\Bigg ) -\frac{1}{2}k\beta . \end{aligned}$$

For the third condition we first simplify \(R_1\). Note that the \(p_1\) and \(p_2\) are constant with respect to battleground district cutoffs and \(p_1=1-p_2\) in a symmetric equilibrium. Then, \(p(\sigma )=p_1p_2 +(2p_1^2-2p_1+1)p_3,\) which gives us the last FOC (evaluated at \(\alpha \), \(\beta \), and \(\gamma \)):

$$\begin{aligned} \frac{\partial {R_1}}{\partial {\sigma _1^3}} = \frac{\partial {R_2}}{\partial {\sigma _2^3}} = w\frac{1}{2\gamma }\Bigg (2F^2\Bigg (\frac{1-k}{k}\frac{\alpha }{\beta }\Bigg ) - 2F\Bigg (\frac{1-k}{k}\frac{\alpha }{\beta }\Bigg )+1\Bigg )-\frac{\gamma }{4}. \end{aligned}$$

For \(\frac{1-k}{k}\frac{\alpha }{\beta } >1\), the first two first order conditions are:

$$\begin{aligned} \beta = \frac{(1-k)^2}{k}\frac{2}{w}\alpha ^3,\quad \alpha = \frac{w}{2}\frac{1}{1-k}\frac{1}{\beta } \end{aligned}$$

and give

$$\begin{aligned} \alpha= & {} \sigma _1^{1*}=\sqrt{w}\left( \frac{k}{4(1-k)^3}\right) ^{\frac{1}{4}} \end{aligned}$$
(9)
$$\begin{aligned} \beta= & {} \sigma _1^{2*}=\sqrt{w}\frac{1}{(4k(1-k))^{\frac{1}{4}}} \end{aligned}$$
(10)
$$\begin{aligned} \gamma= & {} \sigma _1^{3*}=\sqrt{w}\left[ \frac{k}{1-k}-2\left( \frac{k}{1-k}\right) ^{\frac{1}{2}}+2\right] ^{\frac{1}{2}} \end{aligned}$$
(11)

The above equilibrium is the unique symmetric interior solution. To see this, suppose \(\frac{1-k}{k}\frac{\alpha }{\beta } \le 1\). Re-taking the FOCs gives \(\frac{\alpha }{\beta }=\sqrt{\frac{k}{1-k}}\), which implies \(k\ge \frac{1}{2}\), which is a contradiction.

1.2 Boundary equilibria

Since \(k, w > 0\), it follows that \(\alpha , \beta , \gamma > 0\). Thus, as long as the election has positive importance, no optimal \(\sigma \) will ever be on the 0 boundary. Since the ordering of the cutoffs is dependent on k, we have two cases.

1.2.1 Low levels of disagreement: \(k \in (0, \frac{1}{5}]\)

By Proposition 1, we know that \(\sigma _1^{1*}\le \sigma _1^{3*}\le \sigma _1^{2*}\). Thus, when \(k<\frac{1}{5}\), the equilibrium takes on one of four cases: (1) the interior solution; (2) only \(\sigma _1^{2*}\) is on the boundary; (3) only \(\sigma _1^{2*}\) and \(\sigma _1^{3*}\) are on the boundary; or (4) all three cutoffs are on the boundary. The previous subsection details the interior solutions.

Case 2: Taking \(\sigma _1^{2*} = 1\) and retaking FOCs for \(\sigma _1^{3*}\) and \(\sigma _1^{1*}\) gives boundary equilibrium of

$$\begin{aligned} {\sigma ^1_1}^*&= \left( \frac{kw}{2(1-k)^2}\right) ^{\frac{1}{3}}, \quad {\sigma _1^3}^* = \left[ \left( \frac{4wk^4}{(1-k)^2} \right) ^{\frac{1}{3}}-\left( \frac{16w^2k^2}{(1-k)}\right) ^{\frac{1}{3}} +2w\right] ^{\frac{1}{2}},\nonumber \\ {\sigma _1^2}^*&= 1 . \end{aligned}$$

The interval is:

$$\begin{aligned} \left[ \left( \frac{4wk^4}{(1-k)^2} \right) ^{\frac{1}{3}}-\left( \frac{16w^2k^2}{(1-k)}\right) ^{\frac{1}{3}} +2w\right] ^{\frac{1}{2}}<1,\quad \frac{1}{w} \le \frac{1}{(4k(1-k))^{\frac{1}{2}}}. \end{aligned}$$

