Abstract
A hyper-preference is a weak order over all linear orders defined over a finite set A of alternatives. An extension rule associates with each linear order p over A a hyper-preference. The well-known Kemeny extension rule ranks all linear orders over A according to their Kemeny distance to p. More generally, an extension rule is metrizable iff it extends p to a hyper-preference consistent with a distance criterion. We characterize the class of metrizable extension rules by means of two properties, namely self-consistency and acyclicity across orders. Moreover, we provide a characterization of neutral and metrizable extension rules, based on a simpler formulation of acyclicity across orders. Furthermore, we establish the logical incompatibility between neutrality, metrizability and strictness. However, we show that these three conditions are pairwise logically compatible.
Similar content being viewed by others
Notes
There are also rank-weighted versions of the Kemeny metric (giving a semi-metric) considered in García-Lapresta and Pérez-Román (2011) (see also Can (2014) and Can and Storcken (2015) for a generalization). In fact, both in the statistics literature and in the growing field of studying consensus, one can find beyond the Kemeny distance many measures of concordance or discordance between two linear or weak orders. In particular, different rank correlation indices, such as Spearman’s rho (Spearman 1904), Kendall’s tau (Kendall 1962) and Gini’s cograduation index (Gini 1954) have been considered for assigning grades of agreement between two rankings. These indices have been extended to the analysis of concordance within a set of rankings (see Eckert and Klamler (2011), García-Lapresta and Pérez-Román (2011), Alcalde-Unzu and Vorsatz (2011) and Borroni and Zenga (2007)). One can also note the alternative (semi-)metrics considered in Blin (1976), Cook and Seiford (1978), Armstrong et al. (1982), Cook and Kress (1985), and Monjardet (1997, 1998).
Let \(A=\{a,b,c,d\}\). Consider, without loss of generality, the bijection \( f(\{a,b\})=1,\)\(f(\{b,c\})=2,f(\{b,d\})=3,f(\{c,d\})=4,f(\{a,c\})=5\) and \( f(\{a,d\})=6\). Hence \(w_{ab}^{f}=\frac{1}{2}\), \(w_{bc}^{f}=\frac{1}{4}\), \( w_{bd}^{f}=\frac{1}{8}\), \(w_{cd}^{f}=\frac{1}{16}\), \(w_{ac}^{f}=\frac{1}{32}\) , and \(w_{ad}^{f}=\frac{1}{64}\). For \(p=abcd\), \(q=bacd\), and \(q^{\prime }=adcb\), we have q\(\varepsilon _{K}^{*}(p)\)\(q^{\prime }\) for the Kemeny rule and \(q^{\prime }\varepsilon _{d_{w}}^{*}(p)\)\(q^{\prime }\) for the weigthed-pair rule.
References
Alcalde-Unzu J, Vorsatz M (2011) Measuring consensus: concepts, comparisons, and properties. In: Herrera-Viedma E, García-Lapresta JL, Kacprzyk J, Nurmi H, Fedrizzi M, Zadrozny S (eds) Consensual processes. Springer, Berlin, pp 195–211
Armstrong RD, Cook WD, Seiford L (1982) Priority ranking and consensus formation: the case of ties. Manag Sci 28(6):638–645
Arrow KJ (1963) Social choice and individual values, 2nd edn. Wiley, New York
Athanasoglou S (2016) Strategyproof and efficient preference aggregation with Kemeny-based criteria. Games Econ Behav 95:156–167
Barberà S, Bossert W, Pattanaik P (2004) Ranking sets of objects. In: Barberà S., Hammond PJ, Seidl C (eds) Handbook of utility theory, pp 893-977
Barthélémy JP (1979) Caractérisations axiomatiques de la distance de la différence symétrique entre des relations binaires. Mathématiques et Sciences Humaines 67:85–113
Blin JM (1976) A linear assignment formulation of the multiattribute decision problem. Review Automatique, Informatique et Recherche Opé rationnelle 10(6):21–23
Bogart KP (1973) Preference structures I: distances between transitive preference relations. J. Math. Soc. 3:49–67
Borroni CG, Zenga M (2007) A test of concordance based on Gini’s mean difference. Stat Methods Appl 16:289–308
Bossert W, Storcken T (1992) Strategy-proofness of social welfare functions: the use of the Kemeny distance between preference orderings. Soc Choice Welf 9:345–360
