Skip to main content
Log in

Positionalist voting rules: a general definition and axiomatic characterizations

  • Original Paper
  • Published:
Social Choice and Welfare Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The paper proposes a general definition of positionalist voting rules. Unlike the commonly-employed scoring rules, our notion of positionalism allows for non-linear criteria to be included in the requisite class. We define a voting rule as positionalist if, for any profile of strict individual orderings, any two alternatives are compared collectively solely on the basis of their positional scores according to the individual rankings. In contrast to the class of scoring rules, however, we do not restrict attention to linear aggregation procedures. Two plausible unanimity properties are examined in the context of our new class of positionalist rules and, moreover, we characterize the lexicographic extensions that refine the plurality rule and its inverse counterpart.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

References

  • Arrow KJ (1951) Social choice and individual values, 1st edn. Wiley, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Arrow KJ (1963) Social choice and individual values, 2nd edn. Notes on the theory of social choice, Wiley, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Arrow KJ (2012) Social choice and individual values, 3rd edn. “Foreword to the third edition” by Eric Maskin. Yale University Press, New Haven

  • Arrow KJ, Sen AK, Suzumura K (eds) (2002) Handbook of social choice and welfare, vol 1. Elsevier, Amsterdam

    Google Scholar 

  • Atkinson AB (1970) On the measurement of inequality. J Econ Theory 2:244–263

    Google Scholar 

  • Baharad E, Nitzan S (2002) Ameliorating majority decisiveness through expression of preference intensity. Am Polit Sci Rev 96:745–754

    Google Scholar 

  • Baharad E, Nitzan S (2016) Is majority consistency possible? Soc Choice Welf 46:287–299

    Google Scholar 

  • Bentham J (1776) A fragment on government. T. Payne, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Black D (1958) The theory of committees and elections. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (Reprinted in McLean, McMillan and Monroe)

    Google Scholar 

  • Blau JH (1976) Neutrality, monotonicity, and the right of veto: a comment. Econometrica 44:603

    Google Scholar 

  • Borda J-C (1781) Mémoire sur les élections au scrutin, Mémoires de l’Académie Royale des Sciences année 1781, pp 657–665 (Translated and reprinted in McLean and Urken (1995, Chapter 5))

  • Bossert W, Suzumura K (2016) The greatest unhappiness of the least number. Soc Choice Welf 47:187–205 (Republished in a Special Issue in Honor of John Roemer (2017), Soc Choice Welf 49:637–655)

    Google Scholar 

  • Bossert W, Suzumura K (2019) Vote budgets and Dodgson’s method of marks. Oxford Economic Papers (forthcoming)

  • Bouyssou D (1992) Ranking methods based on valued preference relations: a characterization of the net flow method. Eur J Oper Res 60:61–67

    Google Scholar 

  • Brams SJ (1975) Game theory and politics. Free Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Brams SJ, Fishburn PC (1978) Approval voting. Am Polit Sci Rev 72:831–847

    Google Scholar 

  • Brams SJ, Fishburn PC (1983) Approval voting. Birkhäuser, Boston

    Google Scholar 

  • Brams SJ, Fishburn PC (2002) Voting procedures. In: Arrow, Sen and Suzumura, pp 173–236

  • Chebotarev PYu, Shamis E (1998) Characterizations of scoring methods for preference aggregation. Ann Oper Res 80:299–332

    Google Scholar 

  • Ching S (1996) A simple characterization of plurality rule. J Econ Theory 71:298–302

    Google Scholar 

  • de Condorcet MJAN (1785) Essai sur l’application de l’analyse à la probabilité des décisions rendues à la pluralité des voix. Imprimerie Royale, Paris (Translated and reprinted in part in McLean and Urken (1995, Chapter 6))

  • d’Aspremont C, Gevers L (1977) Equity and the informational basis of collective choice. Rev Econ Stud 44:199–209

    Google Scholar 

  • Dodgson CL (1873) A discussion of the various methods of procedure in conducting elections, E.B. Gardner, E. Pickard Hall and J.H. Stacy. Printers to the University, Oxford (Reprinted in McLean and Urken (1995, Chapter 12))

  • Dodgson CL (1876) A method of taking votes on more than two issues. Clarendon Press, Oxford (Reprinted in McLean and Urken (1995, Chapter 12))

    Google Scholar 

  • Fine B, Fine K (1974a) Social choice and individual ranking I. Rev Econ Stud 41:302–322

    Google Scholar 

  • Fine B, Fine K (1974b) Social choice and individual ranking II. Rev Econ Stud 41:459–475