Case 3: Taking both \(\sigma _1^{2*}\) and \(\sigma _1^{3*}\) on the boundary and retaking the FOCs yields

$$\begin{aligned} {\sigma ^1_1}^* = \left( \frac{kw}{2(1-k)^2}\right) ^{\frac{1}{3}}, \quad {\sigma _1^3}^* = 1, \quad {\sigma _1^2}^* = 1. \quad \end{aligned}$$

The interval is:

$$\begin{aligned} \frac{k}{2(1-k)^2} < \frac{1}{w}, 1 \le \left[ \left( \frac{4wk^4}{(1-k)^2} \right) ^{\frac{1}{3}}-\left( \frac{16w^2k^2}{(1-k)}\right) ^{\frac{1}{3}} +2w\right] ^{\frac{1}{2}}. \end{aligned}$$

Case 4: All three cutoffs are on the boundary when \(\sigma _1^{1*}\) from Case 3 reaches 1. The interval is

$$\begin{aligned} \frac{1}{w} \le \frac{k}{2(1-k)^2}. \end{aligned}$$

1.2.2 High-levels of disagreement: \(k \in (\frac{1}{5}, \frac{1}{2})\)

By Property 1, the cutoffs are now ordered \(\sigma _1^{1*} \le \sigma _1^{2*} \le \sigma _1^{3*}\). Setting \({\sigma _1^3}^* = 1\) and retaking the FOCs for \(\sigma _1^2\) and \(\sigma _1^1\) yields that

$$\begin{aligned} {\sigma ^1_1}^* =\frac{w^{\frac{1}{2}}k^{\frac{1}{4}}}{(4(1-k)^3)^\frac{1}{4}}, \quad {\sigma _1^2}^* =\frac{w^{\frac{1}{2}}}{(4k(1-k))^{\frac{1}{4}}}, \quad {\sigma _1^3}^* = 1. \end{aligned}$$

The interval is:

$$\begin{aligned} \frac{1}{(4k(1-k))^{\frac{1}{2}}} < \frac{1}{w} \le \left[ \frac{k}{1-k}-2\left( \frac{k}{1-k}\right) ^{\frac{1}{2}} +2\right] . \end{aligned}$$

When both the largest and second largest cutoffs are at the boundary, we get that

$$\begin{aligned} {\sigma ^1_1}^* = \left( \frac{kw}{2(1-k)^2}\right) ^{\frac{1}{3}},\quad {\sigma _1^2}^* = 1,\quad {\sigma _1^3}^* = 1. \end{aligned}$$

The interval is:

$$\begin{aligned} \frac{k}{2(1-k)^2} < \frac{1}{w} \le \frac{1}{(4k(1-k))^{\frac{1}{2}}}. \end{aligned}$$

All three cutoffs are on the boundary when \(\sigma _1^1\) from the previous case reaches 1, which occurs when

$$\begin{aligned} \frac{1}{w} \le \frac{k}{2(1-k)^2}. \end{aligned}$$

Appendix B: Proofs of properties

1.1 Proposition 1

We first show that cutoff rules are decreasing in k for the minority and battleground districts, and increasing in k for the majority district. The derivative of the interior solutions from Eqs. 9, 10, and 11 are:

$$\begin{aligned} \frac{\partial {\sigma _1^1}^*}{\partial k}= & {} \frac{\sqrt{2w}}{2}\left( \frac{ \frac{1}{4} (1-k)^{\frac{3}{4}} k^{-\frac{3}{4}} + k^\frac{1}{4} \frac{3}{4} (1-k)^ {-\frac{1}{4}} }{(1-k)^\frac{3}{2}} \right) \\ \frac{\partial {\sigma _1^2}^*}{\partial k}= & {} -\sqrt{w} \frac{ \frac{1}{4}(4-8k) }{ (4k(1-k))^\frac{5}{4}} \\ \frac{\partial {\sigma _1^3}^*}{\partial k}= & {} \frac{\sqrt{w}}{(1-k)^2\sqrt{k}} \times \frac{\sqrt{k}-\sqrt{1-k}}{2 \left( \frac{k}{1-k}-2 \left( \frac{k}{1-k} \right) ^\frac{1}{2}+2 \right) ^\frac{1}{2}}. \end{aligned}$$

The partial derivative for the majority district, \(\frac{\partial {\sigma _1^1}^*}{\partial k}\), is clearly positive, implying that the cutoff rule in the majority district is increasing in k. Since \(k<\frac{1}{2}\), \(\frac{\partial {\sigma _1^2}^*}{\partial k}\) is negative, implying the cutoff rule in the minority district is decreasing in k. Since \(\sqrt{k}-\sqrt{1-k}<0\) for all \(k<\frac{1}{2}\), it follows that the cutoff rule is decreasing for the battleground district.