Bossert W, Sprumont Y (2014) Strategy-proof preference aggregation. Games Econ Behav 85:109–126
Can B (2014) Weighted distances between preferences. J Math Econ 51:109–115
Can B, Storcken T (2013) A re-characterization of the Kemeny distance. Research Memorandum 009, Maastricht University, Graduate School of Business and Economics (GSBE)
Can B, Storcken T (2015) Comparing orders, rankings, queues, tournaments and lists. Research Memorandum 020, Maastricht University, Graduate School of Business and Economics (GSBE)
Cook WD, Kress M (1985) Ordinal ranking with intensity of preference. Manag Sci 31(1):26–32
Cook WD, Seiford LM (1978) Priority ranking and consensus formation. Manag Sci 24:1721–1732
Doğan O, Lainé J (2016) Strategic manipulation of social welfare functions via strict preference extensions. Mimeo, 5th World Congress of the Game Theory Society, Maastricht
Eckert D, Klamler C (2011) Distance-based aggregation theory. In: Herrera-Viedma E, García-Lapresta JL, Kacprzyk J, Nurmi H, Fedrizzi M, Zadrozny S (eds) Consensual processes. Springer, Berlin, pp 3–22
García-Lapresta JL, Pérez-Román D (2011) Measuring consensus in weak orders. In: Herrera-Viedma E, Garc ía-Lapresta JL, Kacprzyk J, Nurmi H, Fedrizzi M, Zadrozny S (eds) Consensual processes. Springer, Berlin, pp 213–234
Gini C (1954) Corso di Statistica. Veschi, Rome
Grandmont JM (1978) Intermediate preferences and the majority rule. Econometrica 46(2):317–330
Haeringer G, Hałaburda H (2016) Monotone strategyproofness. Games Econ Behav 98:68–77
Igersheim H (2007) Du paradoxe libéral-parétien à un concept de métaclassement des préférences. Recherches économiques de Louvain 73:173–192
Jeffrey RC (1974) Preferences among preferences. J Philos 13:377–391
Kemeny JG (1959) Mathematics without numbers. Daedalus 88:577–591
Kemeny JG, Snell LJ (1962) Preference ranking: an axiomatic approach. Mathematical models in the social sciences. Ginn, Boston, pp 9–32
Kendall MG (1962) Rank correlation methods. Griffin, London
Lainé J, Ozkes AI, Sanver MR (2016) Hyper-stable social welfare functions. Soc Choice Welf 46:157–182
Maskin E (1999) Nash equilibrium and welfare optimality. Rev Econ Stud 66:23–38
Meskanen T, Nurmi H (2006) Distance from consensus: a theme and variations. In: Simeone Pukelsheim F (eds) Mathematics and democracy: recent advances in voting systems and collective choice. Studies in choice and welfare, Springer, pp 117–132
Monjardet B (1997) Concordance between two linear orders: Kendall and Spearman coefficients revisited. J Classif 14(2):269–295
Monjardet B (1998) On the comparison of the Spearman and kendall metrics between linear orders. Discr Math 192:281–292
Priddat BP (2014) Morals: restrictions, metapreferences: adjusting an economics of morality. In: Communication and economic theory, Springer, New York, pp 39–63
Sato S (2015) Bounded response and the equivalence between nonmanipulability and independence of irrelevant alternatives. Soc Choice Welf 44(1):133–149
Sen AK (1974) Choice, orderings and morality. In: Körner S (ed) Practical reason, Oxford, pp 54–67
Sen AK (1970) The impossibility of a Paretian liberal. J Polit Econ 78(1):152–157
Spearman C (1904) The proof and measurement of association between two things. Am J Psychol 15:72–101
van der Veen RJ (1981) Meta-rankings and collective optimality. Soc Sci Inf 20(2):345–374
Author information
Authors and Affiliations
Corresponding author
Additional information
Publisher's Note
Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.
This project has been supported by the ANR-14-CE24-0007-01 (CoCoRICoCoDEC), the project IDEX ANR-10-IDEX-0001-02 PSL MIFID and the PICS CNRS exchange programme. We thank Goksel Asan, Onur Dogan and Dominik Peters for useful discussions.
Rights and permissions
About this article
Cite this article
Laffond, G., Lainé, J. & Sanver, M.R. Metrizable preferences over preferences. Soc Choice Welf 55, 177–191 (2020). https://doi.org/10.1007/s00355-019-01235-0
Received:
Accepted:
Published:
Issue Date:
DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s00355-019-01235-0