    Google Scholar 

  • Fishburn PC (1973a) Summation social choice functions. Econometrica 41:1183–1196

    Google Scholar 

  • Fishburn PC (1973b) The theory of social choice. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Google Scholar 

  • Fishburn PC (1975) Axioms for lexicographic preferences. Rev Econ Stud 42:415–419

    Google Scholar 

  • Gärdenfors P (1973) Positionalist voting functions. Theory Decis 4:1–24

    Google Scholar 

  • Guha AS (1972) Neutrality, monotonicity, and the right of veto. Econometrica 40:821–826

    Google Scholar 

  • Hammond PJ (1976) Equity, Arrow’s conditions, and Rawls’ difference principle. Econometrica 44:793–804

    Google Scholar 

  • Hammond PJ (1979) Equity in two person situations: some consequences. Econometrica 47:1127–1135

    Google Scholar 

  • Hansson B, Sahlquist H (1976) A proof technique for social choice with variable electorate. J Econ Theory 13:193–200

    Google Scholar 

  • Henriet D (1985) The Copeland choice function: an axiomatic characterization. Soc Choice Welf 2:49–63

    Google Scholar 

  • Howard N (1971) Paradoxes of rationality: theory of metagames and political behavior. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Kraft CH, Pratt JW, Seidenberg A (1959) Intuitive probability on finite sets. Ann Math Stat 30:408–419

    Google Scholar 

  • Maskin E (1978) A theorem on utilitarianism. Rev Econ Stud 45:93–96

    Google Scholar 

  • May KO (1952) A set of independent necessary and sufficient conditions for simple majority decision. Econometrica 20:680–684

    Google Scholar 

  • McLean I, Urken AB (eds) (1995) Classics of social choice. University of Michigan Press, Ann Arbor

    Google Scholar 

  • McLean I, McMillan A, Monroe BL (eds) (1998) The theory of committees and elections by Duncan Black and Committee Decisions with complementary valuation by Duncan Black and R.A. Newing, with a Foreword by Ronald H. Coase, Revised second editions. Kluwer Academic Publishers, Boston

  • Mitchell WC (1937) The backward art of spending money and other essays. McGraw-Hill, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Nitzan S, Rubinstein A (1981) A further characterization of Borda ranking method. Public Choice 36:153–158

    Google Scholar 

  • Pattanaik PK (2002) Positionalist rules of collective decision-making. In: Arrow, Sen and Suzumura, pp 361–394

  • Richelson JT (1978) A characterization result for the plurality rule. J Econ Theory 19:548–550

    Google Scholar 

  • Roberts KWS (1980) Possibility theorems with interpersonally comparable welfare levels. Rev Econ Stud 47:409–420

    Google Scholar 

  • Sen AK (1970) Collective choice and social welfare, original ed. Holden-Day, San Francisco

  • Sen AK (2017) Collective choice and social welfare, expanded ed. Penguin Random House, London

  • Sen AK (1977) On weights and measures: informational constraints in social welfare analysis. Econometrica 45:1539–1572

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith JH (1973) Aggregation of preferences with variable electorate. Econometrica 41:1027–1041

    Google Scholar 

  • Young HP (1974) An axiomatization of Borda’s rule. J Econ Theory 9:43–52

    Google Scholar 

  • Young HP (1975) Social choice scoring functions. SIAM J Appl Math 28:824–838

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Walter Bossert.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

We thank Salvador Barberà, Steven Brams, Amartya Sen, Peyton Young and two referees for comments and suggestions. Financial support from the Fonds de Recherche sur la Société et la Culture of Québec and from a Grant-in-Aid for Scientific Research from the Ministry of Education, Culture, Sports, Science and Technology of Japan for the Project on The Pursuit of Normative Economics with Extended Informational Bases, and the Reexamination of Its Doctrinal History (Grant Number 16H03599) is gratefully acknowledged.

Appendix: Scoring rules and representable rules

Appendix: Scoring rules and representable rules

In this Appendix, we prove that all scoring rules are representable in the sense of Gärdenfors (1973). Moreover, although the reverse implication is not valid in general, the two notions are equivalent in the presence of neutrality. We first provide the formal definition of representability.

Definition 11

A voting rule F is representable if and only if there exists a function \(g :\mathcal{P} \times \mathbf{A} \rightarrow \mathbb {R}\) such that, for all \(\mathbf{R} \in \mathcal{P}^N\) and for all \(a,b \in \mathbf{A}\),

$$\begin{aligned} a F(\mathbf{R}) b \; \Leftrightarrow \; \sum _{i=1}^N g(R_i,a) \ge \sum _{i=1}^N g(R_i,b). \end{aligned}$$

The proof of the result under neutrality employs Theorem 5.1 of Gärdenfors (1973, pp. 13–14), and we require the following definition for this purpose.