We next show that the cutoff rule in the majority district is always lower. First note that all of the cutoff rules converge to \(\sqrt{w}\) if \(k=\frac{1}{2}\). Since the cutoff rule is increasing in k for the majority district, this must be the maximum cutoff for that district. Since the cutoff rules are decreasing in the minority and battleground district, this is the minimum cutoff for those districts. Thus, the majority district always has the lowest cutoff.

Lastly, we show that for high levels of disagreement (\(k>\frac{1}{5}\)), the cutoff is higher in the battleground district than in the minority district, and that for low levels of disagreement (\(k<\frac{1}{5}\)), the cutoff rule is higher in the minority district. With much algebra, it can be shown that the majority district has a higher cutoff rule if and only if \(20k^3-24k^2+9k-1\) is positive. This polynomial is negative for k in \((0,\frac{1}{5})\) and positive for k in \((\frac{1}{5},\frac{1}{2})\).

1.2 Proposition 2

The Proposition states \(\frac{1}{2}\frac{1}{2}\sigma _1^{3*}> \frac{1}{2}(1-k)\sigma _1^{1*} > \frac{1}{2}k\sigma _1^{2*}.\) First we show that \(\frac{1}{2}\sigma _1^{3*}>\frac{1}{2}w^{\frac{1}{2}}>(1-k)\sigma _1^{1*}\). Some algebra will show that \(\frac{1}{2}\sigma _1^{3*}>\frac{1}{2}w^{\frac{1}{2}}\) if and only if \(4k^2-4k+1\) is positive, which is true for all \(k \in (0,\frac{1}{2})\) since the polynomial has a global minimum of 0 at \(k=\frac{1}{2}\).

Next, \(\frac{1}{2}w^{\frac{1}{2}}>(1-k)\sigma _1^{1*} \Longleftrightarrow \frac{1}{4} > (1-k)k\). This inequality is assured by \(k \in (0,\frac{1}{2})\). Thus we have that \(\frac{1}{2}\frac{1}{2}\sigma _1^{3*} > \frac{1}{2}(1-k)\sigma _1^{1*}\).

Next,

$$\begin{aligned} (1-k)\sigma _1^{1*}> & {} k\sigma _1^{2*}\\\Longleftrightarrow & {} \frac{k^{\frac{1}{4}}(1-k)}{(1-k)^{\frac{3}{4}}}> \frac{k}{((1-k)k)^{\frac{1}{4}}}. \\\Longleftrightarrow & {} k(1-2k)> 0, \end{aligned}$$

which holds since \(k \in (0, \frac{1}{2})\), and gives \(\frac{1}{2}(1-k)\sigma _1^{1*} > \frac{1}{2}k\sigma _1^{2*}\), which finishes the proof of the first part of the Proposition.

The proof of Proposition 1 showed that \(\frac{d\sigma _1^{3*}}{dk}>0\), so it follows that a party’s expected turnout \(\frac{1}{2}\frac{1}{2}\frac{d\sigma _1^{3*}}{dk}>0\) also.

Expected turnout for the majority party is

$$\begin{aligned} \frac{1}{2}(1-k)\sigma _1^{1*} = \frac{1}{2}\left( \frac{w}{2}\right) ^{\frac{1}{2}}\big ((1-k)k)^{\frac{1}{4}}. \end{aligned}$$

Its derivative is

$$\begin{aligned} \frac{1}{8}\big (\frac{w}{2}\big )^{\frac{1}{2}}\frac{1-2k}{\left( k-k^2\right) ^{\frac{3}{4}}}>0 \end{aligned}$$

since \(k \in (0, \frac{1}{2})\). Thus expected turnout for a party’s majority district is increasing in k.