Two strict preference orderings \(R,R' \in \mathcal{P}\)have the same frame if there exists a one-to-one mapping \(\phi :\mathbf{A} \rightarrow \mathbf{A}\) such that aRb if and only if \(\phi (a)R'\phi (b)\) for all \(a,b \in \mathbf{A}\); see Gärdenfors (1973, p. 12) for this definition applied to the set of all (not necessarily strict) orderings. Note that any two strict preference orderings have the same frame. This is the case because, for any two \(R,R' \in \mathcal{P}\), we can define \(\phi \) to be the one-to-one mapping that assigns, to each alternative \(a \in \mathbf{A}\), the unique alternative \(b \in \mathbf{A}\) such that the rank of a in R is the same as the rank of b in \(R'\).

Theorem 9

  1. (a)

    A scoring rule must be representable. The reverse implication is not valid.

  2. (b)

    A neutral and representable voting rule must be a scoring rule.

Proof

(a) Suppose that F is a scoring rule. Thus, there exists an A-tuple of weights \(w = (w_1,\ldots ,w_A) \in \mathbb {R}^A\) such that, for all \(\mathbf{R} \in \mathcal{P}^N\) and for all \(a,b \in \mathbf{A}\),

$$\begin{aligned} a F(\mathbf{R}) b \; \Leftrightarrow \; \sum _{j=1}^A w_j \cdot s_j(\mathbf{R},a) \ge \sum _{j=1}^A w_j \cdot s_j(\mathbf{R},b). \end{aligned}$$
(26)

Recall that \(s_j(\mathbf{R},a)\) is the number of individuals i who place a in position j according to their ordering \(R_i\). That is, for each of these individuals, \(p(R_i,a)\) is equal to j. It follows that the term

$$\begin{aligned} w_j \cdot s_j(\mathbf{R},a) \end{aligned}$$

is equal to the sum

$$\begin{aligned} \sum _{i \in \mathbf{N} \mid p(R_i,a) = j} w_j \end{aligned}$$

for each possible position \(j \in \{1,\ldots ,A\}\) and, therefore, the sum

$$\begin{aligned} \sum _{j=1}^A w_j \cdot s_j(\mathbf{R},a) \end{aligned}$$

is equal to the sum

$$\begin{aligned} \sum _{j=1}^A \sum _{i \in \mathbf{N} \mid p(R_i,a) = j} w_j. \end{aligned}$$

Equivalently, this sum can be expressed as

$$\begin{aligned} \sum _{i=1}^N w_{p(R_i,a)} \end{aligned}$$

and, defining

$$\begin{aligned} g(R_i,a) = w_{p(R_i,a)} \end{aligned}$$

for all \(i \in \mathbf{N}\), for all \(R_i \in \mathcal{P}\) and for all \(a \in \mathbf{A}\), we can use (26) to obtain

$$\begin{aligned} a F(\mathbf{R}) b\Leftrightarrow & {} \sum _{j=1}^A w_j \cdot s_j(\mathbf{R},a) \ge \sum _{j=1}^A w_j \cdot s_j(\mathbf{R},b) \\\Leftrightarrow & {} \sum _{i=1}^N g(R_i,a) \ge \sum _{i=1}^N g(R_i,b) \end{aligned}$$

for all \(\mathbf{R} \in \mathcal{P}^N\) and for all \(a,b \in \mathbf{A}\). Thus, F is representable.

That the reverse implication is not true in general is established by means of the following example. Let \(a^0,b^0 \in \mathbf{A}\) be two distinct fixed alternatives. Furthermore, let \(R^0 \in \mathcal{P}\) be a fixed strict preference ordering such that \(a^0 R^0 b^0 R^0 c\) for all \(c \in \mathbf{A} {\setminus } \{a^0,b^0\}\). Define the function \(g :\mathcal{P} \times \mathbf{A} \rightarrow \mathbb {R}\) by

$$\begin{aligned} g(R,a) = A - p(R,a) \end{aligned}$$

for all \(R \in \mathcal{P} {\setminus } \{R^0\}\) and for all \(a \in \mathbf{A}\);

$$\begin{aligned} g(R^0,a) = A - p(R^0,a) \end{aligned}$$

for all \(a \in \mathbf{A} {\setminus } \{a^0\}\); and

$$\begin{aligned} g(R^0,a^0) = 2 \cdot (A-1). \end{aligned}$$

Thus, the values of g correspond to the Borda numbers with the exception of \(g(R^0,a^0)\), which assigns twice the Borda number to the greatest element \(a^0\) in \(\mathbf{A}\) according to \(R^0\). Define F by letting, for all \(\mathbf{R} \in \mathcal{P}^N\) and for all \(a,b \in \mathbf{A}\),

$$\begin{aligned} a F(\mathbf{R}) b \; \Leftrightarrow \; \sum _{i=1}^N g(R_i,a) \ge \sum _{i=1}^N g(R_i,b). \end{aligned}$$