Expected total turnout in a party’s minority district is

$$\begin{aligned} \frac{1}{2}k\sigma _1^{2*} = \frac{1}{2}\left( \frac{w}{2}\right) ^{\frac{1}{2}}\frac{k^{\frac{3}{4}}}{(1-k)^{\frac{1}{4}}}. \end{aligned}$$

Its derivative is

$$\begin{aligned} \frac{1}{2}\left( \frac{w}{2}\right) ^{\frac{1}{2}}\frac{\frac{3}{4}\bigg (\frac{1-k)}{k}\bigg )^{\frac{1}{4}}+\frac{1}{4}\bigg (\frac{k}{1-k}\bigg )^{\frac{3}{4}}}{(1-k)^{\frac{1}{2}}} > 0, \end{aligned}$$

and thus expected turnout for the minority party is increasing in k.

1.3 Proposition 3

Expected total turnout for each party is increasing in k for the majority and minority in the partisan districts. Thus, the total expected turnout in a partisan district is also increasing in k. Both parties’ expected turnout is decreasing in k for the battleground district, so expected total turnout is also decreasing in k.

To see that the expected total turnout in the partisan districts converges to that of the battleground district, consider:

$$\begin{aligned} \lim _{k\rightarrow \frac{1}{2}} \frac{1}{2}\frac{1}{2}\sigma _1^{3*} + \frac{1}{2}\frac{1}{2}\sigma _2^{3*} = \lim _{k\rightarrow \frac{1}{2}} \frac{1}{2}\sqrt{w}\Bigg (\frac{k}{1-k} - 2\bigg (\frac{k}{1-k}\bigg )^{\frac{1}{2}}+2\Bigg )^{\frac{1}{2}} = \frac{1}{2}\sqrt{w} \end{aligned}$$

and

$$\begin{aligned} \lim _{k \rightarrow \frac{1}{2}} \frac{1}{2}(1-k)\sigma _1^{1*} + \frac{1}{2}k\sigma _2^{1*}= & {} \lim _{k\rightarrow \frac{1}{2}} \frac{1}{2}(1-k)\sqrt{w}\frac{k^{\frac{1}{4}}}{(4(1-k)^3)^{\frac{1}{4}}} \nonumber \\&+ \frac{1}{2}k\sqrt{w}\frac{1}{(4(k(1-k))^{\frac{1}{4}}} \nonumber \\= & {} \frac{1}{4}\sqrt{w}+\frac{1}{4}\sqrt{w}= \frac{1}{2}\sqrt{w}. \end{aligned}$$

1.4 Proposition 4

The Proposition states that as k approaches \(\frac{1}{2}\), the probability of winning a party’s majority district decreases, the probability of the party winning its minority district increases, and the probability a party wins the battleground district stays constant at \(\frac{1}{2}\).

To see this, consider the probability of party 1 winning its majority district:

$$\begin{aligned} F\Bigg (\frac{(1-k)\sigma _1^{1*}}{k\sigma _2^{1*}}\Bigg ) = 1 - \frac{k\sigma _2^{1*}}{2(1-k)\sigma _1^{1*}} = 1 - \frac{1}{2}\Bigg (\frac{k}{1-k}\Bigg )^{\frac{1}{2}}. \end{aligned}$$

Notice that this quantity approaches \(\frac{1}{2}\) as \(k \rightarrow \frac{1}{2}\). Taking the derivative with respect to k gives

$$\begin{aligned} \frac{\partial F\left( \frac{(1-k)\sigma _1^{1*}}{k\sigma _2^{1*}}\right) }{\partial k} = -\frac{1}{4}\frac{1}{k^{\frac{1}{2}}{(1-k)^{\frac{3}{2}}}}, \end{aligned}$$

which is negative for \(k \in (1, \frac{1}{2})\). Thus the probability that a party wins their majority district is decreasing in k.

The probability of party 1 winning district 2 is

$$\begin{aligned} F\left( \frac{(1-k)\sigma _2^{2*}}{k\sigma _1^{2*}}\right) = \frac{k\sigma _1^{2*}}{2(1-k)\sigma _2^{2*}} = \frac{1}{2}\Bigg (\frac{k}{1-k}\Bigg )^{\frac{1}{2}}. \end{aligned}$$

This quantity is increasing in k by the same argument that the previous result is decreasing in k.

Finally, the probability that candidate 1 wins the battleground district is

$$\begin{aligned} F\left( \frac{\frac{1}{2}\sigma _1^{3*}}{\frac{1}{2}\sigma _2^{3*}}\right) = F(1) = \frac{1}{2}. \end{aligned}$$

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Jorgenson, A., Saavedra, M. The Electoral College, battleground states, and rule-utilitarian voting. Soc Choice Welf 51, 577–593 (2018). https://doi.org/10.1007/s00355-018-1128-2

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s00355-018-1128-2