It is immediate that F is representable. To prove that F is not a scoring rule, suppose that \(\mathbf{A} = \{a^0,b^0,c\}\) and \(\mathbf{N} = \{1,2\}\). Let \(b^0 R a^0 R c\) and consider the profile \(\mathbf{R} = (R^0,R) \in \mathcal{P}^2\). It follows that

$$\begin{aligned} g(R^0,a^0) + g(R,a^0) = 4 + 1 = 5 > 3 = 1 + 2 = g(R^0,b^0) + g(R,b^0) \end{aligned}$$

and hence \(a^0 P_{(R^0,R)} b^0\). But we also have

$$\begin{aligned} \mathbf{s}(\mathbf{R},a^0) = (1,1,0) = \mathbf{s}(\mathbf{R},b^0) \end{aligned}$$

and, therefore, any scoring rule has to declare \(a^0\) and \(b^0\) indifferent. Thus, F cannot be a scoring rule.

(b) Suppose that F is a neutral and representable voting rule. Thus, there exists a function \(g :\mathcal{P} \times \mathbf{A} \rightarrow \mathbb {R}\) such that, for all \(\mathbf{R} \in \mathcal{P}^N\) and for all \(a,b \in \mathbf{A}\),

$$\begin{aligned} a F(\mathbf{R}) b \; \Leftrightarrow \; \sum _{i=1}^N g(R_i,a) \ge \sum _{i=1}^N g(R_i,b). \end{aligned}$$

By Theorem 5.1 of Gärdenfors (1973, pp. 13–14), neutrality is equivalent to the property that, for any two preference orderings R and \(R'\) that have the same frame (with the mapping \(\phi \)), we must have

$$\begin{aligned} g(R,a) - g(R,b) = g(R',\phi (a)) - g(R',\phi (b)) \end{aligned}$$
(27)

for all \(a,b \in \mathbf{A}\). As mentioned in the paragraph preceding the theorem statement, any two strict preference orderings have the same frame. Now fix a strict preference ordering \(R^0 \in \mathcal{P}\). It follows that, for any profile \(\mathbf{R} \in \mathcal{P}^N\) and for any two alternatives \(a,b \in \mathbf{A}\), the relative ranking of a and b according to \(F(\mathbf{R})\) can be determined by means of the given ordering \(R^0\). To see that this is indeed the case, let \(\mathbf{R} \in \mathcal{P}^N\) and, for all \(i \in \mathbf{N}\), define the function \(\phi _i\) by letting

$$\begin{aligned} \phi _i(a) = c \; \Leftrightarrow \; p(R_i,a) = p(R^0,c) \end{aligned}$$

for all \(a \in \mathbf{A}\). To simplify the exposition, suppose that, without loss of generality, the alternatives in \(\mathbf{A}\) are numbered so that \(a_1 R^0 \cdots R^0 a_A\) and define, for all \(j \in \{1,\ldots ,A\}\),

$$\begin{aligned} w_j = g(R^0,a_j). \end{aligned}$$
(28)

Theorem 5.1 of Gärdenfors (1973) allows us to invoke (27) to conclude that

$$\begin{aligned} a F(\mathbf{R}) b \; \Leftrightarrow \; \sum _{i=1}^N g(R^0,\phi _i(a)) \ge \sum _{i=1}^N g(R^0,\phi _i(b)) \end{aligned}$$

for all \(a,b \in \mathbf{A}\) and, substituting (28), it follows that

$$\begin{aligned} a F(\mathbf{R}) b \; \Leftrightarrow \; \sum _{j=1}^A w_j \cdot s_j(\mathbf{R},a) \ge \sum _{j=1}^A w_j \cdot s_j(\mathbf{R},b) \end{aligned}$$

for all \(a,b \in \mathbf{A}\) so that F is a scoring rule. \(\square \)

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Bossert, W., Suzumura, K. Positionalist voting rules: a general definition and axiomatic characterizations. Soc Choice Welf 55, 85–116 (2020). https://doi.org/10.1007/s00355-019-01232-3

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s00355-019-01232-3

Navigation